Results for 'Biological macromolecules'

971 found
Order:
  1.  23
    The significance of the macromolecules in the historiography of molecular biology.Robert C. Olby - 1979 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 1 (2):185 - 198.
  2.  41
    The chondrocyte, architect of cartilage. Biomechanics, structure, function and molecular biology of cartilage matrix macromolecules.Helen Muir - 1995 - Bioessays 17 (12):1039-1048.
    Chondrocytes are specialised cells which produce and maintain the extracellular matrix of cartilage, a tissue that is resilient and pliant. In vivo, it has to withstand very high compressive loads, and that is explicable in terms of the physico‐chemical properties of cartilage‐specific macromolecules and with the movement of water and ions within the matrix. The functions of the cartilage‐specific collagens, aggrecan (a hydrophilic proteoglycan) and hyaluronan are discussed within this context. The structures of cartilage collagens and proteoglycans and their (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  52
    Biological complexity and the dynamics of life processes.Jacques Ricard - 1999 - New York: Elsevier.
    The aim of this book is to show how supramolecular complexity of cell organization can dramatically alter the functions of individual macromolecules within a cell. The emergence of new functions which appear as a consequence of supramolecular complexity, is explained in terms of physical chemistry. The book is interdisciplinary, at the border between cell biochemistry, physics and physical chemistry. This interdisciplinarity does not result in the use of physical techniques but from the use of physical concepts to study (...) problems. In the domain of complexity studies, most works are purely theoretical or based on computer simulation. The present book is partly theoretical, partly experimental and theory is always based on experimental results. Moreover, the book encompasses in a unified manner the dynamic aspects of many different biological fields ranging from dynamics to pattern emergence in a young embryo. The volume puts emphasis on dynamic physical studies of biological events. It also develops, in a unified perspective, this new interdisciplinary approach of various important problems of cell biology and chemistry, ranging from enzyme dynamics to pattern formation during embryo development, thus paving the way to what may become a central issue of future biology. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  19
    ¿Es posible una ontología procesual de las entidades bioquímicas? Consideraciones a partir del caso de los receptores celulares y la señalización celular.Fiorela Alassia - 2022 - Estudios de Filosofía (Universidad de Antioquia) 65:153-175.
    Biological macromolecules, considered as the items of the biochemical domain, are typically conceived under the ontological category of substantial individuals. In this paper, I will argue that the philosophical framework of process ontology, according to which the living world is not populated by individuals but by a dynamic hierarchy of processes, is more adequate to account for the structure and functioning of macromolecules. In particular, I will analyze its application to the phenomenon of cell signaling and to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  54
    Sorry, Darwin: Chemistry Never Made the Transition to Biology.Bhakti Niskama Shanta - 2011 - Science and Scientist (scienceandscientist.org/biology) and Darwin Under Siege (scienceandscientist.org/Darwin).
    The term biology is of Greek origin meaning the study of life. On the other hand, chemistry is the science of matter, which deals with matter and its properties, structure, composition, behavior, reactions, interactions and the changes it undergoes. The theory of abiogenesis maintains that chemistry made a transition to biology in a primordial soup. To keep the naturalistic ‘inanimate molecules to human life’ evolution ideology intact, scientists must assemble billions of links to bridge the gap between the inanimate chemicals (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  45
    The Two Cultures and Systems Biology: How Philosophy Starts Where Science Ends.Yanay Ofran - 2008 - The European Legacy 13 (5):589-604.
    The gap between Science and the Humanities becomes tangible when they both attempt to address the same problem. One such case is relationship between Life and biological molecules. Traditionally, molecular biology has attempted to explain biological processes in terms of physicochemical characteristics of individual macromolecules. The new science of systems biology largely ignores the molecular characteristics of specific molecules and endeavors to analyze biological processes through the relationship between thousands of molecules. On the face of it, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  33
    Fluorescence correlation spectroscopy for the detection and study of single molecules in biology.Miguel Ángel Medina & Petra Schwille - 2002 - Bioessays 24 (8):758-764.
