Results for ' Kant, and categorical imperative'

955 found
Order:
  1. Kant's categorical imperative, the value of respect, and the treatment of women.Marcus Schulzke - 2012 - Journal of Military Ethics 11 (1):26-41.
    This paper explores the relevance of Kant's categorical imperative to military ethics and the solution it suggests for improving the treatment of women in the military. The second formulation of the categorical imperative makes universal respect for humanity a moral requirement by asserting that one must always treat other people as means in themselves and never as merely means to an end. This principle is a promising guide for military ethics and can be reconciled with the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Kant's Categorical Imperative and Human Rights.S. Jhingran - 2006 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 33 (1):41.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  24
    Kant's Categorical Imperative and the Moral Worth of Increasing Profits.Karsten M. Thiel - 2013 - In Christopher Luetege (ed.), Handbook of the Philosophical Foundations of Business Ethics. Springer. pp. 339--354.
  4. How "Full" is Kant's Categorical Imperative?Kenneth Westphal - 1995 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik/Annual Review of Law and Ethics 3:465-509.
    Through a careful examination of two detailed investigations of Kant’s Categorical Imperative as a criterion for determining correct action I show that Hegel’s widely castigated critique of Kant’s CI has significant merit. Kant holds that moral imperatives are categorical because the obligations they express do not depend upon our contingent ends or desires and he holds that the CI is the supreme normative principle. However, his actual illustrations show that Kant repeatedly appeals to contingent ends and desires (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  89
    (1 other version)Autonomous Reboot: Kant, the categorical imperative, and contemporary challenges for machine ethicists.Jeffrey White - 2022 - AI and Society 37 (2):661-673.
    Ryan Tonkens has issued a seemingly impossible challenge, to articulate a comprehensive ethical framework within which artificial moral agents satisfy a Kantian inspired recipe—"rational" and "free"—while also satisfying perceived prerogatives of machine ethicists to facilitate the creation of AMAs that are perfectly and not merely reliably ethical. This series of papers meets this challenge by landscaping traditional moral theory in resolution of a comprehensive account of moral agency. The first paper established the challenge and set out autonomy in Aristotelian terms. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6.  32
    Rawls's original position and Kant's categorical imperative procedure.Jinghua Chen - 2024 - South African Journal of Philosophy 43 (1):42-56.
    The idea of the "original position" is one of the most famous concepts in contemporary political philosophy. Since the first publication of A Theory of Justice in 1971, the device of the original position has become a popular theoretical method in many political theorists' writings. Unfortunately, the true meaning of the original position is far from clear both in Rawls's and Rawlsians' accounts. This has caused a lot of misunderstanding and misuse of this concept in contemporary literature. This study attempts (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Means-ends rationality and categorical imperatives in empirical inquiry.Oliver Schulte - unknown
    Kant taught us that there are two kinds of norms: Categorical imperatives that one ought to follow regardless of one's personal aims and circumstances, and hypothetical imperatives that direct us to employ the means towards our chosen ends. Kant's distinction separates two approaches to normative epistemology. On the one hand, we have principles of "inductive rationality", typically supported by considerations such as intuitive plausibility, conformity with exemplary practice, and internal consistency. On the other hand, we may assess rules for (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  67
    Kant’s Categorical Imperative as a Criterion of the Rightness of Actions. [REVIEW]Gerhard Robbers - 1991 - Philosophy and History 24 (1-2):45-45.
  9. Insufficient Reason: An Interpretation and Critique of Kant's Categorical Imperative.Andrew Burkitt Johnson - 2001 - Dissertation, The University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill
    Kant's moral theory, along with Utilitarianism and Virtue Ethics, is one of the three leading moral theories in contemporary Western moral philosophy. I argue in this dissertation, however, that Kant's moral theory suffers from deeper flaws than its proponents have acknowledged---flaws that render it untenable. But a great deal of interpretative argument must be done before this critique can be compelling, since every critique rests on interpretative presuppositions that are liable to be questioned. Hence the dissertation also spends significant time (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Can Positive Duties be Derived from Kant’s Categorical Imperative?Michael Yudanin - 2015 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (3):595-614.
