Results for 'Hempel-Oppenheim'

950 found
Order:
  1. (1 other version)Studies in the logic of explanation.Carl Gustav Hempel & Paul Oppenheim - 1948 - Philosophy of Science 15 (2):135-175.
    To explain the phenomena in the world of our experience, to answer the question “why?” rather than only the question “what?”, is one of the foremost objectives of all rational inquiry; and especially, scientific research in its various branches strives to go beyond a mere description of its subject matter by providing an explanation of the phenomena it investigates. While there is rather general agreement about this chief objective of science, there exists considerable difference of opinion as to the function (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   722 citations  
  2. (1 other version)A definition of "degree of confirmation".Carl G. Hempel & Paul Oppenheim - 1945 - Philosophy of Science 12 (2):98-115.
    1. The problem. The concept of confirmation of an hypothesis by empirical evidence is of fundamental importance in the methodology of empirical science. For, first of all, a sentence cannot even be considered as expressing an empirical hypothesis at all unless it is theoretically capable of confirmation or disconfirmation, i.e. unless the kind of evidence can be characterized whose occurrence would confirm, or disconfirm, the sentence in question. And secondly, the acceptance or rejection of a sentence which does represent an (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  3. (1 other version)Der Typusbegriff im Lichte der neuen Logik.C. G. Hempel & P. Oppenheim - 1936 - Erkenntnis 6 (1):266-268.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  4. Reply to David L. Miller's comments.Carl G. Hempel & Paul Oppenheim - 1948 - Philosophy of Science 15 (4):350-352.
    Like a number of other authors, Miller uses the term “emergent” interchangeably with “unpredictable” and employs it as a property term, i.e., in contexts of the form “Event E is emergent.” As we showed in our article, however, predictability and unpredictability as well as emergence are relations; they can be predicated of an event only relatively to some body of information. Thus, a lunar eclipse is predictable by means of information including data on the locations and speeds, at some particular (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Der Typusbegriff im Lichte der neuen Logik, Leiden 1936.C. Hempel & P. Oppenheim - 1946 - Kwartalnik Filozoficzny 16 (1):98-100.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  30
    Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel: A Tribute on the Occasion of His Sixty-Fifth Birthday.Donald Davidson, Carl Gustav Hempel & Nicholas Rescher (eds.) - 1970 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    The eminent philosopher of science Carl G. Hempel, Stuart Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University and a Past President of the American Philosophical Association, has had a long and distinguished academic career in the course of which he has been professorial mentor to some of America's most distinguished philosophers. This volume gathers together twelve original papers by Hempel's students and associates into a volume intended to do homage to Hempel on the occasion of his 65th year in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  7. Essays in honor of Carl G. Hempel.Carl G. Hempel, Donald Davidson & Nicholas Rescher (eds.) - 1970 - Dordrecht,: D. Reidel.
    Reminiscences of Peter, by P. Oppenheim.--Natural kinds, by W. V. Quine.--Inductive independence and the paradoxes of confirmation, by J. Hintikka.--Partial entailment as a basis for inductive logic, by W. C. Salmon.--Are there non-deductive logics?, by W. Sellars.--Statistical explanation vs. statistical inference, by R. C. Jeffre--Newcomb's problem and two principles of choice, by R. Nozick.--The meaning of time, by A. Grünbaum.--Lawfulness as mind-dependent, by N. Rescher.--Events and their descriptions: some considerations, by J. Kim.--The individuation of events, by D. Davidson.--On properties, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  8.  9
    Einleitung: 40 Jahre nach Hempel- Oppenheim.Gerhard Schurz - 1990 - In G. Schurz (ed.), Erklären und Verstehen in der Wissenschaft. Vittorio Klostermann. pp. 11-30.
  9.  38
    Systematic power.John G. Kemeny & Paul Oppenheim - 1955 - Philosophy of Science 22 (1):27-33.
