Results for '‘Is’–‘ought’ derivation'

981 found
Order:
  1. ‘Is’–‘Ought’ Derivations and Ethical Taxonomies.Scott Hill - 2008 - Philosophia 36 (4):545-566.
    Hume seems to claim that there does not exist a valid argument that has all non-ethical sentences as premises and an ethical sentence as its conclusion. Starting with Prior, a number of counterexamples to this claim have been proposed. Unfortunately, all of these proposals are controversial. Even the most plausible have a premise that seems like it might be an ethical sentence or a conclusion that seems like it might be non-ethical. Since it is difficult to tell whether any of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  2.  22
    A Critique of Gewirth's "Is-Ought" Derivation.Paul Allen Iii - 1982 - Ethics 92 (2):211 - 226.
  3.  29
    A Critique of Gewirth's "Is-Ought" Derivation.Paul Allen - 1982 - Ethics 92 (2):211-226.
  4.  44
    A critique of Gewirth's "is-ought" derivation.I. I. I. Allen - 1982 - Ethics 92 (2):211-226.
  5.  17
    The is-Ought Problem: An Investigation in Philosophical Logic.Gerhard Schurz - 1997 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Schurz draws on modern alethic- deontic predicate logic to address the venerable yet enduring problem of whether what ought to be can be derived from what is. After two extensive introductory chapters supplying the background in philosophy and logic to readers unfamiliar with it, he examines such dimensions as the logical explication of Hume's thesis, the special Hume thesis, weakened versions of it, generalizations, some applications to ethical arguments, problems of identity and existence, whether there are analytic bridge principles, and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  6. Collective Acceptance and the Is-Ought Argument.Frank Hindriks - 2013 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16 (3):465-480.
    According to John Searle’s well-known Is-Ought Argument, it is possible to derive an ought-statement from is-statements only. This argument concerns obligations involved in institutions such as promising, and it relies on the idea that institutions can be conceptualized in terms of constitutive rules. In this paper, I argue that the structure of this argument has never been fully appreciated. Starting from my status account of constitutive rules, I reconstruct the argument and establish that it is valid. This reconstruction reveals that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  7. Closing the ‘Is’-‘Ought’ Gap.Stephen Maitzen - 1998 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28 (3):349-366.
    In a dense and fascinating article of some ten years ago, Toomas Karmo adds his voice to the chorus of philosophers who deny the possibility of soundly deriving ‘ought’ from ‘is.’ According to Karmo, no derivation containing an ethical conclusion and only non-ethical premises can possibly be sound, where ‘sound’ describes a deductively valid derivation all of whose premises are true. He also suggests that the only valid derivations of ‘ought’ from ‘is’ will be trivial ones. His argument (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  8. Hume’s Is/Ought Dichtomy and the Relation of Ecology to Leopold’s Land Ethic.J. Baird Callicott - 1982 - Environmental Ethics 4 (2):163-174.
    Environmental ethics in its modem classical expression by Aldo Leopold appears to fall afoul of Hume’s prohibition against deriving ought-statements from is-statements since it is presented as a logical consequence of the science of ecology. Hume’s is/ought dichotomy is reviewed in its historical theoretical context. A general formulation bridging is and ought, in Hume’s terms, meeting his own criteria for sound practical argument, is found. It is then shown that Aldo Leopold’s land ethic is expressible as a special case of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  9.  38
    The “is-ought fallacy” fallacy.Mike Oaksford & Nick Chater - 2011 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (5):262-263.
    Mere facts about how the world is cannot determine how we ought to think or behave. Elqayam & Evans (E&E) argue that this undercuts the use of rational analysis in explaining how people reason, by ourselves and with others. But this presumed application of the fallacy is itself fallacious. Rational analysis seeks to explain how people do reason, for example in laboratory experiments, not how they ought to reason. Thus, no ought is derived from an is; and rational analysis is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  34
    Doing Justice to the Is-Ought Gap.Matt Silliman & David K. Braden-Johnson - 2018 - Social Philosophy Today 34:117-132.
