Results for 'Empirical idealism'

956 found
Order:
  1.  54
    Empirical Idealism in Outline.H. W. Wright - 1929 - The Monist 39 (1):45-57.
  2.  46
    Empirical Idealism.V. T. Franks - 2010 - Review of Metaphysics 64 (1):105-127.
  3.  15
    Mind as Behavior and Studies in Empirical Idealism.L. P. Chambers - 1926 - Philosophical Review 35 (3):287.
  4.  29
    Mind as behavior and Studies in empirical idealism.Edgar Arthur Singer - 1924 - New York: AMS Press. Edited by Edgar Arthur Singer.
    And yet when after the lapse of four maturing decades we recall certain passages of this Essay, how can we exonerate Clifford from backsliding Can we even urge ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  47
    Edgar A. Singer, jr., and the aesthetic of empirical idealism.Milton C. Nahm - 1957 - Journal of Philosophy 54 (19):584-594.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Transcendental realism, empirical realism and transcendental idealism.Henry E. Allison - 2006 - Kantian Review 11:1-28.
    This essay argues that the key to understanding Kant's transcendental idealism is to understand the transcendental realism with which he contrasts it. It maintains that the latter is not to be identified with a particular metaphysical thesis, but with the assumption that the proper objects of human cognitions are “objects in general” or “as such,” that is, objects considered simply qua objects of some understanding. Since this appears to conflict with Kant's own characterization of transcendental realism as the view (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  7.  64
    British Idealism and its Empire.William Sweet - 2011 - Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 17 (1):7-36.
    It is generally acknowledged that the British Idealism of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries had a significant influence in the philosophy, politics, and culture of that country. In this study, I argue that it also had a considerable impact throughout much of the English-speaking world, and beyond -- in Canada, Australia, the United States, South Africa, India, and even East Asia. This idealism engaged 'local' philosophical traditions and culture, contributed to them, and sometimes led to 'new' (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  33
    Mind as Behavior and Studies in Empirical Idealism[REVIEW]DeWitt H. Parker - 1925 - Journal of Philosophy 22 (13):353-355.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  23
    Transcendental Idealism, Empirical Realism, and the Completeness Principle.Gordon G. Brittan Jr - 2001 - In Volker Gerhardt, Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Ralph Schumacher (eds.), Kant Und Die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des IX Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. New York: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 541-548.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  19
    The Empire of Idealism.Ian Tregenza & M. Hughes-Warrington - 2011 - Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 17 (1):5-6.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Can't Kant Cognize His Empirical Self? Or, a Problem for (almost) Every Interpretation of the Refutation of Idealism.Andrew Chignell - 2017 - In Andrew Stephenson & Anil Gomes (eds.), Kant and the Philosophy of Mind: Perception, Reason, and the Self. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 138-158.
    Kant seems to think of our own mental states or representations as the primary objects of inner sense. But does he think that these states also inhere in something? And, if so, is that something an empirical substance that is also cognized in inner sense? This chapter provides textual and philosophical grounds for thinking that, although Kant may agree with Hume that the self is not ‘given’ in inner sense exactly, he does think of the self as cognized through (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12.  9
    (1 other version)12. The Postulates of Empirical Thinking in General and the Refutation of Idealism.Paul Guyer - 1999 - In Marcus Willaschek & Georg Mohr (eds.), Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Peeters Press. pp. 297-324.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  11
    (2 other versions)Ii.—Kant's transcendental idealism and empirical realism.C. M. Walsh - 1903 - Mind 12 (4):454-472.
  14.  72
    Kant and Post-Tractarian Wittgenstein: Transcendentalism, Idealism, Illusion.Bernhard Ritter - 2020 - Cham (CH): Palgrave Macmillan.