    In 1948 Hempel and Oppenheim proposed an explicatum for the concept of systematic power 1, pp. 164–167. Since that time some shortcomings have been found in this first attempt. It is the purpose of this paper to show that one can keep the basic approach of the ‘48 paper, and overcome the known disadvantages by means of changes in the details of the definition. In this improvement certain tools will be used that were not available in 1948.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  22
    Reminiscences of Peter.Paul Oppenheim - 1970 - In Carl G. Hempel, Donald Davidson & Nicholas Rescher (eds.), Essays in honor of Carl G. Hempel. Dordrecht,: D. Reidel. pp. 1--4.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11. Hempel and Oppenheim on explanation.Rolf Eberle, David Kaplan & Richard Montague - 1961 - Philosophy of Science 28 (4):418-428.
    Hempel and Oppenheim, in their paper 'The Logic of Explanation', have offered an analysis of the notion of scientific explanation. The present paper advances considerations in the light of which their analysis seems inadequate. In particular, several theorems are proved with roughly the following content: between almost any theory and almost any singular sentence, certain relations of explainability hold.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  12. H 2 O: Hempel-Helmer-Oppenheim, an Episode in the History of Scientific Philosophy in the 20th Century.Nicholas Rescher - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (2):334 - 360.
    Preface. Almost fifty years ago, in 1948, when I was an undergraduate at Queens College in New York and a student of Carl G. Hempel's, I received from his hands an offprint of his now-classic but then just-published paper “Studies in the Logic of Explanation”, written in collaboration with Paul Oppenheim and then just published in Philosophy of Science.1 This paper greatly impressed me—and I was not alone. We have here one of those unusual publications that sets the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  13.  14
    H20: Hempel-Helmer-Oppenheim.Nicholas Rescher - 1996 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 44 (5):779-806.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14. Hempel und Oppenheim: Der Typusbegriff im Lichte der neuen Logik. Wissenschaftstheoretische Untersuchungen zur Konstitutionsforschung und Psychologie. [REVIEW]Kurt Grelling - 1936 - Erkenntnis 6 (1):266.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  10
    HEMPEL, C. G. and P. OPPENHEIM-Der Typusbegriff im Lichte der neueren Logik. [REVIEW]O. Helmer - 1937 - Mind 46:97.
  16. Hempel, C. G. u. Oppenheim, P., Der Typusbegriff im Lichte der neuen Logik. [REVIEW]E. Hartmann - 1937 - Philosophisches Jahrbuch 50:254-255.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  84
    Hempel Carl G. and Oppenheim Paul. A definition of “degree of confirmation.” Philosophy of science, vol. 12 , pp. 98–115. [REVIEW]Max Black - 1946 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 11 (1):18-19.
  18.  72
    Carl G. Hempel and P. Oppenheim. Der Typusbegriff im Lichte der neuen Logik. A. W. Sijthoff, Leiden 1936, vii + 130 pp. [REVIEW]C. H. Langford & Bertrand Russell - 1937 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 (1):61-61.
  19. Do statistical laws have explanatory efficacy?Samuel E. Gluck - 1955 - Philosophy of Science 22 (1):34-38.
    In "Studies In The Logic Of Explanation" (Philosophy of Science, XV, 1948) Hempel and Oppenheim analyze the basic pattern of scientific explanation. One of the difficult problems which they acknowledge is "whether and how the analysis of explanation can be extended from the case where all general ex- planatory principles invoked are of a strictly universal or 'deterministic' form to the case where explanatory reference is made to statistical hypotheses." It is hoped that the remarks which follow may (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. The Metaphorical Conception of Scientific Explanation: Rereading Mary Hesse.Maria Rentetzi - 2005 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 36 (2):377-391.
    In 1997, five decades after the publication of the landmark Hempel-Oppenheim article "Studies in the Logic of Explanation" Wesley Salmon published Causality and Explanation, a book that re-addresses the issue of scientific explanation. He provided an overview of the basic approaches to scientific explanation, stressed their weaknesses, and offered novel insights. However, he failed to mention Mary Hesse's approach to the topic and analyze her standpoint. This essay brings front and center Hesse's approach to scientific explanation formulated in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  17
    Deskriptions- und Interpretationsprobleme beim psychologischen Erklären.Hans-Georg Bosshardt - 1984 - Analyse & Kritik 6 (2):160-189.