    The two characters in this philosophical dialogue, Russell Steadman and Jules Govier, take up the meaning and significance of David Hume’s famous “is-ought gap”—the proscription on inferring a fully moral claim from any number of purely descriptive statements. Building on the recent work of Hilary Putnam and John F. Post, Jules attempts to show that Hume’s rule is of little consequence when discussing matters related to justice or morality as we encounter them in daily life. He derives his conclusion from (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  43
    On Deriving an Ought from an Is: A Retrospective Look.Kai Nielsen - 1979 - Review of Metaphysics 32 (3):487 - 514.
    ARGUMENT ABOUT whether in any significant sense we can derive an ought from an is has been persistent and intractable. Fifteen to twenty years ago it was orthodoxy in analytical philosophical circles to claim that for all their other differences Hume and Moore were right in agreeing that in no significant sense can we derive an ought from an is. At present there is no orthodoxy or even anything like a dominant view and, given our current understanding of how language (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12. Dissolving the Is-Ought problem: An essay on moral reasoning.Jeremiah Joven Joaquin - manuscript
    The debate concerning the proper way of understanding, and hence solving, the “is-ought problem” produced two mutually exclusive positions. One position claims that it is entirely impossible to deduce an imperative statement from a set of factual statements. The other position holds a contrary view to the effect that one can naturally derive an imperative statement from a set of factual statements under certain conditions. Although these two positions have opposing views concerning the problem, it should be evident that they (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  31
    On Deriving 'Ought' from 'Is'.James E. McClellan & B. Paul Komisar - 1964 - Analysis 25 (2):32 - 37.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  14
    On deriving 'ought' from 'is'.James E. Mcclellan & Alonso Church - 1964 - Analysis 25 (2):32.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Rebutting formally valid counterexamples to the Humean “is-ought” dictum.Daniel Guevara - 2008 - Synthese 164 (1):45-60.
    Various formally valid counterexamples have been adduced against the Humean dictum that one cannot derive an “ought” from an “is.” There are formal rebuttals—some very sophisticated now (e.g., Charles R. Pigden’s and Gerhard Schurz’s)—to such counterexamples. But what follows is an intuitive and informal argument against them. I maintain that it is better than these sophisticated formal defenses of the Humean dictum and that it also helps us see why it implausible to think that we can be as decisive about (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  18
    Revisiting Searle on Deriving “Ought” From “Is”.Paolo Di Lucia & Edoardo Fittipaldi (eds.) - 2021 - Springer Verlag.
    This book reconsiders the supposed impossibility of deriving "Ought" from "Is". John R. Searle’s 1964 article How to Derive "Ought " from "Is’’ sent shockwaves through the philosophical community by offering a straightforward counterexample to this claim of impossibility: from your promising something- and this is an "is" - it simply follows that you "ought" to do it. This volume opens with a brand new chapter from Searle who, in light of his subsequent philosophical developments, expounds the reasons for the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. The Derivation of "Ought" from "Is".Jack Kaminsky - 1958 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 12 (2):144.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  85
    Does the Is-Ought Issue Suggest a Transcendental Realm?Halil Turan - 2007 - The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 1:7-12.
    The principle that values cannot be derived from facts, though first explicitly formulated by David Hume, does not seem to be consistent with Hume's assertions that value becomes intelligible through experience, and that the will is determined by pleasure and pain. Moral reasoning involving pleasures and pains in the context of the peculiarities of human existence in society must be more complicated than reasoning involving ordinary, i.e. natural, pleasures and pains. Nevertheless, all pains and pleasures must be sensations. Hence Hume's (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Kant’s derivation of the moral ‘ought’ from a metaphysical ‘is’.Colin Marshall - 2022 - In Schafer Karl & Stang Nicholas (eds.), The Sensible and Intelligible Worlds: New Essays on Kant's Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxforrd University Press. pp. 382-404.