    The recent development of single molecule detection techniques has opened new horizons for the study of individual macromolecules under physiological conditions. Conformational subpopulations, internal dynamics and activity of single biomolecules, parameters that have so far been hidden in large ensemble averages, are now being unveiled. Herein, we review a particular attractive solution‐based single molecule technique, fluorescence correlation spectroscopy (FCS). This time‐averaging fluctuation analysis which is usually performed in Confocal setups combines maximum sensitivity with high statistical confidence. FCS has proven (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  31
    The amount and value of information in biology.M. V. Volkenstein - 1977 - Foundations of Physics 7 (1-2):97-109.
    The notion of the value of information is discussed. The value one attributes to information is determined by the result of its reception by an open nonequilibrium system. Qualitative reasoning shows that the concept of value of information makes sense only in nonequilibrium situations, and is directly connected with the nonredundancy of information. In biology it is the value and not the amount of information that is important. The value of information is especially high if there are instabilities in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  16
    Of Arrows and Flows. Causality, Determination, and Specificity in the Central Dogma of Molecular Biology.Bernardino Fantini - 2006 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 28 (4):567 - 593.
    From its first proposal, the Central Dogma had a graphical form, complete with arrows of different types, and this form quickly became its standard presentation. In different scientific contexts, arrows have different meanings and in this particular case the arrows indicated the flow of information among different macromolecules. A deeper analysis illustrates that the arrows also imply a causal statement, directly connected to the causal role of genetic information. The author suggests a distinction between two different kinds of causal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  30
    The Theory of Chemical Symbiosis: A Margulian View for the Emergence of Biological Systems.Francisco Prosdocimi, Marco V. José & Sávio Torres de Farias - 2020 - Acta Biotheoretica 69 (1):67-78.
    The theory of chemical symbiosis suggests that biological systems started with the collaboration of two polymeric molecules existing in early Earth: nucleic acids and peptides. Chemical symbiosis emerged when RNA-like nucleic acid polymers happened to fold into 3D structures capable to bind amino acids together, forming a proto peptidyl-transferase center. This folding catalyzed the formation of quasi-random small peptides, some of them capable to bind this ribozyme structure back and starting to form an initial layer that would produce the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11. Macromolecular Pluralism.Matthew H. Slater - 2009 - Philosophy of Science 76 (5):851-863.
    Different chemical species are often cited as paradigm examples of structurally delimited natural kinds. While classificatory monism may thus seem plausible for simple molecules, it looks less attractive for complex biological macromolecules. I focus on the case of proteins that are most plausibly individuated by their functions. Is there a single, objective count of proteins? I argue that the vagaries of function individuation infect protein classification. We should be pluralists about macromolecular classification.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  12.  43
    Structural and organisational conditions for being a machine.Guglielmo Militello & Álvaro Moreno - 2018 - Biology and Philosophy 33 (5-6):35.
    Although the analogy between macroscopic machines and biological molecular devices plays an important role in the conceptual framework of both neo-mechanistic accounts and nanotechnology, it has recently been claimed that certain complex molecular devices cannot be considered machines since they are subject to physicochemical forces that are different from those of macroscopic machines. However, the structural and physicochemical conditions that allow both macroscopic machines and microscopic devices to work and perform new functions, through a combination of elemental functional parts, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13.  57
    The generality of scientific models: a measure theoretic approach.Cory Travers Lewis & Christopher Belanger - 2015 - Synthese 192 (1):269-285.
    Scientific models are often said to be more or less general depending on how many cases they cover. In this paper we argue that the cardinality of cases is insufficient as a metric of generality, and we present a novel account based on measure theory. This account overcomes several problems with the cardinality approach, and additionally provides some insight into the nature of assessments of generality. Specifically, measure theory affords a natural and quantitative way of describing local spaces of possibility. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  30
    Electron microscopy of helical filaments: rediscovering buried treasures in negative stain.Edward H. Egelman & Linda A. Amos - 2009 - Bioessays 31 (9):909-911.