    In this paper, the descriptive information contained in empirical laws is contrasted with common-sense descriptions of situations and behavior. According to the Hempel-Oppenheim-Schema, explanation is, essentially, conceived as a matter of deductive reasoning in which the fact to be explained is subsumed under one (or more) empirically valid generalizations or laws. However, this kind of explanation is necessarily based on intuitive processes of diagnosis and interpretation. It is argued that these intuitive processes enable the scientist to formulate descriptive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Scientific explanation.James Woodward - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (1):41-67.
    Issues concerning scientific explanation have been a focus of philosophical attention from Pre- Socratic times through the modern period. However, recent discussion really begins with the development of the Deductive-Nomological (DN) model. This model has had many advocates (including Popper 1935, 1959, Braithwaite 1953, Gardiner, 1959, Nagel 1961) but unquestionably the most detailed and influential statement is due to Carl Hempel (Hempel 1942, 1965, and Hempel & Oppenheim 1948). These papers and the reaction to them have (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   190 citations  
  23.  37
    La nouvelle casuistique et la naturalisation des normes.Jean-Yves Goffi - 2001 - Philosophiques 28 (1):87-107.
    Il s'agit de déterminer le statut des normes chez les nouveaux casuistes . On indique d'abord quelles sont les circonstances de cette nouvelle casuistique ; on suggère ensuite qu'elle exporte dans le domaine de l'éthique certaines thèses de T. Kuhn, comme le « modèle déductiviste », qu'elle prétend détrôner, s'alimentait au schéma Hempel-Oppenheim de l'explication scientifique. On suggère enfin que les nouveaux casuistes procèdent, de façon plus ou moins radicale, à une naturalisation des normes.It is intented to investigate (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  95
    On the logical conditions of deductive explanation.Jaegwon Kim - 1963 - Philosophy of Science 30 (3):286-291.
    Hempel and Oppenheim have stated in Part III of their paper “Studies in the Logic of Explanation” [2] a set of conditions for deductive explanation. However, their analysis has come under damaging systematic criticisms in a recent paper by Eberle, Kaplan and Montague [1], The principal aim of the present paper is to review the Hempel-Oppenheim analysis and propose a strengthened version of it that avoids the recent criticisms.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  25. Explanation and prediction: A plea for reason.R. B. Angel - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (3):276-282.
    Anyone, today, with even a slight interest in the methodology of science will be aware of the heated debate which has raged in regard to the thesis of the logical symmetry between explanation and prediction, which is entailed by the hypotheticodeductive account of scientific theory. The symmetry thesis, which received its classical exposition in a well-known article by Hempel and Oppenheim [2], has been subject to a steadily growing criticism by several eminent thinkers. My intention, in this article, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  88
    Explanations by mechanisms in the social sciences. Problems, advantages and alternatives.Karl-Dieter Opp - 2005 - Mind and Society 4 (2):163-178.
    This paper discusses various problems of explanations by mechanisms. Two positions are distinguished: the narrow position claims that only explanations by mechanisms are acceptable. It is argued that this position leads to an infinite regress because the discovery of a mechanism must entail the search for other mechanisms etc. Another paradoxical consequence of this postulate is that every successful explanation by mechanisms is unsatisfactory because it generates new ``black box'' explanations. The second – liberal – position that is advanced in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  27. Suppositional Reasoning in Scientific Explanations.Avital Pilpel - 2005 - Dissertation, Columbia University
    To suppose X means to pretend to change one's belief for the sake of the argument to include X. How to do so is a decision problem: of the many ways to modify one's beliefs to include X, one should choose the one that best fits with one's epistemic goals. I examine the role of suppositional reasoning in the evaluation of purported scientific explanations of various sorts, based on Hempel and Oppenheim's deductive-nomological and inductive-statistical explanations. First, I present (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  19
    The Logic of Explanation in Psychoanalysis. [REVIEW]P. K. H. - 1970 - Review of Metaphysics 23 (3):566-567.