    This book suggests that to know how Wittgenstein’s post-Tractarian philosophy could have developed from the work of Kant is to know how they relate to each other. The development from the latter to the former is invoked heuristically as a means of interpretation, rather than a historical process or direct influence of Kant on Wittgenstein. Ritter provides a detailed treatment of transcendentalism, idealism, and the concept of illusion in Kant’s and Wittgenstein’s criticism of metaphysics. Notably, it is through the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  47
    Kant's transcendental idealism and empirical realism (II.).C. M. Walsh - 1904 - Mind 13 (49):54-71.
  16.  16
    Is the Kantian Transcendentalism Idealism? Kant's Conceptual Realism.Sergey Katrechko - 2021 - Studies in Transcendental Philosophy 2 (1).
    In my paper I argue, relying on Kantian definitions and conceptual distinctions, the thesis that Kantian transcen-dental philosophy, which he characterizes as a second-order system of transcendental idealism, is not [empirical] idealism, but a form of realism (resp. compatible with empirical realism [A370-1]). As arguments in favor of this “realistic” thesis, I consistently develop a realistic interpretation of the Kant’s concept of appearance (the theory of “two aspects”), as well as of Kantian Copernican revolution, of his (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  15
    John Foster’s phenomenalistic idealism under scrutiny.Dmytro Sepetyi - 2020 - Filosofska Dumka (Philosophical Thought) 2:102-118.
    The article discusses John Foster’s last attempt at refutation of physical realism and defence of phenomenalistic idealism. Main Foster’s arguments against physical realism, the argument from «the problem of perception» and the argument from the inscrutability of intrinsic content of the external reality are scrutinized and found wanting. The argument from «the problem of perception» is shown to fail against «the decompositional view» because it falsely assumes that the perception of an object, if it is mediated by some processes (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Phenomenological Idealism as Method: The Hidden Completeness of Cassirer’s Matrix of the Symbolic.Tobias Endres - 2021 - In Luigi Filieri & Anne Pollok (eds.), The Method of Culture. Ernst Cassirer's Philosophy of Symbolic Forms. Pisa: Editioni ETS. pp. 121-147.
    This paper defends the idea that Cassirer's methodology is idealistic in regard to validity claims and the structuralist views he holds and at the same time empiric in regard to the facts and genealogy of culture. This perspective is best to be unfolded along Cassirer's model of representation. The author does so by showing that Cassirer's triad of symbolic articulation (expressive, presentational, significative) and the triad of symbolic development (mimetic, analogical, symbolic) form a coherent and exhaustive theory of symbolic formation. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  8
    The Logical Incompatibility of Kant's Transcendental Idealism with Any Genuinely Objective Form of Empirical Realism.Michael Wenisch - 2008 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 25 (4):337 - 358.
  20. (1 other version)Neither idealism nor materialism: A reply to Snyder.Avshalom C. Elitzur - 1990 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 303 (2):303-307.
    Lack of distinction between the formalism of quantum mechanics and its various interpretations leads to some popular misrepresentations. As long as none of the interpretations can present an unambiguous empirical validation, their status remains purely philosophical. These arguments are shown to apply to Snyder's claims. Next it is shown that Snyder's critcism does not address the main points in the argument concerning the physical impact of consciousness. The reply concludes with some reflections on methodology in the search for a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  49
    Kant's Transcendental Idealism and Empirical Realism. [REVIEW]Ralph Barton Perry - 1904 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 1 (6):159-160.
  22. Idealism and Anti-idealism in Modern European Thought.Robert Pippin - 2019 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 33 (3):349-367.
    The project from which this essay is drawn is a philosophical engagement with the tradition of anti-Hegelianism in modern European philosophy, a critique that I want to show amounts to an attack on Hegel's version of idealism and ultimately on philosophy as traditionally understood. Idealism, in this tradition, should not be understood as a claim about the mind-dependence of the world, or about a mind-imposed structure in experience, or as a so-called objective idealism, but first and foremost (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  16
    Did Kant Refute Idealism?Edward G. Lawry - 1980 - Idealistic Studies 10 (1):67-75.