    In this chapter, I argue that Kant can be read as holding that "ought" judgments follow from certain "is" judgments by mere analysis. More specifically, I defend an interpretation according to which (1) Kant holds that “S ought to F” is analytically equivalent to “If, as it can and would were there no other influences on the will, S’s faculty of reason determined S’s willing, S would F” and (2) Kant’s notions of reason, the will, and freedom are all fundamentally (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  46
    Hume and Searle : the ‘Is-Ought’ Gap versus Speech Act Theory.Daniel Schulthess - 2011
    The article compares David Humes’ and John Searle’s positions concerning the relation between descriptive and evaluative statements. Although the two positions seem to be just opposite in that Hume denies the derivability of the ought from the is, while Seale accepts it, the author shows that Hume and Searle have many similarities, for for both obligations rely upon the institution of promising. The difference is that for Hume the speech act of promising as such does not have intrinsic evaluative impact. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Hume on Is and Ought.Charles Pigden (ed.) - 2010 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    It ‘seems altogether inconceivable', says Hume, that this ‘new relation' ought ‘can be a deduction' from others ‘which are entirely different from it' The idea that you can't derive an Ought from an Is, moral conclusions from non-moral premises, has proved enormously influential. But what did Hume mean by this famous dictum? Was he correct? How does it fit in with the rest of his philosophy? And what does this suggest about the nature of moral judgements? This collection, the first (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  22.  87
    Is it Always Fallacious to Derive Values From Facts?Mark T. Nelson - 1995 - Argumentation 9 (4):553-562.
    Charles Pigden has argued for a logical Is/Ought gap on the grounds of the conservativeness of logic. I offer a counter-example which shows that Pigden’s argument is unsound and that there need be no logical gap between Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion. My counter-example is an argument which is logically valid, has only Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion, does not purport to violate the conservativeness of logic, and does not rely on controversial assumptions about Aristotelian biology or 'institutional facts.'.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  23.  73
    You ought to derive "ought" from "is".Robert V. Hannaford - 1972 - Ethics 82 (2):155-162.
  24.  49
    Can An ‘Ought’ Be Derived From An ‘Is’?Philippa Foot - 2019 - Philosophy Now 130:26-27.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  49
    Searle’s Derivation of ‘Ought’ from ‘Is’.Dennis A. Rohatyn - 1973 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 22:121-138.
  26.  9
    Another Way to Derive an 'Ought' from an 'Is'.Elizabeth Smith - 1978 - Philosophy Research Archives 4:247-256.
    In Speech Acts John Searle reframed his derivation of 'ought' from 'is' in order to eliminate the controversial ceteris paribus premises. I argue that the elimination of the first ceteris paribus (3a) is satisfactory but that the elimination of (4a) renders questionable his claim that an 'ought' statement follows from the premises categorically. Further I argue that the use of dilemma in the proof will enable us to show that an 'ought' statement follows from the premises whether everything (at (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  6
    Searle and Conte on Deriving Ought from Is.Jan Woleński - 2021 - In Paolo Di Lucia & Edoardo Fittipaldi (eds.), Revisiting Searle on Deriving “Ought” From “Is”. Springer Verlag. pp. 239-251.
    The view I defend here is that ought cannot be logically derived from is. This can be justified at the level of very elementary deontic logic, as captured by the generalized logical square. This logical fact can be stated as the Hume thesis. However, the inspection of a given normative order may suggest that something exists. On the other hand, such conclusions can be fallible. In order to argue that ought is derivable from is, one must use extralogical elements and, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. In Defense of A Derivation of 'Ought'From 'Is'.M. R. Wheeler - 1999 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 26 (3):344-354.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  50
    On Deriving 'Ought' from 'Is'.Evan K. Jobe - 1965 - Analysis 25 (5):179 - 181.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. How to Derive “Ought” from “Is” Revisited.John R. Searle - 2021 - In Paolo Di Lucia & Edoardo Fittipaldi (eds.), Revisiting Searle on Deriving “Ought” From “Is”. Springer Verlag. pp. 3-16.
    In his seminal article “How to Derive ‘Ought’ from ‘Is’,” which was published in 1964, John R. Searle offered a counterexample to Hume’s law. Here, Searle reconstructs the historical context in which that article appeared, when the task of moral philosophers—especially in the Anglophone world—was supposed to be metaethics, which aims to describe the use of ethical terms and their logical behavior. Searle stands by the validity of his derivation, and in light of his subsequent philosophical developments—notably his social (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. (1 other version)How to derive "ought" from "is".John R. Searle - 1964 - Philosophical Review 73 (1):43-58.
