Results for 'I︠A︡n Tokarz︠h︡evsʹkyĭ-Karashevych'

951 found
Order:
  1. Adam Heinrich Müller ritter von Nittersdorf als ökonom, literat, philosoph und kunstkritiker (1779 bis 1829).I︠A︡n Tokarz︠h︡evsʹkyĭ-Karashevych - 1913 - Wien: Gerold & Co..
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  10
    Kyïvsʹki obriï: istoryko-filosofsʹki narysy.V. S. Horsʹkyĭ & Maryna Tkachuk (eds.) - 1997 - Kyïv: Informat︠s︡iĭno-vydavnychyĭ t︠s︡entr Stylos.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  12
    Phywa-pa Chos-kyi-seng-geʼi gsung gces btus dbu tshad kyi yig cha bzhugs so.Phya-Pa Chos-Kyi-Seng-Ge - 2012 - Lhasa: Bod-ljongs Bod-yig-dpe-rnying Dpe-skrun-khang.
    Selection of author's works on Svātantrika Madhyamika philosophy and logic.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Mindreaders: the cognitive basis of "theory of mind".Ian Apperly - 2011 - New York: Psychology Press.
    Introduction -- Evidence from children -- Evidence form infants and non-human animals -- Evidence from neuroimaging and neuropsychology -- Evidence from adults -- The cognitive basis of mindreading -- Elaborating and applying the theory.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  5. (1 other version)The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice.Ian James Kidd & José Medina (eds.) - 2017 - New York: Routledge.
    In the era of information and communication, issues of misinformation and miscommunication are more pressing than ever. _Epistemic injustice - _one of the most important and ground-breaking subjects to have emerged in philosophy in recent years - refers to those forms of unfair treatment that relate to issues of knowledge, understanding, and participation in communicative practices. The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice is an outstanding reference source to the key topics, problems and debates in this exciting subject. The first collection (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  6. The self-vindication of the laboratory sciences.Ian Hacking - 1992 - In Andrew Pickering, Science as practice and culture. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 29--64.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   182 citations  
  7. Visual adaptation and the purpose of perception.Ian Phillips & Chaz Firestone - 2023 - Analysis 83 (3):555-575.
    What is the purpose of perception? And how might the answer to this question help distinguish perception from other mental processes? Block’s landmark book, The.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  8. Healthcare Practice, Epistemic Injustice, and Naturalism.Ian James Kidd & Havi Carel - 2018 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 84:1-23.
    Ill persons suffer from a variety of epistemically-inflected harms and wrongs. Many of these are interpretable as specific forms of what we dub pathocentric epistemic injustices, these being ones that target and track ill persons. We sketch the general forms of pathocentric testimonial and hermeneutical injustice, each of which are pervasive within the experiences of ill persons during their encounters in healthcare contexts and the social world. What’s epistemically unjust might not be only agents, communities and institutions, but the theoretical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  9. Kinds of People: Moving Targets.Ian Hacking - 2007 - In Hacking Ian, Proceedings of the British Academy, Volume 151, 2006 Lectures. pp. 285-318.
  10.  6
    Rigs lam nor buʼi baṅ mdzod kyi sgo brgya ʼbyed paʼi ʼphrul gyi lde mig. Chos-Kyi-Dbaṅ-Phyug & Blo-Gros-Rgya-Mtsho (eds.) - 2012 - Kalimpong, Distt. Darjeeling, West Bengal: Rigpe Dorje Institute.
    Buddhits logical debates according to Kagyudpa school of Tibetan Buddhism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Narysy z istoriï filosofsʹkoï kulʹtury Kyïvsʹkoï Rusi: seredyna XII-seredyna XIII ct.V. S. Horsʹkyĭ - 1993 - Kyïv: Naukova dumka.
  12.  10
    Relihiĭno-filosofsʹka dumka v Kyi︠e︡vo-Mohyli︠a︡nsʹkiĭ akademiï: i︠e︡vropeĭsʹkyĭ kontekst.V. S. Horsʹkyĭ (ed.) - 2002 - Kyïv: Vydavnychyĭ dim "KM Akademi︠a︡".
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Sotsialʹne seredovyshche ta istoryko-filofsʹkyĭ protses.V. S. Horsʹkyĭ - 1969
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  10
    Fenomenolohii︠a︡ mudrosti: dukhovni priorytety ta imperatyvy (sot︠s︡ialʹno-filosofsʹkyĭ kontekst): monohrafii︠a︡.P. M. Lisovsʹkyĭ - 2016 - Kyiv: Vyd-vo NPU imeni M.P. Drahomanova.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Language, truth and reason.Ian Hacking - 1982 - In Martin Hollis & Steven Lukes, Rationality and relativism. Cambridge: MIT Press. pp. 48--66.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  16. Savoir Faire.Ian Rumfitt - 2003 - Journal of Philosophy 100 (3):158-166.