    Kant’s moral philosophy usually considers two types of duties: negative duties that prohibit certain actions and positive duties commanding action. With that, Kant insists on deriving all morality from reason alone. Such is the Categorical Imperative that Kant lays at the basis of ethics. Yet while negative duties can be derived from the Categorical Imperative and thus from reason, the paper argues that this is not the case with positive duties. After answering a number of attempts (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  22
    Why Are Kant’s Hypothetical and Categorical Imperatives Analytic and Synthetic A Priori Practical Propositions?Margit Ruffing, Guido A. De Almeida, Ricardo R. Terra & Valerio Rohden - 2008 - In Margit Ruffing, Guido A. De Almeida, Ricardo R. Terra & Valerio Rohden (eds.), Law and Peace in Kant's Philosophy/Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants: Proceedings of the 10th International Kant Congress/Akten des X. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Walter de Gruyter.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  12
    On the Rationale of Kant’s Categorical Imperative.Nicholas Rescher - 2000 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 3 (1):185-208.
    Over the years, various critics have accused Kant of a rigorism that is the moral equivalent of fiat iustitia ruat caelum. But this involves a greatly mistaken view of the nature and bearing of his categorical imperative. What Kant does in ethics is to employ a two domain approach that separates a rigoristic realm of theory from a more flexible realm of praxis that is oriented towards the real world of our experience. In the moral sphere demands of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  28
    The Categorical Imperative and the Face of the Other: Immanuel Kant and Emmanuel Levinas.Jurate Baranova - 2005 - In Contemporary philosophical discourse in Lithuania. Washington, D.C.: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy. pp. 4--41.
  14. Manager-employee relationships: Guided by Kant's categorical imperative or by dilbert's business principle. [REVIEW]Paul J. Borowski - 1998 - Journal of Business Ethics 17 (15):1623-1632.
    The relationship between Employer and Employees is a central one in the world of business. While an important relationship, it is one that is often a source of tension for the workplace. Employers are seemingly in constant mistrust of workers, while workers often look upon their bosses as "less than competent". In the American world of business today, should this "adversarial" relationship continue or should the Employer–Employee Relationship be governed by different rules. Immanuel Kant's Categorical Imperative offers some (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15. The Categorical Imperative and Kant’s Conception of Practical Rationality.Andrews Reath - 1989 - The Monist 72 (3):384-410.
    The primary concern of this paper is to outline an explanation of how Kant derives morality from reason. We all know that Kant thought that morality comprises a set of demands that are unconditionally and universally valid. In addition, he thought that to support this understanding of moral principles, one must show that they originate in reason a priori, rather than in contingent facts about human psychology, or the circumstances of human life. But do we really understand how he tries (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16. The Golden Rule Principle in African Ethics and Kant’s Categorical Imperative.Godwin Azenabor - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 10:17-23.
    This research attempts to throw light on and show the fundamental similarities and differences between the African and Western ethical conceptions by examining the foundation of ethics and morality in the two systems, using the Golden rule principle in African ethics and Kant’s categorical imperative in Western ethics as tools of comparative analysis. The African indigenous ethics revolves round the “Golden Rule Principle” as the ultimate moral principle. This principle states that “Do unto others what you want them (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Kant, Paton and BeckThe Categorical Imperative. A Study in Kant's Moral PhilosophyCritique of Practical Reason and other Writings in Moral Philosophy.John E. Smith - 1950 - Review of Metaphysics 3 (2):229-249.
    Although Paton depends for his materials on virtually all of Kant's writings on moral philosophy, he makes the Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten central to his analysis. This is a wise choice and one that is defensible since Paton has set for himself the task of elucidating the categorical imperative and it is in the Grundlegung that Kant sought to grasp the supreme principle of morality and its appearance to us as a categorical imperative. Despite the (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  98
    Immanuel Kant, Jürgen Habermas and the categorical imperative.Anders Bordum - 2005 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 31 (7):851-874.
    It has often been said that discourse ethics as developed by Jürgen Habermas can be understood as a dialogical continuation of the monological ethics developed by Immanuel Kant, as formulated in the categorical imperative in Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals. Like Kant’s categorical imperative, Habermas’ principle of universalization specifies a rule for impartial testing of norms for their moral worthiness. This article will substantiate that discourse ethics develops a dialogical version of the categorical (...), and will make this explicit. This is done by presenting a new interpretation of the Kantian ethics. Renewing the traditional understanding, four instead of two or three formulations of the categorical imperative are identified. Finally it is shown how this interpretation relates to Jürgen Habermas’ discourse ethics. This analysis shows that one must specify which formulation of the categorical imperative one is talking about when discussing it. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19. Categorical imperatives, moral requirements, and moral motivation.Xiaomei Yang - 2005 - Metaphilosophy 37 (1):112–129.