    It was certainly Kant’s purpose in the Critique of Pure Reason to find a middle ground between Cartesian rationalism and empirical idealism. One of the difficulties in reading the Critique is trying to follow how Kant can maintain his dual argument—that of transcendental idealism and that of empirical realism—at every point. Perhaps there is no better example of this than the crucial argument refuting idealism. The second edition Refutation is drastically reduced from the first edition (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  20
    Transcendental and Empirical Levels of Moral Realism and Idealism.Frederick Rauscher - 2017 - In Elke Elisabeth Schmidt & Robinson dos Santos (eds.), Realism and Anti-Realism in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. De Gruyter. pp. 3-20.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Transcendental Idealism and Material Reality: Metaphysics of Scientific Objectivity in Husserl, Deleuze, and Kant.Bilge Akbalik - 2018 - Dissertation, University of Memphis
    This dissertation engages critically with the metaphysical implications of the respective transcendentalisms of Husserl, Deleuze, and Kant in an attempt to disclose their largely untapped resources for a renewed consideration of the ability of science to grasp reality as it is in-itself. Chapter 1 examines the metaphysical implications of Husserl’s critique of natural scientific objectivity in his later transcendental philosophy in connection to his early formulations of phenomenological objectivity around the axis of the distinction between metaphysics as the science of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  84
    Manifest Reality: Kant's Idealism and His Realism.Lucy Allais - 2015 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Lucy Allais presents an original interpretation of Kant's transcendental idealism. She argues that his distinction between things in themselves and things as they appear to us has both epistemological and metaphysical components. Kant is committed to a genuine idealism about things as they appear to us, but this is not a phenomenalist idealism. He is committed to the claim that there is an aspect of reality that grounds mind-dependent spatio-temporal objects, and which we cannot cognize, but he (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  27. Varieties of Transcendental Idealism: Kant and Heidegger Thinking Beyond Life.G. Anthony Bruno - 2015 - Idealistic Studies 45 (1):81-102.
    In recent work, William Blattner claims that Heidegger is an empirical realist, but not a transcendental idealist. Blattner argues that, unlike Kant, Heidegger holds that thinking beyond human life warrants no judgment about nature's existence. This poses two problems. One is interpretive: Blattner misreads Kant's conception of the beyond-life as yielding the judgment that nature does not exist, for Kant shares Heidegger's view that such a judgment must lack sense. Another is programmatic: Blattner overstates the gap between Kant's and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  33
    Idealism and Objectivity: Understanding Fichte's Jena Project (review).Janet Roccanova - 1998 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (4):634-636.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Idealism and Objectivity: Understanding Fichte’s Jena Project by Wayne M. MartinJanet RoccanovaWayne M. Martin. Idealism and Objectivity: Understanding Fichte’s Jena Project. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1997. Pp. xvii + 177. Cloth, $45.00.This text claims to present a new interpretation of Fichte’s Jena system. Toward this end the author presents a primary thesis and several secondary theses as alternatives to standard or recent Fichte interpretations. Martin’s main (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Subjectivism, Material Synthesis and Idealism.Dennis Schulting - 2017 - In Kant's Radical Subjectivism: Perspectives on the Transcendental Deduction. London, UK: Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 371-429.
    In this chapter, I show that there is at least one crucial, non-short, argument, which does not involve arguments about spatiotemporality, why Kant’s subjectivism about the possibility of knowledge, argued in the Transcendental Deduction, must lead to idealism. This has to do with the fact that given the implications of the discursivity thesis, namely, that the domain of possible determination of objects is characterised by limitation, judgements of experience can never reach the completely determined individual, i.e. the thing in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Internal Realism: Transcendental Idealism?Curtis Brown - 1988 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1):145-155.