  32.  38
    Ways of deriving `ought' from `is'.F. Gerald Downing - 1972 - Philosophical Quarterly 22 (88):234-247.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  19
    Is and Ought: Where Does the Problem Lie?Pedro M. S. Alves - 2021 - In Paolo Di Lucia & Edoardo Fittipaldi (eds.), Revisiting Searle on Deriving “Ought” From “Is”. Springer Verlag. pp. 33-57.
    The chapter has two parts. In the first part, I introduce a more fine-grained analysis of evaluative sentences. I distinguish between evaluations proper and directions for action with several degrees of constraint: commands, pieces of advice, suggestions, and so on. I call the latter “ductive-statements.” Thus, I affirm that the realm of morals has two branches: one relative to evaluations, which are is-sentences ranging from the several degrees between good and bad to the indifferent ; the other relative to sentences (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. On Not Deriving 'Ought' from Is'.Antony Flew - 1964 - Analysis 25 (2):25 - 32.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  71
    The ‘Is’ and the ‘Ought’ of the Animal Organism: Hegel’s Account of Biological Normativity.Luca Corti - 2022 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 44 (2):1-22.
    This paper investigates Hegel’s account of the animal organism as it is presented in the Philosophy of Nature, with a special focus on its normative implications. I argue that the notion of “organisation” is fundamental to Hegel’s theory of animal normativity. The paper starts by showing how a Hegelian approach takes up the scientific image of organism and assigns a basic explanatory role to the notion of “organisation” in its understanding living beings. Moving from this premise, the paper turns to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36. Hume On Is and Ought: Logic, Promises and the Duke of Wellington.Charles Pigden - 2016 - In Paul Russell (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of David Hume. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Hume seems to contend that you can’t get an ought from an is. Searle professed to prove otherwise, deriving a conclusion about obligations from a premise about promises. Since (as Schurz and I have shown) you can’t derive a substantive ought from an is by logic alone, Searle is best construed as claiming that there are analytic bridge principles linking premises about promises to conclusions about obligations. But we can no more derive a moral obligation to pay up from the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  95
    Charles R. Pigden : Hume on Is and Ought: Palgrave Macmillan, Hampshire, 2010, xiv + 352 pp, ISBN: 978-0-230-20520-8, GBP 74.00.David Hommen - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (6):1419-1422.
    Within a single paragraph in his Treatise of Human Nature, David Hume prompted what has become one of the most central orthodoxies in ethical theory: the thesis that one cannot derive what ought to be from what there is. In the aftermath of Hume’s seminal discussion, the No-Ought-From-Is-thesis has obtained approval among moral theorists to the point that it has been assigned the status of an undisputed ‘law’. As common with commonplaces in philosophy, alas, both the exact content and argument (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  22
    The “Is” and “Ought” Convention.Duen Marti-Huang - 1987 - Dialectica 41 (1‐2):145-153.
    SummaryInstead of telling us why one should or should not derive an ‘ought’ from an ‘is’, most philosophers try to see whether this can or cannot be done. Since there are no clearly stated rules of inference for the ordinary language, the is‐ought dichotomy is re‐examined within the context of the deontic logic. This paper shows that rules like ‐AB ÓOB enables us to adopt the theorems of the propositional logic normatively, because logical standards for exactness, truth, completeness, etc. are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. pt. 4. The challenge of deriving an ought from an is: Moral acquaintances and natural facts in the Darwinian age.Stephen S. Hanson - 2009 - In Mark J. Cherry (ed.), The normativity of the natural: human goods, human virtues, and human flourishing. [Dordrecht]: Springer.
  40.  86
    Searle’s Derivation, Natural Law, and Moral Relativism.Edmund Wall - 2008 - Philosophia 36 (2):237-249.
    Some philosophers have maintained that even if John R. Searle’s attempted derivation of an evaluative proposition from purely descriptive premises is successful, moral ought would not have been derived. Searle agrees. I will argue that if Searle has successfully derived “ought,” then, based on various approaches taken towards the content of “morality,” this is moral ought. I will also trace out some of the benefits of a successful derivation of moral ought in relation to natural law ethics. I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  58
    How and why we reason from is to ought.Jonathan St B. T. Evans & Shira Elqayam - 2020 - Synthese 197 (4):1429-1446.
