Results for 'G. Fodor'

925 found
Order:
  1. Setting the first few syntactic parameters: A computational analysis.William G. Sakas & Janet Dean Fodor - 1998 - In Morton Ann Gernsbacher & Sharon J. Derry (eds.), Proceedings of the 20th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Lawerence Erlbaum.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  28
    On the acquisition of syntax: A critique of "contextual generalization.".T. G. Bever, J. A. Fodor & W. Weksel - 1965 - Psychological Review 72 (6):467-482.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3. Still looking for structural complexity effects in the representation of lexical concepts.R. G. De Almeida & J. A. Fodor - 1996 - In Garrison W. Cottrell (ed.), Proceedings of the Eighteenth Annual Conference of The Cognitive Science Society. Lawrence Erlbaum.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  26
    Is linguistics empirical?T. G. Bever, J. A. Fodor & W. Weksel - 1965 - Psychological Review 72 (6):493-500.
  5. The specificity of language skills.Jerry A. Fodor, Thomas G. Bever & Mary Garrett - 1974 - In Jerry Fodor, Bever A., Garrett T. G. & F. M. (eds.), The Psychology of Language: An Introduction to Psycholinguistics and Generative Grammar. Mcgraw-Hill.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   270 citations  
  6. The Psychology of Language: An Introduction to Psycholinguistics and Generative Grammar.Jerry Fodor, Bever A., Garrett T. G. & F. M. - 1974 - Mcgraw-Hill.
  7.  6
    A dolgok természete.Gábor G. Fodor & András Lánczi (eds.) - 2009 - Budapest: Századvég.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  23
    Folk Psychology from the Standpoint of Conceptual Analysis.J. Fodor, Replies In B. Loewer & G. Rey - 1996 - In William T. O'Donohue & Richard F. Kitchener (eds.), The philosophy of psychology. Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage Publications.
  9. Simulating the mind: A technical neuropsychoanalytical approach.D. Dietrich, G. Fodor, G. Zucker & D. Bruckner (eds.) - 2009
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  33
    Bigrams and the Richness of the Stimulus.Xuân-Nga Cao Kam, Iglika Stoyneshka, Lidiya Tornyova, Janet D. Fodor & William G. Sakas - 2008 - Cognitive Science 32 (4):771-787.
    Recent challenges to Chomsky's poverty of the stimulus thesis for language acquisition suggest that children's primary data may carry “indirect evidence” about linguistic constructions despite containing no instances of them. Indirect evidence is claimed to suffice for grammar acquisition, without need for innate knowledge. This article reports experiments based on those of, who demonstrated that a simple bigram language model can induce the correct form of auxiliary inversion in certain complex questions. This article investigates the nature of the indirect evidence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  11.  19
    Multiple Team Membership, Performance, and Confidence in Estimation Tasks.Oana C. Fodor, Petru L. Curşeu & Nicoleta Meslec - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Multiple team membership is a form of work organization extensively used nowadays to flexibly deploy human resources across multiple simultaneous projects. Individual members bring in their cognitive resources in these multiple teams and at the same time use the resources and competencies developed while working together. We test in an experimental study whether working in MTM as compared to a single team yields more individual performance benefits in estimation tasks. Our results fully support the group-to-individual transfer of learning, yet the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  20
    Minority Dissent and Social Acceptance in Collaborative Learning Groups.L. Curşeu Petru, G. L. Schruijer Sandra & C. Fodor Oana - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Referential and quantificational indefinites.Janet Dean Fodor & Ivan A. Sag - 1982 - Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (3):355 - 398.
    The formal semantics that we have proposed for definite and indefinite descriptions analyzes them both as variable-binding operators and as referring terms. It is the referential analysis which makes it possible to account for the facts outlined in Section 2, e.g. for the purely ‘instrumental’ role of the descriptive content; for the appearance of unusually wide scope readings relative to other quantifiers, higher predicates, and island boundaries; for the fact that the island-escaping readings are always equivalent to maximally wide scope (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  14. Flash! Fodor splits the atom.G. Vision - 2001 - Analysis 61 (1):5-10.
    Has Fodor demonstrated conceptual atomism?
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15. Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis.Jerry A. Fodor & Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1988 - Cognition 28 (1-2):3-71.