    Kant has argued that moral requirements are categorical. Kant's claim has been challenged by some contemporary philosophers; this article defends Kant's doctrine. I argue that Kant's claim captures the unique feature of moral requirements. The main arguments against Kant's claim focus on one condition that a categorical imperative must meet: to be independent of desires. I argue that there is another important, but often ignored, condition that a categorical imperative must meet, and this second condition (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  21
    Hegel on the Empty Formalism of Kant's Categorical Imperative.Sally Sedgwick - 2011 - In Stephen Houlgate & Michael Baur (eds.), A Companion to Hegel. Malden, MA: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 263–280.
    This chapter contains sections titled: 1 2 3 4 5.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  13
    Confucian Moral Principles and Kant's Categorical Imperative.Lim HeonGyu - 2010 - THE JOURNAL OF KOREAN PHILOSOPHICAL HISTORY 29:125-152.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  37
    Kant and the categorical imperative.Alan Montefiore - 2003 - Think 2 (5):75-82.
    Alan Montefiore explains how Kant's moral philosophy fits into and depends on the wider sweep of his work.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  67
    The Other as Categorical Imperative: Levinas’s Reading of Kant.Brigitta Keintzel - 2020 - Levinas Studies 14:127-149.
    For Kant and Levinas, the categorical imperative is the only possible formula for universalization. It has a structural necessity. Its claim is ultimate, valid without exception, and therefore reason-based. What differentiates Levinas from Kant is Kant’s assumption that “pure reason, practical of itself” is “immediately lawgiving.” Levinas contradicted this form of reason legislating itself as an end in itself: according to Levinas, reason has no self-generated power. Although both agree that the achievement of an ethical insight depends on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Kant on Determinism and the Categorical Imperative.Markus Kohl - 2015 - Ethics 125 (2):331-356.
    I provide a sympathetic reconstruction of Kant’s motivation for endorsing incompatibilism about human freedom. On my interpretation, Kant holds that if all the determining grounds of our actions were subject to natural necessity, we would never be free to respect or defy laws of practical reason, and for Kant such freedom is a condition for the possibility that our actions are governed by categorical imperatives. I argue that his view rests on a gripping construal of the rational imperfection that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  25.  16
    6. Maxims and Categorical Imperatives.Robert Greenberg - 2016 - In The Bounds of Freedom: Kant’s Causal Theory of Action. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 81-98.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  12
    Illocutionary logic as a tool for reconstructing Kant’s derivation of the formula of the categorical imperative from its mere concept.Dirk Greimann - 2024 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 28 (1):175-185.
    This paper aims to reconstruct Kant’s derivation of the formula of the categorical imperative from its mere concept with the help of the resources of Searle’s and Vanderveken’s illocutionary logic. The main exegetical hypothesis is that the derivation envisaged by Kant consists in deriving the formula from the success conditions of categorical imperatives. These conditions, which are analogous to the success conditions of ordinary orders, contain restrictions for the successful construction of a system of moral laws that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  50
    The Categorical Imperative in Action: Enabler and Enablee of Self-Legislation.Christoph Hanisch - 2023 - Philosophia 51 (2):597-607.
    Their important exegetical and philosophical disagreements notwithstanding, Pauline Kleingeld and Marcus Willaschek, on the one hand, and Alyssa Bernstein, on the other, seem to agree that Kant’s Categorical Imperative transcends the contemporary dichotomy between moral realism and ethical constructivism. My contribution is an attempt to further elaborate on the third, unique, conceptual option that they have identified. I employ the notion of an “enabling condition,” introduced in epistemology and action theory by Jonathan Dancy, in order to show that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  21
    The Unity of Pure Practical Reason: Towards a Unified Interpretation of the Three Formulas of Kant’s Categorical Imperative.Margit Ruffing, Guido A. De Almeida, Ricardo R. Terra & Valerio Rohden - 2008 - In Margit Ruffing, Guido A. De Almeida, Ricardo R. Terra & Valerio Rohden (eds.), Law and Peace in Kant's Philosophy/Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants: Proceedings of the 10th International Kant Congress/Akten des X. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Walter de Gruyter.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant's Moral Philosophy.H. J. Paton - 1946 - Hutchinson's University Library.
    This scarce antiquarian book is a facsimile reprint of the original. Due to its age, it may contain imperfections such as marks, notations, marginalia and flawed pages. Because we believe this work is culturally important, we have made it available as part of our commitment for protecting, preserving, and promoting the world's literature in affordable, high quality, modern editions that are true to the original work.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  30. Husserl’s Categorical Imperative and His Related Critique of Kant.Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl - 2010 - In Pol Vandevelde & Sebastian Luft (eds.), Epistemology, Archaeology, Ethics: Current Investigations of Husserl's Corpus. Continuum.