    Although negative stain electron microscopy is a wonderfully simple way of directly visualizing protein complexes and other biological macromolecules, the images are not really comparable to those of objects seen in everyday life. The failure to appreciate this has recently led to an incorrect interpretation of RecA‐family filament structures.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  36
    Hypercomplexity.Vic Norris, Armelle Cabin & Abdallah Zemirline - 2005 - Acta Biotheoretica 53 (4):313-330.
    What is biological complexity? How many sorts exist? Are there levels of complexity? How are they related to one another? How is complexity related to the emergence of new phenotypes? To try to get to grips with these questions, we consider the archetype of a complex biological system, Escherichia coli. We take the position that E. coli has been selected to survive adverse conditions and to grow in favourable ones and that many other complex systems undergo similar selection. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The Origin of Cellular Life and Biosemiotics.Attila Grandpierre - 2013 - Biosemiotics (3):1-15.
    Recent successes of systems biology clarified that biological functionality is multilevel. We point out that this fact makes it necessary to revise popular views about macromolecular functions and distinguish between local, physico-chemical and global, biological functions. Our analysis shows that physico-chemical functions are merely tools of biological functionality. This result sheds new light on the origin of cellular life, indicating that in evolutionary history, assignment of biological functions to cellular ingredients plays a crucial role. In this (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  25
    Is life as a multiverse phenomenon?Claus Emmeche - 1993 - In Christopher G. Langton (ed.), Artificial Life III ( = Santa Fe Institute Studies in the Sciences of Complexity, Proceedings Volume XVII). Reading, Massachusetts.: Addison-Wesley Publishing Company.
    When posing the question "is artificial life possible?", our immediate answer is that on the one hand : of course it is - people make it, and indeed very interesting and even breathtaking structures have already been constructed, such as `aminats', self-reproducing patterns and the other things, we have seen already. In this sense we are forced to take artificial life as a fact (at least as a fact about a new branch of research), nearly in the same way that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18. The Varieties of Molecular Explanation.Marco J. Nathan - 2012 - Philosophy of Science 79 (2):233-254.
    Reductionists in biology claim that all biological events can be explained in terms of genes and macromolecules alone, while antireductionists argue that some biological events must be explained at a higher level. The literature, however, does not distinguish between different kinds of molecular explanation. The goal of this article is to identify and analyze three such kinds. The analysis of molecular explanations herein carries an important philosophical implication; in shunning crude reductionism and extreme versions of holism, we (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  19.  12
    Complex systems in drug research: II. The ligand-active site-water confluence as a complex system.Lemont B. Kier & Bernard Testa - 1996 - Complexity 1 (4):37-42.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  73
    History in the Gene: Negotiations Between Molecular and Organismal Anthropology.Marianne Sommer - 2008 - Journal of the History of Biology 41 (3):473-528.
    In the advertising discourse of human genetic database projects, of genetic ancestry tracing companies, and in popular books on anthropological genetics, what I refer to as the anthropological gene and genome appear as documents of human history, by far surpassing the written record and oral history in scope and accuracy as archives of our past. How did macromolecules become "documents of human evolutionary history"? Historically, molecular anthropology, a term introduced by Emile Zuckerkandl in 1962 to characterize the study of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  21.  28
    Chemistry and the Engineering of Life Around 1900: Research and Reflections by Jacques Loeb.Ute Deichmann - 2009 - Biological Theory 4 (4):323-332.
    Dissatisfied with the descriptive and speculative methods of evolutionary biology of his time, the physiologist Jacques Loeb , best known for his “engineering” approach to biology, reflected on the possibilities of artificially creating life in the laboratory. With the objective of experimentally tackling one of the crucial questions of organic evolution, i.e., the origin of life from inanimate matter, he rejected claims made by contemporary scientists of having produced artificial life through osmotic growth processes in inorganic salt solutions. According to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  68
    Left/right, up/down: The role of endogenous electrical fields as directional signals in development, repair and invasion.Kenneth R. Robinson & Mark A. Messerli - 2003 - Bioessays 25 (8):759-766.