    This paper challenges the linguistic arguments Jason Stanley and Timothy Williamson gave in support of their thesis that knowing how is a species of knowing that.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  17. Perceiving temporal properties.Ian Phillips - 2008 - European Journal of Philosophy 18 (2):176-202.
    Philosophers have long struggled to understand our perceptual experience of temporal properties such as succession, persistence and change. Indeed, strikingly, a number have felt compelled to deny that we enjoy such experience. Philosophical puzzlement arises as a consequence of assuming that, if one experiences succession or temporal structure at all, then one experiences it at a moment. The two leading types of theory of temporal awareness—specious present theories and memory theories—are best understood as attempts to explain how temporal awareness is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  18.  30
    Why is There Philosophy of Mathematics at All?Ian Hacking - 2014 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This truly philosophical book takes us back to fundamentals - the sheer experience of proof, and the enigmatic relation of mathematics to nature. It asks unexpected questions, such as 'what makes mathematics mathematics?', 'where did proof come from and how did it evolve?', and 'how did the distinction between pure and applied mathematics come into being?' In a wide-ranging discussion that is both immersed in the past and unusually attuned to the competing philosophical ideas of contemporary mathematicians, it shows that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  19.  43
    Intellectual Humility: An Introduction to the Philosophy and Science.Ian M. Church & Peter L. Samuelson - 2016 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic. Edited by Peter L. Samuelson.
    Two intellectual vices seem to always tempt us: arrogance and diffidence. Regarding the former, the world is permeated by dogmatism and table-thumping close-mindedness. From politics, to religion, to simple matters of taste, zealots and ideologues all too often define our disagreements, often making debate and dialogue completely intractable. But to the other extreme, given a world with so much pluralism and heated disagreement, intellectual apathy and a prevailing agnosticism can be simply all too alluring. So the need for intellectual humility, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  20. Data Over Dogma: A Brief Introduction to Experimental Philosophy of Religion.Ian M. Church - 2024 - Philosophy Compass 19 (6):1-13.
    Experimental philosophy of religion is the project of taking the tools and resources of the human sciences—especially psychology and cognitive science—and bringing them to bear on issues within philosophy of religion toward explicit philosophical ends. This paper introduces readers to experimental philosophy of religion. §1 explores the contours of experimental philosophy of religion by contrasting it with a few related fields: the psychology of religion and cognitive science of religion, on the one hand, and natural theology, on the other. §2 (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21. Experience of and in Time.Ian Phillips - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (2):131-144.
    How must experience of time be structured in time? In particular, does the following principle, which I will call inheritance, hold: for any temporal property apparently presented in perceptual experience, experience itself has that same temporal property. For instance, if I hear Paul McCartney singing ‘Hey Jude’, must my auditory experience of the ‘Hey’ itself precede my auditory experience of the ‘Jude’, or can the temporal order of these experiences come apart from the order the words are experienced as having? (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  22. Pathocentric epistemic injustice and conceptions of health.Ian James Kidd & Havi Carel - 2019 - In Benjamin R. Sherman & Stacey Goguen, Overcoming Epistemic Injustice: Social and Psychological Perspectives. London: Rowman & Littlefield International. pp. 153-168.
    In this paper, we argue that certain theoretical conceptions of health, particularly those described as ‘biomedical’ or ‘naturalistic’, are viciously epistemically unjust. Drawing on some recent work in vice epistemology, we identity three ways that abstract objects (such as theoretical conceptions, doctrines, or stances) can be legitimately described as epistemically vicious. If this is right, then robust reform of individuals, social systems, and institutions would not be enough to secure epistemic justice: we must reform the deeper conceptions of health that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  23. The Competition Account of Achievement‐Value.Ian D. Dunkle - 2019 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 100 (4):1018-1046.
    A great achievement makes one’s life go better independently of its results, but what makes an achievement great? A simple answer is—its difficulty. I defend this view against recent, pressing objections by interpreting difficulty in terms of competitiveness. Difficulty is determined not by how hard the agent worked for the end but by how hard others would need to do in order to compete. Successfully reaching a goal is a valuable achievement because it is difficult, and it is difficult because (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  24. How are power and unfreedom related.Ian Carter - 2008 - In Cecile Laborde & John Maynor, Republicanism and Political Theory. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 58--82.