    Idealism is an ontological view, a view about what sorts of things there are in the universe. Idealism holds that what there is depends on our own mental structure and activity. Berkeley of course held that everything was mental; Kant held the more complex view that there was an important distinction between the mental and the physical, but that the structure of the empirical world depended on the activities of minds. Despite radical differences, idealists like Berkeley and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  57
    Making Kant's Empirical Realism Possible.Simon Gurofsky - 2018 - Dissertation, University of Chicago
    Famously, Kant is a transcendental idealist. Yet he also endorses empirical realism, and even boasts that only the transcendental idealist can be an empirical realist. The difficulty of making sense of those commitments together leads many interpreters to begin by attributing to Kant some variant of conventional, subjective idealism. That in turn requires that Kant's empirical realism be at best a merely ersatz or quasi-realism. But that drains Kant's boast of its significance. For any idealist can (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  94
    An empirical investigation of the relationships between ethical beliefs, ethical ideology, political preference and need for closure.Patrick Van Kenhove, Iris Vermeir & Steven Verniers - 2001 - Journal of Business Ethics 32 (4):347-361.
    An analysis is presented of the relationships between consumers ethical beliefs, ethical ideology, Machiavellianism, political preference and the individual difference variable "need for closure". It is based on a representative survey of 286 Belgian respondents. Standard measurement tools of proven reliability and robustness are used to measure ethical beliefs (consumer ethics scale), ethical ideology (ethical positioning), Machiavellianism (Mach IV scale) and need for closure. The analysis finds the following. First, individuals with a high need for closure tend to have beliefs (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  33.  69
    Hegel, Idealism, and Robert Pippin.Kenneth R. Westphal - 1993 - International Philosophical Quarterly 33 (3):263-272.
    In Hegel’s Idealism, Robert Pippin contends that Hegel develops a more adequate version of Fichte’s idealism, where the key to idealism lies in the general thesis that there are conditions presupposed by self-conscious judgments about objects. Focusing on this thesis led post-Kantian German idealists to dismiss Kant’s doctrine that space and time are a priori forms of intuition and to develop views of the autonomy of human reason in terms of thought’s self-determination. While Pippin and I agree (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  84
    Empirical psychology, common sense, and Kant’s empirical markers for moral responsibility.Patrick Frierson - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 39 (4):473-482.
    This paper explains the empirical markers by which Kant thinks that one can identify moral responsibility. After explaining the problem of discerning such markers within a Kantian framework, I briefly explain Kant’s empirical psychology. I then argue that Kant’s empirical markers for moral responsibility—linked to higher faculties of cognition—are not sufficient conditions for moral responsibility, primarily because they are empirical characteristics subject to natural laws. Next, I argue that these markers are not necessary conditions of moral (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  61
    L'Idéalism de Lachelier (review). [REVIEW]Herbert Wallace Schneider - 1963 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 1 (1):112-115.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:112 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Gallie's Peirce and Pragmatism (1952). She believes that the translation of Peirce's theory of the categories into the conceptual framework of British empiricism and naturalism misrepresents Peirce's cosmology which had very peculiar traits--traits which the author associates with the Platonic tradition. She shows in detail how Peirce tried at first (1868) to relate his three categories to the Scotist, Scholastic, concepts of "essence" and "substance," (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  46
    German Idealism In the Context of Light Metaphysics.Klaus Hedwig - 1972 - Idealistic Studies 2 (1):16-38.
    An essential trait distinguishing the history of occidental thought from the leading trends of American and Asian philosophies may be found in a rather curious fact. The entire fabric of development and all progress of European philosophy, emerging and uniting out of numerous components, has always taken place as a kind of regress; that is, as a return to the past which sought in every epoch to ascertain its ancient, Greek origins. Continuity, in this connection, means less the identity of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Empirical Realism and the Great Outdoors: A Critique of Meillassoux.G. Anthony Bruno - 2017 - In Marie-Eve Morin (ed.), Continental Realism and its Discontents. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. pp. 1-15.