    A fundamental aspect of biological systems is their spatial organization. In development, regeneration and repair, directional signals are necessary for the proper placement of the components of the organism. Likewise, pathogens that invade other organisms rely on directional signals to target vulnerable areas. It is widely understood that chemical gradients are important directional signals in living systems. Less well recognized are electrical fields, which can also provide directional information. Small, steady electrical fields can directly guide cell movement and growth (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23.  30
    Formalizing Metabolic-Regulatory Networks by Hybrid Automata.Lin Liu & Alexander Bockmayr - 2019 - Acta Biotheoretica 68 (1):73-85.
    Computational approaches in systems biology have become a powerful tool for understanding the fundamental mechanisms of cellular metabolism and regulation. However, the interplay between the regulatory and the metabolic system is still poorly understood. In particular, there is a need for formal mathematical frameworks that allow analyzing metabolism together with dynamic enzyme resources and regulatory events. Here, we introduce a metabolic-regulatory network model that allows integrating metabolism with transcriptional regulation, macromolecule production and enzyme resources. Using this model, we show that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  33
    Hierarchy, determinism, and specificity in theories of development and evolution.Ute Deichmann - 2017 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 39 (4):33.
    The concepts of hierarchical organization, genetic determinism and biological specificity have played a crucial role in biology as a modern experimental science since its beginnings in the nineteenth century. The idea of genetic information and genetic determination was at the basis of molecular biology that developed in the 1940s with macromolecules, viruses and prokaryotes as major objects of research often labelled “reductionist”. However, the concepts have been marginalized or rejected in some of the research that in the late (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  19
    Nuclear envelope budding: Getting large macromolecular complexes out of the nucleus.Kevin C. Sule, Mitsutoshi Nakamura & Susan M. Parkhurst - 2024 - Bioessays 46 (2):2300182.
    Transport of macromolecules from the nucleus to the cytoplasm is essential for nearly all cellular and developmental events, and when mis‐regulated, is associated with diseases, tumor formation/growth, and cancer progression. Nuclear Envelope (NE)‐budding is a newly appreciated nuclear export pathway for large macromolecular machineries, including those assembled to allow co‐regulation of functionally related components, that bypasses canonical nuclear export through nuclear pores. In this pathway, large macromolecular complexes are enveloped by the inner nuclear membrane, transverse the perinuclear space, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  32
    A process ontology approach in biochemistry: the case of GPCRs and biosignaling.Fiorela Alassia - 2022 - Foundations of Chemistry 24 (3):405-422.
    According to process ontology in the philosophy of biology, the living world is better understood as processes rather than as substantial individuals. Within this perspective, an organism does not consist of a hierarchy of structures like a machine, but rather a dynamic hierarchy of processes, dynamically maintained and stabilized at different time scales. With this respect, two processual approaches on enzymes by Stein (Hyle Int J Philos Chem 10(4):5–22, 2004, Process Stud 34:62–80, 2005, Found Chem 8:3–29, 2006) and by Guttinger (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  22
    Hierarchy, determinism, and specificity in theories of development and evolution.Ute Diechmann - 2017 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 39 (4):33.
    The concepts of hierarchical organization, genetic determinism and biological specificity have played a crucial role in biology as a modern experimental science since its beginnings in the nineteenth century. The idea of genetic information and genetic determination was at the basis of molecular biology that developed in the 1940s with macromolecules, viruses and prokaryotes as major objects of research often labelled “reductionist”. However, the concepts have been marginalized or rejected in some of the research that in the late (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Macromolecular intelligence in microorganisms. [REVIEW]Frank J. Bruggeman, Wally C. Van Heeswijk, Fred Boogerd & Hans V. Westerhoff - 2000 - Biological Chemistry 381:965-972.