    This paper explores the difference between Connectionist proposals for cognitive a r c h i t e c t u r e a n d t h e s o r t s o f m o d e l s t hat have traditionally been assum e d i n c o g n i t i v e s c i e n c e . W e c l a i m t h a t t h (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1143 citations  
  16. Could there be a theory of perception?Jerry A. Fodor - 1966 - Journal of Philosophy 63 (June):369-380.
  17. Introduction: a Fodor's guide to cognitive science.Roberto G. de Almeida & Lila Gleitman - 2017 - In Roberto G. De Almeida & Lila R. Gleitman (eds.), On Concepts, Modules, and Language: Cognitive Science at its Core. New York, NY: Oup Usa.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. The red Herring and the pet fish: Why concepts still can't be prototypes.Jerry Fodor & Ernest Lepore - 1996 - Cognition 58 (2):253-70.
    1 There is a Standard Objection to the idea that concepts might be prototypes (or exemplars, or stereotypes): Because they are productive, concepts must be compositional. Prototypes aren't compositional, so concepts can't be prototypes (see, e.g., Margolis, 1994).2 However, two recent papers (Osherson and Smith, 1988; Kamp and Partee, 1995) reconsider this consensus. They suggest that, although the Standard Objection is probably right in the long run, the cases where prototypes fail to exhibit compositionality are relatively exotic and involve phenomena (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  19.  21
    Cognitive science and folk psychology: the right frame of mind.W. F. G. Haselager - 1997 - Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage Publications.
    `Folk Psychology' - our everyday talk of beliefs, desires and mental events - has long been compared with the technical language of `Cognitive Science'. Does folk psychology provide a correct account of the mental causes of our behaviour, or must our everyday terms ultimately be replaced by a language developed from computational models and neurobiology? This broad-ranging book addresses these questions, which lie at the heart of psychology and philosophy. Providing a critical overview of the key literature in the field, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  20.  43
    Edwin W. Miller. On a property of families of sets. English with Polish summary. Sprawozdania z posiedzeń Towarzystwa Naukowego Warszawskiego , Class III, vol. 30 , pp. 31–38. - Ben Dushnik and Miller E. W.. Partially ordered sets. American journal of mathematics, vol. 63 , pp. 600–610. - P. Erdős. Some set-theoretical properties of graphs. Revista, Universidad Nacional de Tucumán, Serie A, Matemáticas y física teórica, vol. 3 , pp. 363–367. - G. Fodor. Proof of a conjecture of P. Erdős. Acta scientiarum mathematicarum, vol. 14 no. 4 , pp. 219–227. - P. Erdős and Rado R.. A partition calculus in set theory. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 62 , pp. 427–489. - P. Erdős and Rado R.. Intersection theorems for systems of sets. The journal of the London Mathematical Society, vol. 35 , pp. 85–90. - A. Hajnal. Some results and problems on set theory. Acta mathematica Academiae Scientiarum Hungaricae, vol. 11 , pp. 277–298. - P. Erdős and Hajnal A.. On a property of families. [REVIEW]James E. Baumgartner - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (2):698-701.
  21.  22
    Fine, Arthur 30 Finley, MI 53 Fishburn, PC 133, 140,151 Fodor. J. 250, 271.R. W. Fogel, J. Foreman-Peck, R. E. Frank, G. Frege, B. S. Frey, B. Friedman, Michael Friedman, Milton Friedman, R. Gagnier & P. Galison - 2001 - In Uskali Mäki (ed.), The Economic World View: Studies in the Ontology of Economics. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  82
    On correlating brain states with psychological states.Carl G. Hedman - 1970 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 48 (2):247-51.
  23. Meaning holism and semantic realism (Reprinted in Callaway 2008, Meaning without Analyticity).H. G. Callaway - 1992 - Dialectica 46 (1):41-59.
    Reconciliation of semantic holism with interpretation of individual expressions is advanced here by means of a relativization of sentence meaning to object language theories viewed as idealizations of belief-systems. Fodor's view of the autonomy of the special sciences is emphasized and this is combined with detailed replies to his recent criticisms of meaning holism. The argument is that the need for empirical evidence requires a holistic approach to meaning. Thus, semantic realism requires semantic holism. -/- .
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Speaking up for Darwin.Ruth G. Millikan - 1990 - In Barry M. Loewer (ed.), Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 151-164.