    This book about philosophical and methodological problems in psychoanalytic theory is surely one of the best pieces of literature on this subject of recent vintage. The author, a psychiatrist on the faculty of Harvard Medical School, displays considerable logical skill and philosophical sophistication, in addition to the expected familiarity with the psychoanalytic literature. The major purport of the book is a logical and philosophical defense of the claim that psychoanalytic explanations of human behavior--if constructed with proper and adequate regard for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  30
    The Matter of Life: Philosophical Problems of Biology. [REVIEW]M. E. - 1972 - Review of Metaphysics 26 (1):173-175.
    Given the tremendous burst of activity in the philosophy of science during the last quarter century, the number of books by trained philosophers dealing with the logic of biology is surprisingly small. Simon’s book resembles Morton Beckner’s The Biological Way of Thought in its comprehensive ambitions: "trying to discover what, if anything, is distinctive about biological science, its concepts, and its mode of explaining." The most obvious difference of the two books is Simon’s long central chapter on "Theories, Models, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Idealization and Structural Explanation in Physics.Martin King - manuscript
    The focus in the literature on scientific explanation has shifted in recent years towards modelbased approaches. The idea that there are simple and true laws of nature has met with objections from philosophers such as Nancy Cartwright (1983) and Paul Teller (2001), and this has made a strictly Hempelian D-N style explanation largely irrelevant to the explanatory practices of science (Hempel & Oppenheim, 1948). Much of science does not involve subsuming particular events under laws of nature. It is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  61
    Probability, Confirmation, and Simplicity. [REVIEW]J. M. P. - 1966 - Review of Metaphysics 20 (2):385-386.
    As inductive logic and the philosophy of probability theory have become of wider interest, it has become clear that a book of readings in these and related topics would be useful for courses since most of the important articles are scattered and inaccessible. The editors have fashioned an extensive collection of papers in four main areas: the meaning of probability, confirmation theory, simplicity of theories and structures, the justification of induction. Each chapter is preceded by an introduction which sets out (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  35
    (1 other version)Some Remarks on the Logic of Explanation in the Social Sciences.Albrecht Wellmer - 1970 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 4:64-81.
    If one were to write a history of the philosophy of science in the spirit of T. S. Kuhn, one would have to consider the model of scientific explanation which Popper proposed and Hempel and Oppenheim developed to be one of the great paradigms of contemporary analytical philosophy of science. This analogue to the historically important paradigms of the individual sciences seems to me to be justifiable for the following reasons: first, the HempelOppenheim model claims universal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Explanation revisited.David Kaplan - 1961 - Philosophy of Science 28 (4):429-436.
    In 'Hempel and Oppenheim on Explanation', (see preceding article) Eberle, Kaplan, and Montague criticize the analysis of explanation offered by Hempel and Oppenheim in their 'Studies in the Logic of Explanation'. These criticisms are shown to be related to the fact that Hempel and Oppenheim's analysis fails to satisfy simultaneously three newly proposed criteria of adequacy for any analysis of explanation. A new analysis is proposed which satisfies these criteria and thus is immune to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  34.  73
    Nikolay Milkov and Volker Peckhaus, eds. The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism. [REVIEW]Alan Richardson - 2015 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 5 (1):174-77.
    This is an important volume for rounding out our understanding of the origins and dimensions of the logical empiricist project. While the existence of a Berlin wing of logical empiricism—personified principally in Hans Reichenbach and Carl G. Hempel—has been well known, in the recent reappraisal literature the spotlight has been firmly on the Vienna Circle. [...] The essays give an expansive sense of the German-Berlin context of the work of not only Reichenbach and Hempel but also their philosophical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  7
    The Laws of History.Stephan Berry - 2008 - In Aviezer Tucker (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of History and Historiography. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 162–171.
    This chapter contains sections titled: A Systematic Look at Laws in History and Nature The History of the “Laws of History” Current Problems and Debates in History and Neighboring Disciplines References Further Reading.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. Grounding, scientific explanation, and Humean laws.Marc Lange - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 164 (1):255-261.