  25. Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure of Euclid 's "Elements".Ian Mueller - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (1):57-70.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  26. The Connectives.Ian Humberstone - unknown
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  27. Naive Realism and the Science of (Some) Illusions.Ian Phillips - 2016 - Philosophical Topics 44 (2):353-380.
    Critics have long complained that naive realism cannot adequately account for perceptual illusion. This complaint has a tendency to ally itself with the aspersion that naive realism is hopelessly out of touch with vision science. Here I offer a partial reply to both complaint and aspersion. I do so by showing how careful reflection on a simple, empirically grounded model of illusion reveals heterodox ways of thinking about familiar illusions which are quite congenial to the naive realist.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  28. Depression and the Problem of Absent Desires.Ian Tully - 2017 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 11 (2):1-16.
    I argue that consideration of certain cases of severe depression reveals a problem for desire-based theories of welfare. I first show that depression can result in a person losing her desires and then identify a case wherein it seems right to think that, as a result of very severe depression, the individuals described no longer have any desires whatsoever. I argue that the state these people are in is a state of profound ill-being: their lives are going very poorly for (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  29.  23
    Eckhart, Heidegger, and the imperative of releasement.Ian Alexander Moore - 2019 - Albany: SUNY Press, State University of New York Press.
    In the late Middle Ages the philosopher and mystic Meister Eckhart preached that to know the truth you must be the truth. But how to be the truth? Eckhart's answer comes in the form of an imperative: release yourself, let be. Only then will you be able to understand that the deepest meaning of being is releasement. Only then will you become who you truly are. This book interprets Eckhart's Latin and Middle High German writings under the banner of an (...)
  30.  62
    Concepts and society.Ian Charles Jarvie - 1972 - London,: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
    1 The logic of the situation1 What do the social sciences explain? It is a mistake, to which careless expressions by social scientists often give ...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  31. Truth and Meaning.Ian Rumfitt - 2014 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 88 (1):21-55.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  32. A neuron doctrine in the philosophy of neuroscience.Ian Gold & Daniel Stoljar - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5):809-830.
    It is widely held that a successful theory of the mind will be neuroscientific. In this paper we ask, first, what this claim means, and, secondly, whether it is true. In answer to the first question, we argue that the claim is ambiguous between two views--one plausible but unsubstantive, and one substantive but highly controversial. In answer to the second question, we argue that neither the evidence from neuroscience itself nor from other scientific and philosophical considerations supports the controversial view.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  33. Plural terms : Another variety of reference?Ian Rumfitt - 2005 - In José Luis Bermúdez, Thought, reference, and experience: themes from the philosophy of Gareth Evans. New York : Oxford University Press: Clarendon Press. pp. 84--123.
  34. Content and context: The paratactic theory revisited and revised.Ian Rumfitt - 1993 - Mind 102 (407):429-454.
  35. (2 other versions)Why Does Language Matter to Philosophy?Ian Hacking - 1975 - Linguistics and Philosophy 3 (3):429-436.
  36. What is Frege's "Concept horse Problem" ?Ian Proops - 2013 - In Sullivan Michael Potter and Peter, Wittgenstein's Tractatus: History and Interpretation. Oxford University Press. pp. 76-96.
    I argue that Frege's so-called "concept 'horse' problem" is not one problem but many. When these different sub-problems are distinguished, some emerge as more tractable than others. I argue that, contrary to a widespread scholarly assumption originating with Peter Geach, there is scant evidence that Frege engaged with the general problem of the inexpressibility of logical category distinctions in writings available to Wittgenstein. In consequence, Geach is mistaken in his claim that in the Tractatus Wittgenstein simply accepts from Frege certain (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37. Natural kinds.Ian Hacking - 1990 - In Barret And Gibson, Perspectives on Quine. pp. 129--141.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  38. The participant irrealist at large in the laboratory.Ian Hacking - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (3):277-294.
  39.  58
    Beyond Simulation–Theory and Theory–Theory: Why social cognitive neuroscience should use its own concepts to study “theory of mind”.Ian A. Apperly - 2008 - Cognition 107 (1):266-283.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  40. Truth conditions and communication.Ian Rumfitt - 1995 - Mind 104 (416):827-862.
    The paper addresses itself to the "Homeric struggle" in the theory of meaning between those (e.g., Grice) who try to analyze declarative meaning in terms of an intention to induce a belief and those (e.g., Davidson) for who declarative meaning consists in truth conditions. (The point of departure is Strawson's celebrated discussion of this issue, in his Inaugural Lecture.) I argue that neither style of analysis is satisfactory, and develop a "hybrid" that may be-although what I take from the Gricean (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  41.  7
    Faith in Schools?: Autonomy, Citizenship, and Religious Education in the Liberal State.Ian MacMullen - 2007 - Princeton University Press.