  25.  32
    Systematicity: Psychological evidence with connectionist implications.S. Phillips & G. S. Halford - unknown
    At root, the systematicity debate over classical versus connectionist explanations for cognitive architecture turns on quantifying the degree to which human cognition is systematic. We introduce into the debate recent psychological data that provides strong support for the purely structure-based generalizations claimed by Fodor and Pylyshyn (1988). We then show, via simulation, that two widely used connectionist models (feedforward and simple recurrent networks) do not capture the same degree of generalization as human subjects. However, we show that this limitation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26. A new lilliputian argument against machine functionalism.William G. Lycan - 1979 - Philosophical Studies 35 (April):279-87.
  27.  21
    On Concepts, Modules, and Language: Cognitive Science at its Core.Roberto G. De Almeida & Lila R. Gleitman (eds.) - 2017 - New York, NY: Oup Usa.
    What are the landmarks of the cognitive revolution? What are the core topics of modern cognitive science? Where is cognitive science heading to? Leading cognitive scientists--Chomsky, Pylyshyn, Gallistel, and others--examine their own work in relation to one of cognitive science's most influential and polemical figures: Jerry Fodor.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  82
    INTERVIEW: Gedacht wird in der Welt, nicht im Kopf.Ruth G. Millikan, Markus Wild & Martin Lenz - 2010 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 58 (6):981-1000.
    This interview deals with the major themes in the work of Ruth Millikan. Her most fundamental idea is that the intentionality of inner and outer representations can be understood in analogy to biological functions. Another innovative feature is the view that thought and language stand parallel to each other. Thirdly, the basic ideas concerning the ontology and the epistemology of concepts are explained. Millikan aims at clarifying her position by contrasting it with Dretske, Fodor, Sellars, and Brandom. Finally, the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  98
    A conflict between language and atomistic information.Corey G. Washington - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (3):397-421.
  30. Jerry Fodor on Non-conceptual Content.Katalin Balog - 2009 - Synthese 167 (3):311 - 320.
    Proponents of non-conceptual content have recruited it for various philosophical jobs. Some epistemologists have suggested that it may play the role of “the given” that Sellars is supposed to have exorcised from philosophy. Some philosophers of mind (e.g., Dretske) have suggested that it plays an important role in the project of naturalizing semantics as a kind of halfway between merely information bearing and possessing conceptual content. Here I will focus on a recent proposal by Jerry Fodor. In a recent (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  31. Language and thought: the nature of mind from G. Frege and J. Fodor to cognitive linguistics.Sofia Miguens - 2004 - In da Silva Soares Augusto (ed.), In Linguagem, Cultura e Cognição: Estudos de Linguística Cognitiva. Almedina.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. "LOT2" by Jerry A. Fodor[REVIEW]Tim Crane - 2009 - The Times Literary Supplement 1.
    In G.K. Chesterton’s The Man who was Thursday, six of the seven anarchists named after different days of the week turn out to be secret policemen. Chesterton’s hero Syme finds himself opposed to not just a disparate group of anarchists, but to the unified forces of authority. A similar thing seems to have happened in recent years to Jerry Fodor. When Fodor published The Language of Thought in 1975 his targets were, as he says, ‘a mixed bag’: reductionists, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Zależność kontekstowa w paradygmacie semantyki kompozycyjnej.Krystian Bogucki - 2018 - Kwartalnik Filozoficzny 46 (3):25 - 48.
    The Principle of Compositionality is the principle stating that the meaning of an expression is a function of (and only of) the meanings of its parts together with the method by which those parts are combined. The paper concerns the relationship between this principle and the phenomenon of context dependence. In a compositional language, it seems, the meaning of an expression depends upon the meanings of its parts in a bottom-up fashion, so some philosophers (e.g. Fodor&Lepore) argued that compositionality (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Biosemantics: an evolutionary theory of thought.Crystal L'Hôte - 2009 - EEO 3 (2).