    It has often been argued that Humean accounts of natural law cannot account for the role played by laws in scientific explanations. Loewer (Philosophical Studies 2012) has offered a new reply to this argument on behalf of Humean accounts—a reply that distinguishes between grounding (which Loewer portrays as underwriting a kind of metaphysical explanation) and scientific explanation. I will argue that Loewer’s reply fails because it cannot accommodate the relation between metaphysical and scientific explanation. This relation also resolves a puzzle (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  37.  41
    Kim on deductive explanation.Charles G. Morgan - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (3):434-439.
    In [2] Hempel and Oppenheim give a definition of “explanation” for a certain formal language. In [1] Eberle, Kaplan, and Montague prove five theorems demonstrating that the Hempel and Oppenheim definition is not restrictive enough. In [3] Kim proposes two further conditions to supplement the Hempel and Oppenheim definition in order to avoid the objections posed in [1]. In this paper it is shown that the definition of Hempel and Oppenheim supplemented by (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  38. The Impact of the Paradigm of Complexity On the Foundational Frameworks of Biology and Cognitive Science.Alvaro Moreno - unknown
    According to the traditional nomological-deductive methodology of physics and chemistry [Hempel and Oppenheim, 1948], explaining a phenomenon means subsuming it under a law. Logic becomes then the glue of explanation and laws the primary explainers. Thus, the scientific study of a system would consist in the development of a logically sound model of it, once the relevant observables (state variables) are identified and the general laws governing their change (expressed as differential equations, state transition rules, maximization/minimization principles,. . (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  39.  67
    Three types of explanation.Brian Cupples - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (3):387-408.
    Several revisions of the Hempel and Oppenheim definition of explanation have been offered in recent years, and none have gone uncriticized in the literature. In the present paper it is argued that the difficulties involved with these attempts are based upon a confusion between three types of explanation, and that Professor David Kaplan's model of S-explanation provides a uniform treatment of all three types.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  75
    The Berlin School of Logical Empiricism and its Legacy.Nicolas Rescher - 2006 - Erkenntnis 64 (3):281-304.
    What has become generally known as the Berlin School of Logical Empiricism constitutes a philosophical movement that was erected on foundations laid by Albert Einstein. His revolutionary work in physics had a profound impact on philosophers interested in scientific issues, prominent among them Paul Oppenheim and Hans Reichenbach, the founding fathers of the school, who joined in viewing him as their hero among philosopher-scientists. Overall the membership of this school falls into three groups. The founding generation was linked by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  41. "How does it work" versus "what are the laws?": Two conceptions of psychological explanation.Robert C. Cummins - 2000 - In Robert A. Wilson & Frank C. Keil (eds.), The Shadows and Shallows of Explanation. MIT Press.
    In the beginning, there was the DN (Deductive Nomological) model of explanation, articulated by Hempel and Oppenheim (1948). According to DN, scientific explanation is subsumption under natural law. Individual events are explained by deducing them from laws together with initial conditions (or boundary conditions), and laws are explained by deriving them from other more fundamental laws, as, for example, the simple pendulum law is derived from Newton's laws of motion.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  42. Explanation in dynamical cognitive science.Joel Walmsley - 2008 - Minds and Machines 18 (3):331-348.
    In this paper, I outline two strands of evidence for the conclusion that the dynamical approach to cognitive science both seeks and provides covering law explanations. Two of the most successful dynamical models—Kelso’s model of rhythmic finger movement and Thelen et al.’s model of infant perseverative reaching—can be seen to provide explanations which conform to the famous explanatory scheme first put forward by Hempel and Oppenheim. In addition, many prominent advocates of the dynamical approach also express the provision (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  43.  35
    Comment on Professor Jeffner's Paper.Colin Wright - 1981 - Religious Studies 17 (2):227 - 232.
    By far the most common term in Professor Jeffner's paper is ‘understanding’, and it is clearly with understanding that he is primarily concerned. However, at the beginning of his paper he talks of understanding and explanation, and at least in the case of his third kind of reality he clearly sees understanding and explanation as intimately related. In this he is surely right. I myself would say that understanding is cognizing a manifold as a single whole in all its internal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Aristotle's Four Becauses.Max Hocutt - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (190):385 - 399.