  31.  15
    Corporate Bodies and Categorical Imperatives.Eric Palmes - 2001 - In Volker Gerhardt, Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Ralph Schumacher (eds.), Kant Und Die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des IX Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. New York: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 228-238.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32. Groundwork for a Metaphysic of Morals (second formula of the categorical Imperative and other selections). Kant - 1997 - In Louis P. Pojman & Robert Westmoreland (eds.), Equality: Selected Readings. Oup Usa.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  98
    Kant and Compliance With Conventionalized Injustice.Cheshire Calhoun - 1994 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 32 (2):135-159.
    Kant's Categorical Imperative reveals the injustice of excepting ourselves from conventional social practices like promise keeping. But can it equally reveal the injustice of complying with societally entrenched unjust maxims, e.g., slave-holding maxims in colonial America? Standard Kantian arguments against slavery depend on overly narrow definitions of slavery and an implausible requirement that we universalization across all rational beings. This essay reconstructs the CI-procedure so that it can detect and explain the wrongness of conventionalized injustice. In particular, maxim (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34. The categorical imperative and the ethics of trust.Bjørn K. Myskja - 2008 - Ethics and Information Technology 10 (4):213-220.
    Trust can be understood as a precondition for a well-functioning society or as a way to handle complexities of living in a risk society, but also as a fundamental aspect of human morality. Interactions on the Internet pose some new challenges to issues of trust, especially connected to disembodiedness. Mistrust may be an important obstacle to Internet use, which is problematic as the Internet becomes a significant arena for political, social and commercial activities necessary for full participation in a liberal (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  35.  22
    The Categorical Imperative and the Natural Law.Roger J. Sullivan - 1989 - Proceedings of the Sixth International Kant Congress 2 (2):219-228.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  33
    The Categorical Imperative and Not Being Unworthy of the Event: Ethics in Deleuze's Difference and Repetition.Leonard Lawlor - 2020 - Deleuze and Guattari Studies 14 (1):109-135.
    This essay starts from a consideration of Deleuze's theory of time. It begins with the empty form of time. But the essay's aim is to understand Deleuze's reversal of Platonism in his 1968 Difference and Repetition. There is no question that the stakes of the reversal of Platonism are ontological. But I argue that what is really at stake is a movement of demoralisation. The essay proceeds in three steps. First, we determine what sufficient reason or grounding is, for Deleuze. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Categorical imperative as the source for morality.Joyce Lazier - 2011 - In Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone (eds.), Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Kant's argument that the categorical imperative is the source for morality broken down into premise and conclusion logical format.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Is the Categorical Imperative the Highest Principle of Both Pure Practical and Theoretical Reason?Heiner F. Klemme - 2014 - Kantian Review 19 (1):119-126.
    In her new book, Patricia Kitcher supports Onora O'Neill's view that the categorical imperative is the highest principle of both practical and theoretical reason. I claim that neither O'Neill's original interpretation nor Kitcher's additional evidence in favour of it are convincing. At its core, this misconception of Kant's position consists in the identification of self-referential critique of reason with the concept of autonomy. It will be shown that the (Kant) of both practical and theoretical reason is not the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39. Living the categorical imperative: autistic perspectives on lying and truth telling–between Kant and care ethics. [REVIEW]Pier Jaarsma, Petra Gelhaus & Stellan Welin - 2012 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 15 (3):271-277.
    Lying is a common phenomenon amongst human beings. It seems to play a role in making social interactions run more smoothly. Too much honesty can be regarded as impolite or downright rude. Remarkably, lying is not a common phenomenon amongst normally intelligent human beings who are on the autism spectrum. They appear to be ‘attractively morally innocent’ and seem to have an above average moral conscientious objection against deception. In this paper, the behavior of persons with autism with regard to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40.  16
    Categorical Imperative as the Source for Morality.Joyce Lazier - 2011 - In Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone (eds.), Just the Arguments. Chichester, West Sussex, U.K.: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 217–220.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Kant's utopian categorical imperative.E. Ethelbert Miller - unknown
    The motivation of this paper is to contribute to the project of finding new ways to use "utopia" in philosophy again. Since philosophers as well as poets can look to their forbears for inspiration in re-inventing terms, it would be nice if those of us trying to rehabilitate the term could lean a bit on our own disciplinary heavies, especially in the current climate of philosophical skepticism, even cynicism, about the very idea of utopia. My contribution to that task here (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  34
    The Extraordinary Categorical Imperative.Shalini Satkunanandan - 2011 - Political Theory 39 (2):234-260.