    Biochemistry and molecular biology have been focusing on the structural, catalytic, and regulatory proper- ties of individual macromolecules from the perspective of clarifying the mechanisms of metabolism and gene expression. Complete genomes of ‘primitive’ living organisms seem to be substantially larger than necessary for metabolism and gene expression alone. This is in line with the findings of silent phenotypes for supposedly important genes, apparent redundancy of functions, and variegated networks of signal transduction and transcription factors. Here we propose that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  9
    Les secrets du vivant: contre la pensée unique en biologie.Michel Morange - 2005 - Paris: Editions La Découverte.
    Annoncé à grand fracas, le décryptage do génome humain devait nous révéler le secret ultime de la vie et ouvrir la voie à de nouvelles thérapies miracles. Espoirs déçus : à l'ère de la post-génomique, les secrets du vivant sont maintenant recherchés dans les théories de la complexité, dans la convergence des efforts des biologistes, des physiciens et des mathématiciens. Comment comprendre la signification de cette succession rapide d'objectifs apparemment différents, de cette alternance d'espoirs et de désillusions? Dans ce livre (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30. Messy Chemical Kinds.Joyce C. Havstad - 2018 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69 (3):719-743.
    Following Kripke and Putnam, the received view of chemical kinds has been a microstructuralist one. To be a microstructuralist about chemical kinds is to think that membership in said kinds is conferred by microstructural properties. Recently, the received microstructuralist view has been elaborated and defended, but it has also been attacked on the basis of complexities, both chemical and ontological. Here, I look at which complexities really challenge the microstructuralist view; at how the view itself might be made more complicated (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  31.  23
    Structural and functional domains of tubulin.Ricardo B. Maccioni, Luis Serrano & Jesus Avila - 1985 - Bioessays 2 (4):165-169.
    The molecular aspects of the microtubule system is a research area that has developed very rapidly during the past decade. Research on the assembly mechanisms and chemistry of tubulin and the molecular biology of microtubules have advanced our understanding of microtubule formation and its regulation. The emerging view of tubulin is of a macromolecule containing spatially discrete sequences that constitute functionally different domains with respect to self‐association, interactions with microtubule associated proteins (MAPs) and specific ligands. Recent studies point to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  22
    Strengths and opportunities in research into extracellular matrix ageing: A consultation with the ECMage research community.Matthew J. Dalby, Vanja Pekovic-Vaughan, Daryl P. Shanley, Joe Swift, Lisa J. White & Elizabeth G. Canty-Laird - 2024 - Bioessays 46 (5):2300223.
    Ageing causes progressive decline in metabolic, behavioural, and physiological functions, leading to a reduced health span. The extracellular matrix (ECM) is the three‐dimensional network of macromolecules that provides our tissues with structure and biomechanical resilience. Imbalance between damage and repair/regeneration causes the ECM to undergo structural deterioration with age, contributing to age‐associated pathology. The ECM ‘Ageing Across the Life Course’ interdisciplinary research network (ECMage) was established to bring together researchers in the United Kingdom, and internationally, working on the emerging (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  26
    Exploring molecular mechanisms in chemically induced cancer: Complementation of mammalian DNA repair defects by a prokaryotic gene.G. P. Margison, J. Brennand, C. H. Ockey & P. J. O'Connor - 1987 - Bioessays 6 (4):151-156.
    Exposure of man to chemical agents can occur intentionally, as in the treatment of disease, or inadvertently because the environment contains a wide range of synthetic or naturally occurring chemicals. The alkylating agents are a diverse group of compounds (Fig. 1) and comprise a good example of such xenobiotics, since much is known about their occurrence, and their biological effects include carcinogenicity, mutagenicity, toxicity and teratogenicity.Exposure to potentially carcinogenic alkylating agents such as nitrosamines may occur occupationally, from cigarette smoke, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  14
    Striving for atomic resolution in biomolecular topography: The scanning force microscope (SFM).Achim Schaper & Thomas M. Jovin - 1996 - Bioessays 18 (11):925-935.