    What has traditionally been labelled ‘Aristotle's theory of causes’ would be more intelligible if construed as ‘Aristotle's theory of explanations’, where the term ‘explanation’ has substantially the sense of Hempel and Oppenheim, who construe explanations as deductions. For Aristotle, specifying ‘causes’ is constructing demonstrations.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  45.  23
    Hans Reichenbach Papers 1884-1979 1909 - 1953.Hans Reichenbach - unknown
    The Hans Reichenbach Papers comprise published and unpublished manuscripts, lectures, correspondence, photographs, drawings, and related materials from his early student days until his death. The correspondence contains about 9000 pages to and from Reichenbach; it ranges over his entire career. Those with whom Reichenbach maintained lifelong contact include Rudolf Carnap, Ernst Cassirer, Herbert Feigl, Philip Frank, Carl Hempel, Sidney Hook, Paul Oppenheim and Wolfgang Pauli. In addition, there is significant correspondence with von Astor, Bergmann, Bertalanffy, Dingler, Dubislav, Einstein, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  66
    Explaining Things Probabilistically.Wesley C. Salmon - 2001 - The Monist 84 (2):208-217.
    Human beings crave explanations of all sorts of things. If “probabilityis our very guide of life,” then probability must play a crucial role in explanation. There are, of course, many types of explanations, and scientific explanations are no doubt in the minority; nevertheless, they are sometimes enormously important. Carl G. Hempel and Paul Oppenheim’s 1948 classic, “Studies in the Logic of Explanation,” characterized one form of deductive explanation with considerable precision, as well as another, which they dealt with (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  42
    Some Remarks on the Logic of Explanation.Lars Skarsgård - 1958 - Philosophy of Science 25 (3):199 - 207.
    These considerations on Carl G. Hempel's and Paul Oppenheim's lucid article “Studies in the Logic of Explanation'”—LE for short—are an attempt to exploit some of the considerable advances made there. I wish to show how these advances may be incorporated into a technique for the investigation of problems of the philosophy of science, which has been called discourse-analytic. This discipline consists essentially in a technique of examining actual texts provided by specialists, such as physicists, psychologists, historians, etc., the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Readings in analytical philosophy.Hans Regnéll - 1971 - Stockholm,: Läromedelsförlagen.
    Empiricism, semantics, and ontology, by R. Carnap.--Decision and belief in science, by A. Wedberg.--On what there is, by W.V.O. Quine.--Metaphysics in logic, by G.J. Warnock.--Propositions, sentences, and the semantic definition of truth, by A. Pap.--Bertrand Russell's doubts about induction, by P. Edwards.--The logic of explanation, by C.G. Hempel and P. Oppenheim.--One's knowledge of other minds, by A.J. Ayer.--On the interpretation of philosophical texts, by G. Aspelin.--The Cartesian doubt and the Cogito, ergo sum, by K. Marc-Wogau.--Metaphysics, logic and theology, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The Covering Law Model Applied to Dynamical Cognitive Science: A Comment on Joel Walmsley.Raoul Gervais & Erik Weber - 2011 - Minds and Machines 21 (1):33-39.
    In a 2008 paper, Walmsley argued that the explanations employed in the dynamical approach to cognitive science, as exemplified by the Haken, Kelso and Bunz model of rhythmic finger movement, and the model of infant preservative reaching developed by Esther Thelen and her colleagues, conform to Carl Hempel and Paul Oppenheim’s deductive-nomological model of explanation (also known as the covering law model). Although we think Walmsley’s approach is methodologically sound in that it starts with an analysis of scientific (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  50.  51
    War Cäsar ein Großer Mann?Manfred Tietzel - 1979 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 10 (2):320-337.
    Im vorliegenden Beitrag wird versucht, bezogen auf das Beispiel Cäsars, eine wissenschaftstheoretische Kritik der Vorstellung von "historischer Größe" und gleichzeitig eine Korrektur unseres Cäsar-Bildes durch eine historische Erklärungsskizze, wie sie Hempel und Oppenheim vorschlagen, vorzunehmen.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 950