    Evolutionary theory has an unexpected application in philosophy of mind, where it is used by the so-called biosemantic program—also called the teleosemantic program— to account for the representational capacities of neural states and processes in a way that conforms to an overarching scientific naturalism. Biosemantic theories account for the representational capacities of neural states and processes by appealing in particular to their evolutionary function, as that function is determined by a process of natural selection. As a result, biosemantic theories have (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  45
    Layered Cognitive Networks.Ian J. Thompson - manuscript
    In cognitive psychology there appears to be a creative tension between models that use connections of a network, and models that use rules for symbol manipulation. The idea of a connectionist network goes back to McCulloch & Pitts [1943] and Hebb [1949], and finds recent revival in the `parallel distributed processing' (PDP) models that have been extensively examined in the last few years (see e.g. Rumelhart et al. [1986]). In the intervening years, however, the predominant explanations of psychology have been (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  92
    Too close for comfort? Psychosemantics and the distal.Dan Ryder - unknown
    What makes a mental representation about what it's about? The majority view among naturalists seems to be that representation has something to do with causation, or information, or correlation, or some other related notion. But such "information-based" views (e.g. Fodor, Prinz, Stalnaker, Usher, Mandik, Tye, and lots of other people who gesture towards this kind of theory1) cannot accommodate representation of the distal.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Danto on perception.Sam Rose & Bence Nanay - 2022 - In Jonathan Gilmore & Lydia Goehr (eds.), Blackwell Companion to Arthur Danto. Blackwell. pp. 92-101.
    Jerry Fodor wrote the following assessment of Danto’s importance in 1993: “Danto has done something I’ve been very much wanting to do: namely, reconsider some hard problems in aesthetics in the light of the past 20 years or so of philosophical work on intentionality and representation” (Fodor 1993, p. 41). Fodor is absolutely right: some of Danto’s work could be thought of as the application of some influential ideas about perception that Fodor also shared. The problem (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  27
    [Omnibus Review].James E. Baumgartner - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1):239-240.
    Reviewed Works:Edwin W. Miller, On a Property of Families of Sets.Ben Dushnik, E. W. Miller, Partially Ordered Sets.P. Erdos, Some Set-theoretical Properties of Graphs.G. Fodor, Proof of a Conjecture of P. Erdos.P. Erdos, R. Rado, A Partition Calculus in Set Theory.P. Erdos, R. Rado, Intersection Theorems for Systems of Sets.A. Hajnal, Some Results and Problems on Set Theory.P. Erdos, A. Hajnal, On a Property of Families of Sets.A. Hajnal, Proof of a Conjecture of S. Ruziewicz.P. Erdos, A. Hajnal, R. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Physicalism, Teleology and the Miraculous Coincidence Problem.Jonathan Knowles - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (195):164-181.
    I focus on Fodor’s model of the relationship between special sciences and basic physics, and on a criticism of this model, that it implies that the causal stability of, e.g., the mental in its production of behaviour is nothing short of a miraculous coincidence. David Papineau and Graham Macdonaldendorse this criticism. But it is far less clear than they assume that Fodor’s picture indeed involves coincidences, which in any case their injection of a teleological supplement cannot explain. Papineau’s (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  50
    Thoughts, sentences and cognitive science.Andy Clark - 1988 - Philosophical Psychology 1 (3):263-78.
    Abstract Cognitive Science, it is argued, comprises two distinct projects. One is an Engineering project whose goal is understanding the in?the?head computational activities which ground intelligent behaviour. The other is a Descriptive project whose goal is the mapping of relations between thoughts as ascribed using the (sentential) apparatus of the propositional attitudes. Some theorists (e.g. Fodor, 1987) insist that the two projects are (in a sense to be explained) deeply related. This view is contested, and the consequences of its (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  41. Content, computation, and individuation.Keith Butler - 1998 - Synthese 114 (2):277-92.
    The role of content in computational accounts of cognition is a matter of some controversy. An early prominent view held that the explanatory relevance of content consists in its supervenience on the the formal properties of computational states (see, e.g., Fodor 1980). For reasons that derive from the familiar Twin Earth thought experiments, it is usually thought that if content is to supervene on formal properties, it must be narrow; that is, it must not be the sort of content (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  67
    Realism and folk psychology in the ascription of concepts.Bradley Franks - 1992 - Philosophical Psychology 5 (4):369-390.
    This paper discusses some requirements on a folk-psychological, computational account of concepts. Although most psychological views take the folk-psychological stance that concept-possession requires capacities of both representation and classification, such views lack a philosophical context. In contrast, philosophically motivated views stress one of these capacities at the expense of the other. This paper seeks to provide some philosophical motivation for the (folk-) psychological stance. Philosophical and psychological constraints on a computational level account provide the context for evaluating two theses. The (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  46
    The physiology of desire.Keith Butler - 1992 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 13 (1):69-88.