    Meillassoux seeks knowledge of transcendental reality, blaming Kant for the ‘correlationist’ proscription of independent access to either thought or being. For Meillassoux, correlationism blocks an account of the meaning of ‘ancestral statements’ regarding reality prior to humans. I examine three charges on which Meillassoux’s argument depends: (1) Kant distorts ancestral statements’ meaning; (2) Kant fallaciously infers causality’s necessity; (3) Kant’s transcendental idealism cannot grasp ‘the great outdoors’. I reject these charges: (1) imposes a Cartesian misreading, hence Meillassoux’s false assumption (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  18
    Anti/Idealism: Re-Interpreting a German Discourse.Juliana Albuquerque & Gert Hofmann (eds.) - 2019 - De Gruyter.
    The late 18th century is characterized by two crucial events: the rise of Goethe as a dominating literary figure and the emergence of Kant’s critical philosophy and its productive reception not only in the philosophical but also literary discourse of the time. While the Tübingen School concreatively adopted Kant’s philosophy as a system of ideas, they also critically responded to its intellectualising impulse by positing the equiprimordiality of world and Self, of art and reason. Adhering to the self-critical impulse of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  11
    Live empirical issues in debates over objectivity in the social sciences.Harold Kincaid - 2020 - Synthese 199 (1-2):1935-1954.
    Questions of objectivity involve many general philosophy of science issues; when directed toward the social sciences, even more complex issues surface about the status of the social sciences, e.g. can they be sciences as are the natural sciences? This paper does not take on this mass of issues directly, but instead argues for more restricted theses, in particular that questions about objectivity in the social sciences are often usefully seen as local empirical issues. I look at arguments around underdetermination, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Kantian Phenomenalism Without Berkeleyan Idealism.Tim Jankowiak - 2017 - Kantian Review 22 (2):205-231.
    Phenomenalist interpretations of Kant are out of fashion. The most common complaint from anti-phenomenalist critics is that a phenomenalist reading of Kant would collapse Kantian idealism into Berkeleyan idealism. This would be unacceptable because Berkeleyan idealism is incompatible with core elements of Kant’s empirical realism. In this paper, I argue that not all phenomenalist readings threaten empirical realism. First, I distinguish several variants of phenomenalism, and then show that Berkeley’s idealism is characterized by his (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  41.  31
    Thomas Carlyle, Scotland's Migrant Philosophers, and Canadian Idealism, c. 1870–1914.Alexander Jordan - 2021 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 19 (1):39-56.
    That the great Scottish man of letters Thomas Carlyle (1795–1881) exercised a formative influence over late-nineteenth- and early-twentieth-century ‘British Idealism’ has long been recognized by historians. Through works such as Sartor Resartus (1833–1834), Heroes and Hero-Worship (1841), Past and Present (1843), and Latter-Day Pamphlets (1850), Carlyle transmitted his ideas regarding the immanence of the divine in nature and man, the infinite character of duty, and the ethical role of the state to a generation of subsequent philosophers. The following article (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  71
    An empirical investigation of the ethics position questionnaire in the people's republic of china.Kylie Redfern - 2004 - Journal of Business Ethics 50 (3):199-210.
    While many studies have investigated the ethical perceptions, ideologies and value systems of the Chinese, few studies have focused on mainland China, and even fewer have examined regional differences within China. This study examines the factor structure of Forsyth's (1980) Ethics Position Questionnaire in a sample of managers from the PRC. According to Forsyth, individual differences in Relativism and Idealism influence judgements of moral issues (Forsyth, 1980). In a sample of 115 managers, results show that two similar constructs to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  43.  78
    From Moral Principles to Political Judgments: The Case for Pragmatic Idealism.Pierre-Étienne Vandamme - 2021 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 8 (2):261-283.