    Many political theorists assume that Kant's categorical imperative can only present itself to politics epistemologically—that is, as a test or procedure for acquiring more certain knowledge of duties. This study retrieves the ontological aspect of the categorical imperative by showing that the Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals is a conversion narrative. In the Groundwork Kant describes a transformative encounter with the categorical imperative as a principle that discloses our ontological condition. This encounter opens (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43. Right, Morals, and the Categorical Imperative.Fiorella Tomassini - 2023 - Kant Studien 114 (3):513-538.
    In this paper I examine the relationship between the principle of right and the principle of morals [Sitten] in Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals. My interpretation denies that the principle of right is derived from the categorical imperative, but neither does it adhere to the independence thesis. I present a third way of understanding the relationship between the law of right and the universal law of morals: the latter is needed in order to formulate the former, but it is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  34
    God’s Law or Categorical Imperative: on Crusian Issues of Kantian Morality.L. E. Kryshtop - 2019 - Kantian Journal 38 (2):31-44.
    The ethics of Kant and the ethics of Crusius are strikingly similar. This is manifested in a whole range of principles and concepts. Crusius’ moral teaching hinges on the rigorous moral law which has to be obeyed absolutely, and which makes it different from other prescriptions that are binding only to a relative degree. This is very close to the Kantian distinction between hypothetical and categorical imperatives. Another salient feature of Crusius’ moral teaching is the stress laid on the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  57
    Kalin on the categorical imperative.Jeffrie G. Murphy - 1969 - Ethics 79 (2):163-164.
    The article is a critical reply to jesse kalin's "a note on singer and kant" ("ethics", 1968). Kalin had argued that kant's categorical imperative entails absurdly counterintuitive consequences--E.G. That it is wrong to punish people. Against kalin, It is argued that such consequences are not entailed by the categorical imperative if it is properly interpreted. A proper interpretation involves, For example, Distinguishing the categorical imperative's function as a criterion for imperfect duties from its function (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  94
    Kantian Right and the Categorical Imperative: Response to Willaschek.Michael Nance - 2012 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 20 (4):541-556.
    Abstract In his 2009 article "Right and Coercion," Marcus Willaschek argues that the Categorical Imperative and the Universal Principle of Right are conceptually independent of one another because (1) the concept of right and the authorization to use coercion are analytically connected in Kant's "Doctrine of Right", but (2) the authorization to coerce cannot be derived from the Categorical Imperative. Given that the principle of right just is a principle of authorized coercion, the fact that the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  82
    The Categorical Imperative and the Golden Rule.E. W. Hirst - 1934 - Philosophy 9 (35):328 - 335.
    Is the assimilation of these two formulations of the moral principle by Kant and some of his expositors justified? In the Analytic of Pure Practical Reason Kant claims that his view of morality agrees with the ancient command that man should love his neighbour as himself. Also in the Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals he regards the Golden Rule as a deduction, though with several limitations, from the second version of the Categorical Imperative.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Practical Reason: Categorical Imperative, Maxims, Laws.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2010 - In Will Dudley & K. Engelhard (eds.), Kant: Key Concepts. Acumen Publishing.
    This chapter considers the centrality of principles in Kant’s moral philosophy, their distinctively ‘Kantian’ character, why Kant presents a ‘metaphysical’ system of moral principles and how these ‘formal’ principles are to be used in practice. These points are central to how Kant thinks pure reason can be practical. These features have often puzzled Anglophone readers, in part due to focusing on Kant’s Groundwork, to the neglect of his later works in moral philosophy, in which the theoretical preliminaries of that first (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  35
    The Categorical Imperative and the Universal Principle of Right.Michael Nance - 2013 - In Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Boston: de Gruyter. pp. 873-884.
  50.  18
    The Ethics of the Categorical Imperative. Lossky under the Influence of Kant.Polina R. Bonadyseva - 2022 - Kantian Journal 41 (4):60-75.
    The Russian intuitivist philosopher Nikolay Lossky repeatedly admitted Kant’s substantial formative influence on him as a scholar. Moreover, Lossky was a disciple of the Russian Kantian Aleksander Vvedensky, and was one of the most successful translators of the first Critique. However, his own philosophical project is rather the opposite of the critical programme. While in the framework of Lossky’s epistemology the specificities of his reading of Kant have received a fair amount of attention in Russian scholarship, in the ethical field (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 955