    I argue, contrary to wide-spread opinion, that belief-desire psychology is likely to reduce smoothly to neuroscientific theory. I therefore reject P.M. Churchland's eliminativism and Fodor's nonreductive materialism. The case for this claim consists in an example reduction of the desire construct to a suitable construct in neuroscience. A brief account of the standard view of intertheoretic reduction is provided at the outset. An analysis of the desire construct in belief-desire psychology is then undertaken. Armed with these tools, the paper (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44. On being systematically connectionist.Lars F. Niklasson & Tim van Gelder - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (3):288-30.
    In 1988 Fodor and Pylyshyn issued a challenge to the newly-popular connectionism: explain the systematicity of cognition without merely implementing a so-called classical architecture. Since that time quite a number of connectionist models have been put forward, either by their designers or by others, as in some measure demonstrating that the challenge can be met (e.g., Pollack, 1988, 1990; Smolensky, 1990; Chalmers, 1990; Niklasson and Sharkey, 1992; Brousse, 1993). Unfortu- nately, it has generally been unclear whether these models actually (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  45.  28
    The automorphism tower of a centerless group without Choice.Itay Kaplan & Saharon Shelah - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (8):799-815.
    For a centerless group G, we can define its automorphism tower. We define G α : G 0 = G, G α+1 = Aut(G α ) and for limit ordinals ${G^{\delta}=\bigcup_{\alpha<\delta}G^{\alpha}}$ . Let τ G be the ordinal when the sequence stabilizes. Thomas’ celebrated theorem says ${\tau_{G}<(2^{|G|})^{+}}$ and more. If we consider Thomas’ proof too set theoretical (using Fodor’s lemma), we have here a more direct proof with little set theory. However, set theoretically we get a parallel theorem without (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  51
    "Narrow"-mindedness breeds inaction.David J. Buller - 1992 - Behavior and Philosophy 20 (1):59-70.
    Discussion of Fodor's doctrine of 'methodological solipsism' and Stich's principle of autonomy' has been concerned to show that these principles are incompatible with psychological theories which appeal to states with content (e.g. beliefs and desires). Concern with these issues, and the subsequent attempt to develop a notion of 'narrow' content which is solipsistic or autonomous, has, I believe, obscured a more fundamental issue: No theory which satisfies these principles would ever be able to explain behavior under descriptions which are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  23
    How to make the World Fit Our Language.Wüliam J. Rapaport - 1981 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 14:1-21.
    Natural languages differ from most formal languages in having a partial, rather than a total, semantic interpretation function; e.g., some noun phrases don't refer. The usual semantics for handling such noun phrases (e.g., Russell, Quine) require syntactic reform. The alternative presented here is semantic expansion, viz., enlarging the range of the interpretaion function to make it total. A specific ontology based on Meinong's Theory of Objects, which can serve as domain on interpretation, is suggested, and related to the work of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  48. Wittgenstein’s Deflationary Account of Reference.Diane Proudfoot & Jack Copeland - 2002 - Language and Communication 22 (3):331-351.
    Traditional accounts hold that reference consists in a relation between the mind and an object; the relation is effected by a mental act and mediated by internal mental contents (internal representations). Contemporary theories as diverse as Fodor’s [Fodor, J.A., 1987. Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA] language of thought hypothesis, Dretske’s [Dretske, F., 1988. Explaining Behaviour: Reasons in a World of Causes. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA] informational semantics and Millikan’s [Millikan, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  52
    The role of the systematicity argument in classicism and connectionism.Kenneth Aizawa - 1997 - In S. O'Nuillain, Paul McKevitt & E. MacAogain (eds.), Two Sciences of Mind. John Benjamins.
    Despite the prominence of the systematicity argument in the debate between Classicists and Connectionists, there is extremely widespread misunderstanding of the nature of the argument. For example, Matthews (1994), has argued that the systematicity argument is a kind of trick, where Niklasson and van Gelder (1994), have claimed that it is obscure. More surprisingly, once one examines the argument carefully, one finds that Fodor, Pylyshyn, and McLaughlin, themselves have not fully understood it. 1 In part as a result of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  7
    O, P.Samuel Guttenplan - 1994 - In Samuel D. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 452–513.
    Ontology is the branch of metaphysics centrally concerned with determining what there is. (The name comes from the present participle of the Greek verb corresponding to the English verb ‘to be’.) Thus, if one asks whether there are numbers and other abstract objects, or whether there are PROPERTIES, one is asking ontological questions. Given the fundamental nature of these questions, ontology plays a part in virtually all areas of philosophical investigation, but it has a specific importance to certain debates within (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 925