    Political judgments usually combine a normative principle or intuition with an appreciation of empirical facts regarding the achievability of different options and their potential consequences. The interesting question dividing partisans of political idealism and realism is whether these kinds of considerations should be integrated into the normative principles themselves or considered apart. At first sight, if a theorist is concerned with guiding political judgments, non-ideal or realist theorizing can seem more attractive. In this article, however, I argue that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. The Idealist View of Consciousness After Death.Bernardo Kastrup - 2016 - Journal of Consciousness Exploration & Research 7 (11):900-909.
    To make educated guesses about what happens to consciousness upon bodily death, one has to have some understanding of the relationship between body and consciousness during life. This relationship, of course, reflects an ontology. In this brief essay, the tenability of both the physicalist and dualist ontologies will be assessed in view of recent experimental results in physics. The alternative ontology of idealism will then be discussed, which not only can be reconciled with the available empirical evidence, but (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  23
    German Idealism and Tragic Maturity.Shterna Friedman - 2020 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 32 (4):458-492.
    Isaiah Berlin viewed value conflict as tragic, as it requires the sacrifice of some values for others. It is a mark of maturity, he thought, to accept this tragic truth. This view raises certain conceptual problems that can be attributed to Berlin’s subtle departures from the German authors (Kant, Schelling, and Hegel) who originated the doctrine of tragic maturity—figures who had, in turn, transformed the earlier idea that enlightenment is a natural and morally neutral process of maturation. Kant moralized the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Kant's Empirical Realism.Paul Abela - 2002 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Immanuel Kant claims that transcendental idealism yields a form of realism at the empirical level. Polite silence might best describe the reception this assertion has garnered among even sympathetic interpreters. This book challenges that prejudice, offering a controversial presentation and rehabilitation of Kant's empirical realism that places his realist credentials at the centre of the account of representation he offers in the Critique of Pure Reason. This interpretation ranges over the major themes contained in the Analytic of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  47. Is Heidegger a Kantian idealist?William D. Blattner - 1994 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):185 – 201.
    It is argued that Heidegger should be seen as something of a Kantian Idealist. Like Kant, Heidegger distinguishes two standpoints (transcendental and empirical) which we can occupy when we ask the question whether natural things depend on us. He agrees with Kant that from the empirical or human standpoint we are justified in saying that natural things do not depend on us. But in contrast with Kant, Heidegger argues that from the transcendental standpoint we can say neither that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  48.  39
    Kant's Idealism (review).Yolanda Estes - 1998 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (1):143-144.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Kant’s Idealism by Philip J. NeujahrYolanda EstesPhilip J. Neujahr. Kant’s Idealism. Macon, GA: Mercer University Press, 1995. Pp. viii + 134. Paper, $16.00.In Kant’s Idealism, Philip Neujahr contends that the Critique of Pure Reason expresses no distinctively “transcendental” form of idealism. Neujahr disagrees with commentators, such as H. J. Paton and Henry Allison, who attempt to show that the Kantian project is in essence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  40
    Legal Idealism and the Autonomy of Law.Henrik Palmer Olsen & Stuart Toddington - 1999 - Ratio Juris 12 (3):286-310.
    Since Herbert Hart’s “fresh start” encouraged us to interpret legal and political phenomena from an “internal point of view,” and Lon Fuller pointed out the severe constraints upon a conceptually viable construction of this view, jurisprudence has had little choice but to become, methodologically speaking, genuinely and critically sociological. By this, we mean that in breaking with the common-sensical half-truths which produced the imperative or command theory of law, the conceptual problem of modelling the practical rationale of the legal enterprise (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. The World According to Kant - Appearances and Things in Themselves in Critical Idealism.Anja Jauernig - 2021 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    The World According to Kant offers an interpretation of Immanuel Kant’s critical idealism, as developed in the Critique of Pure Reason and associated texts. Critical idealism is understood as an ontological position, which comprises transcendental idealism, empirical realism, and a number of other basic ontological theses. According to Kant, the world, understood as the sum total of everything that has reality, comprises several levels of reality, most importantly, the transcendental level and the empirical level. The (...)
1 — 50 / 956