    The invention in 1986 of scanning force microscopy (SFM) provided a new and powerful tool for the investigation of biological structures. SFM yields a three‐dimensional view at nanometer resolution of the surface topography associated with biological objects. The potential for imaging either macromolecules or biomolecules and cells under native (physiological) conditions is currently being exploited to obtain functional information at the molecular level. In addition, the forces involved in individual bimolecular interactions are being assessed under static and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  28
    Correction to: A process ontology approach in biochemistry: the case of GPCRs and biosignaling.Fiorela Alassia - 2023 - Foundations of Chemistry 25 (1):189-206.
    According to process ontology in the philosophy of biology, the living world is better understood as processes rather than as substantial individuals. Within this perspective, an organism does not consist of a hierarchy of structures like a machine, but rather a dynamic hierarchy of processes, dynamically maintained and stabilized at different time scales. With this respect, two processual approaches on enzymes by Stein (Hyle Int J Philos Chem 10(4):5–22, 2004, Process Stud 34:62–80, 2005, Found Chem 8:3–29, 2006) and by Guttinger (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  88
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy.Gary S. Rosenkrantz (ed.) - 2000 - Philosophy Documentation Center.
    I attempt to define the concept of ‘living organism’. Intuitively, a living organism is a substantial entity with a capacity for certain relevant activities. But biology has discovered that living organisms have a particular compositional or microstructural nature. This nature includes carbon-based macromolecules and water molecules. I argue that such living organisms belong to a natural kind of compound physical object, viz., carbon-based living organism. My definition of a living organism encompasses both the intuitively relevant activities and the empirically (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  42
    Can physicalist antireductionism compute the embryo?Alex Rosenberg - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (4):371.
    It is widely held that (1) there are autonomous levels of organization above that of the macromolecule and that (2) at least sometimes macromolecular processes are best explained in terms of such autonomous kinds. I argue that molecular developmental biology honors neither of these claims, and I show that the only way they can be rendered consistent with a minimal physicalism is through the adoption of controversial claims about causation and explanation which undercut the force of these two antireductionism claims.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  21
    How does oncogene transformation render tumor cells hypersensitive to nutrient deprivation?Gabriel Leprivier & Poul H. Sorensen - 2014 - Bioessays 36 (11):1082-1090.
    Oncogene activation leads to cellular transformation by deregulation of biological processes such as proliferation and metabolism. Paradoxically, this can also sensitize cells to nutrient deprivation, potentially representing an Achilles' heel in early stage tumors. The mechanisms underlying this phenotype include loss of energetic and redox homeostasis as a result of metabolic reprogramming, favoring synthesis of macromolecules. Moreover, an emerging mechanism involving the deregulation of mRNA translation elongation through inhibition of eukaryotic elongation factor 2 kinase (eEF2K) is presented. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  16
    New uses for endothelial cell culture.Una S. Ryan - 1984 - Bioessays 1 (3):114-116.
    Endothelial cells in culture have, in the past, been a valuable but capricious tool to test hypotheses on the role of components of the blood vessel wall in such functions as blood pressure homeostasis, hemostasis, permeability, transport of macromolecules and the processing of circulating biologically active substances. Now techniques are becoming available for raising long‐term, large‐scale cultures that can be maintained reproducibly and without loss of phenotypic characteristics. The outlook for establishing endothelial cell factories invites speculation on some far‐reaching (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  15
    Putting proteins in context.David S. Goodsell - 2012 - Bioessays 34 (9):718-720.
    Graphical AbstractScientific illustrations, such as this cross-section through part of an E. coli cell, can give an impression of the complexity of a cell's interior and of the way its macromolecules are arranged.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  45
    Phototoxicity in live fluorescence microscopy, and how to avoid it.Jaroslav Icha, Michael Weber, Jennifer C. Waters & Caren Norden - 2017 - Bioessays 39 (8):1700003.