    Originally identified by Hume, the validity of is–ought inference is much debated in the meta-ethics literature. Our work shows that inference from is to ought typically proceeds from contextualised, value-laden causal utility conditional, bridging into a deontic conclusion. Such conditional statements tell us what actions are needed to achieve or avoid consequences that are good or bad. Psychological research has established that people generally reason fluently and easily with utility conditionals. Our own research also has shown that people’s reasoning from (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  93
    It Does Not Matter Whether We Can Derive 'Ought' from 'Is'.Alison Jaggar - 1974 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (3):373 - 379.
    In this paper, I want to discuss the recent attempts by Professor John R. Searle to cast doubt on the traditional empiricist distinction between fact and value. Searle's first attack on this distinction was made in 1964 in his now classic article, “How to derive ‘ought’ from ‘is’.” In that paper, he presented what he claimed to be a counter-example to the thesis that statements of fact may not entail statements of value. Searle's argument aroused much controversy and inspired many (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  73
    How not to derive "ought" from "is".James Thomson & Judith Thomson - 1964 - Philosophical Review 73 (4):512-516.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  44
    Democritus on Being and Ought: Some Remarks on the Existential Side of Early Greek Atomism.Björn Freter - 2018 - AKROPOLIS: Journal of Hellenic Studies 2:67-84.
    According to Democritus' anthropogeny is a microcosmic consequence within the process of cosmogony. However, the case of man is a peculiarity: man, this atom complex, is well aware of himself, yet is not aware of what he must do. Man does not naturally do that which promotes the harmonious ordering of his atoms. We must create a second nature. Now it becomes possible for us to be as we must be according to our first nature. Democritus is the is first (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  93
    Frankena on ‘Ought’ and ‘Is’.Robert L. Holmes - 1981 - The Monist 64 (3):394-405.
    Despite its centrality for ethical theory, and the near-axiomatic status it enjoyed for years, the thesis that an Ought cannot be derived from an Is has not until fairly recently come in for close scrutiny. During this time, however, there has been a swing of the pendulum from the view of G. E. Moore, that no one in his right mind could deny the thesis, to that of some contemporary philosophers who speak as though no one in his right mind (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  48
    From Is to Ought: Natural Law in Buddhadasa Bhikkhu and Phra Prayudh Payutto.Sallie B. King - 2002 - Journal of Religious Ethics 30 (2):275 - 293.
    The contemporary Thai Theravada Buddhist monks Buddhadasa Bhikkhu and Phra Prayyudh Payutto espouse a version of natural law thinking in which the norms of good behavior derive from the nature of the world, specifically its features of conditionality, causality, karma and interdependence. An ethic which stresses non-egoic harmony is the result. This paper (1) develops the notion of natural law in their thinking and (2) critically evaluates these ideas as a foundation for ethical thought, specifically asking whether such ideas recognize (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  78
    You cannot derive "ought" from "is".Warren J. Samuels - 1973 - Ethics 83 (2):159-162.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  52
    Ought" and "Is.R. F. Atkinson & A. C. Montefiore - 1958 - Philosophy 33 (124):29 - 49.
    There is probably no student of modern philosophy, and certainly no listener to the Third Programme, who has never received the warning that he must on no account deduce an “ought” from an “is.” This prohibition, it is claimed, is securely based in established and unchallengeable principles of logic. Professor Flew was speaking for many others when he said, in the course of a broadcast entitled “Problems of Perspectives”, “I think it is very important indeed to make as clear as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  35
    A note on John R. Searle's derivation of 'ought' from 'is'.Harald Ofstad & Lars Bergström - 1965 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 8 (1-4):309-314.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. The Normative Ground of the Evidential Ought.Anne Meylan - 2020 - In Scott Stapleford & Kevin McCain (eds.), Epistemic Duties: New Arguments, New Angles. New York: Routledge.
    Many philosophers have defended the view that we are subject to the following evidential ought: “One ought to believe in accordance with one's evidence.” Although they agree on this, a more fundamental question keeps dividing them: from where does the evidential ought derive its normative force? The instrinsicalist answer to this question is sometimes described as the claim that "there is a brute epistemic value in believing in accordance with one's evidence" (Cowie, 2014, 4005). But what does this really mean? (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 981