    This is a work of normative political philosophy that seeks to identify the legitimate goals of public education policy in liberal democratic states and the implications of those goals for arguments about public funding and regulation of religious schools. ;The thesis of the first section is that the inferiority of certain types of religious school as instruments of civic education in a pluralist state would not suffice to justify liberal states in a general refusal to fund such schools. States with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  42. The parody of conversation.Ian Hacking - 1986 - In Ernest LePore, Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 447--458.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  43. Kant's first paralogism.Ian Proops - 2010 - Philosophical Review 119 (4):449–495.
    In the part of the first Critique known as “The Paralogisms of Pure Reason” Kant seeks to explain how even the most acute metaphysicians could have arrived, through speculation, at the ruefully dogmatic conclusion that the self (understood as the subject of thoughts or "thinking I") is a substance. His diagnosis has two components: first, the positing of the phenomenon of “Transcendental Illusion”—an illusion, modelled on but distinct from, optical illusion--that predisposes human beings to accept as sound--and as known to (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  44. The Physics of Pneuma in Early Stoicism.Ian Hensley - 2020 - In Sean Coughlin, David Leith & Orly Lewis, The Concept of Pneuma after Aristotle. Berlin: Edition Topoi. pp. 171-201.
    This chapter examines the ancient Stoic theory of the physical composition of pneuma, how its composition relates to pneuma’s many causal roles in Stoic philosophy, and to what extent each of the first three leaders of the Stoic school accepted the claim that pneuma pervades the cosmos. I argue that pneuma is a compound of fire and air. Furthermore, many functions of pneuma can be reduced to the functions of these elements. Finally, it is likely that each of the early (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  20
    Groundwork of Phenomenological Marxism: Crisis, Body, World.Ian H. Angus - 2021 - Lanham, Maryland: Lexington Books.
    This original, contemporary synthesis between phenomenology and Marx’s late work begins from Edmund Husserl’s The Crisis of the European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology to chart a new program for Socratic phenomenology in the current confrontation between planetary technology and place-based Indigeneity.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46. Barbarous Spectacle and General Massacre: A Defence of Gory Fictions.Ian Stoner - 2020 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 37 (4):511-527.
    Many people suspect it is morally wrong to watch the graphically violent horror films colloquially known as gorefests. A prominent argument vindicating this suspicion is the Argument from Reactive Attitudes (ARA). The ARA holds that we have a duty to maintain a well-functioning moral psychology, and watching gorefests violates that duty by threatening damage to our appropriate reactive attitudes. But I argue that the ARA is probably unsound. Depictions of suffering and death in other genres typically do no damage to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  62
    Greek mathematics and Greek logic.Ian Mueller - 1974 - In John Corcoran, Ancient logic and its modern interpretations. Boston,: Reidel. pp. 35--70.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  48. (1 other version)Towards a theory of mathematical argument.Ian J. Dove - 2009 - Foundations of Science 14 (1-2):136-152.
    In this paper, I assume, perhaps controversially, that translation into a language of formal logic is not the method by which mathematicians assess mathematical reasoning. Instead, I argue that the actual practice of analyzing, evaluating and critiquing mathematical reasoning resembles, and perhaps equates with, the practice of informal logic or argumentation theory. It doesn’t matter whether the reasoning is a full-fledged mathematical proof or merely some non-deductive mathematical justification: in either case, the methodology of assessment overlaps to a large extent (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  49. (1 other version)How we have been learning to talk about autism: A role for stories.Ian Hacking - 2009 - Metaphilosophy 40 (3-4):499-516.
    Autism fiction has become a genre of novel‐writing in its own right. Many examples are given in the essay. What does this activity do for us? There used to be no language in which autistic experience could be described. One characteristic difficulty for autistic people is understanding what other people are doing. So absence of a discourse of autistic experience is to be expected. Analyses advanced by Wolfgang Köhler and Lev Vygotsky already made plain long ago that social interaction is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  50. On the Separability and Inseparability of the Stoic Principles.Ian Hensley - 2018 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (2):187-214.
    Sources for Stoicism present conflicting accounts of the Stoic principles. Some suggest that the principles are inseparable from each other. Others suggest that they are separable. To resolve this apparent interpretive dilemma, I distinguish between the functions of the principles and the bodies that realize those functions. Although the principles cannot separate when realizing their roles, the Stoic theory of blending entails that the bodies that realize those roles are physically separable. I present a strategy for further work on the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 951