    Phototoxicity frequently occurs during live fluorescence microscopy, and its consequences are often underestimated. Damage to cellular macromolecules upon excitation light illumination can impair sample physiology, and even lead to sample death. In this review, we explain how phototoxicity influences live samples, and we highlight that, besides the obvious effects of phototoxicity, there are often subtler consequences of illumination that are imperceptible when only the morphology of samples is examined. Such less apparent manifestations of phototoxicity are equally problematic, and can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  31
    Experiment und Orientierung: Frühe Systeme der in vitro Proteinbiosynthese.Hans-Jörg Rheinberger - 1993 - NTM Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Wissenschaften, Technik und Medizin 1 (1):237-253.
    The history of what we call molecular biology today is not just the story of DNA. Molecular biology emerged from and was supported by a multiplicity of widely scattered, differently embedded, and loosely, if at all connected experimental systems for characterizing living beings to the level of biologically relevant macromolecules. By implementing different modes of technical analysis, these systems created a new space of representation in which the central concepts of molecular biology gradually became articulated. The paper describes the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  11
    The Oparin Hypothesis is a Falling Star.Tonći Kokić - 2023 - Athens Journal of Philosophy 2 (1):39-52.
    The Oparin hypothesis from 1936 was a milestone in the origin of life research, making a model that was at least in part empirically testable, and changing the course of life studies from a long tradition of metaphysics to a scientific domain of investigation. His hypothesis is based on the idea of the prebiotic synthesis of macromolecules as a fundamental step on the road to first life. Although the Oparin hypothesis brought fresh ideas and concepts, in its description of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  45
    Spot the difference: Causal contrasts in scientific diagrams.Raphael Scholl - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 60:77-87.
    An important function of scientific diagrams is to identify causal relationships. This commonly relies on contrasts that highlight the effects of specific difference-makers. However, causal contrast diagrams are not an obvious and easy to recognize category because they appear in many guises. In this paper, four case studies are presented to examine how causal contrast diagrams appear in a wide range of scientific reports, from experimental to observational and even purely theoretical studies. It is shown that causal contrasts can be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. The arbitrariness of the genetic code.Ulrich E. Stegmann - 2004 - Biology and Philosophy 19 (2):205-222.
    The genetic code has been regarded as arbitrary in the sense that the codon-amino acid assignments could be different than they actually are. This general idea has been spelled out differently by previous, often rather implicit accounts of arbitrariness. They have drawn on the frozen accident theory, on evolutionary contingency, on alternative causal pathways, and on the absence of direct stereochemical interactions between codons and amino acids. It has also been suggested that the arbitrariness of the genetic code justifies attributing (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  46. (1 other version)The Importance of Feminist Critique for Contemporary Cell Biology.the Biology Group & Gender Study - 1988 - Hypatia 3 (1):61-76.
    Biology is seen not merely as a privileged oppressor of women but as a co-victim of masculinist social assumptions. We see feminist critique as one of the normative controls that any scientist must perform whenever analyzing data, and we seek to demonstrate what has happened when this control has not been utilized. Narratives of fertilization and sex determination traditionally have been modeled on the cultural patterns of male/female interaction, leading to gender associations being placed on cells and their components. We (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  47.  40
    Transforming Traditions in American Biology, 1880-1915.Jane Maienschein & Regents' Professor President'S. Professor and Parents Association Professor at the School of Life Sciences and Director Center for Biology and Society Jane Maienschein - 1991
  48. Against Biological Determinism the Dialects of Biology Group.Steven P. R. Rose & Dialects of Biology Group - 1981
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  22
    Against Biological Determinism.Steven Peter Russell Rose & Dialectics of Biology Group (eds.) - 1982 - New York, N.Y.: Distributed in the USA by Schocken Books.
  50.  14
    A typology.Biological Naturalism Searle’S. - 2010 - In Jan G. Michel, Dirk Franken & Attila Karakus (eds.), John R. Searle: Thinking about the Real World. Frankfurt: ontos/de Gruyter. pp. 73.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 971