Results for 'Katherine McGovern'

975 found
Order:
  1. Cognitive theories of consciousness.Katherine McGovern & Bernard J. Baars - 2007 - In Morris Moscovitch, Philip Zelazo & Evan Thompson (eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 177--205.
  2. Success and Knowledge-How.Katherine Hawley - 2003 - American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1):19 - 31.
    In this paper, I argue that there is a notion of 'counterfactual success' which stands to knowledge how as true belief stands to propositional knowledge. (I attempt to avoid the question of whether knowledge how is a type of propositional knowledge.).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   142 citations  
  3. (1 other version)How Things Persist.Katherine Hawley - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (1):230-233.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  4. Scientific Structuralism: Presentation and Representation.Katherine Brading & Elaine Landry - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (5):571-581.
    This paper explores varieties of scientific structuralism. Central to our investigation is the notion of `shared structure'. We begin with a description of mathematical structuralism and use this to point out analogies and disanalogies with scientific structuralism. Our particular focus is the semantic structuralist's attempt to use the notion of shared structure to account for the theory-world connection, this use being crucially important to both the contemporary structural empiricist and realist. We show why minimal scientific structuralism is, at the very (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  5. Epistemic Self-Trust: It's Personal.Katherine Dormandy - 2024 - Episteme 21 (1):34-49.
    What is epistemic self-trust? There is a tension in the way in which prominent accounts answer this question. Many construe epistemic trust in oneself as no more than reliance on our sub-personal cognitive faculties. Yet many accounts – often the same ones – construe epistemic trust in others as a normatively laden attitude directed at persons whom we expect to care about our epistemic needs. Is epistemic self-trust really so different from epistemic trust in others? I argue that it is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6. The epistemic benefits of religious disagreement.Katherine Dormandy - 2020 - Religious Studies 56 (3):390-408.
    Scientific researchers welcome disagreement as a way of furthering epistemic aims. Religious communities, by contrast, tend to regard it as a potential threat to their beliefs. But I argue that religious disagreement can help achieve religious epistemic aims. I do not argue this by comparing science and religion, however. For scientific hypotheses are ideally held with a scholarly neutrality, and my aim is to persuade those who arecommittedto religious beliefs that religious disagreement can be epistemically beneficial for them too.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  7. Science as a Guide to Metaphysics?Katherine Hawley - 2006 - Synthese 149 (3):451-470.
    Analytic metaphysics is in resurgence; there is renewed and vigorous interest in topics such as time, causation, persistence, parthood and possible worlds. We who share this interest often pay lip-service to the idea that metaphysics should be informed by modern science; some take this duty very seriously.2 But there is also a widespread suspicion that science cannot really contribute to metaphysics, and that scientific findings grossly underdetermine metaphysical claims. For some, this prompts the thought ‘so much the worse for metaphysics’; (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  8.  25
    Late Bronze Palestinian Pendants.Harold A. Liebowitz, Patrick E. McGovern & Eric M. Meyers - 1989 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 109 (1):115.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Testimony and knowing how.Katherine Hawley - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (4):397-404.
    Much of what we learn from talking and listening does not qualify as testimonial knowledge: we can learn a great deal from other people without simply accepting what they say as being true. In this article, I examine the ways in which we acquire skills or knowledge how from our interactions with other people, and I discuss whether there is a useful notion of testimonial knowledge how.Keywords: Knowledge how; Practical knowledge; Tacit knowledge; Testimony; Skills; Assertion.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  10. Resolving Religious Disagreements.Katherine Dormandy - 2018 - Faith and Philosophy 35 (1):56-83.
    Resolving religious disagreements is difficult, for beliefs about religion tend to come with strong biases against other views and the people who hold them. Evidence can help, but there is no agreed-upon policy for weighting it, and moreover bias affects the content of our evidence itself. Another complicating factor is that some biases are reliable and others unreliable. What we need is an evidence-weighting policy geared toward negotiating the effects of bias. I consider three evidence-weighting policies in the philosophy of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  11.  65
    True Faith: Against Doxastic Partiality about Faith (in God and Religious Communities) and in Defence of Evidentialism.Katherine Dormandy - 2021 - Australasian Philosophical Review 5 (1):4-28.
    ABSTRACT Is it good to form positive beliefs about those you have faith in, such as God or a religious community? Doxastic partialists say that it is. Some hold that it is good, from the viewpoint of faith, to form positive beliefs about the object of your faith even when your evidence favours negative ones. Others try to maintain respect for evidence by appealing to a highly permissive epistemology. I argue against both forms of doxastic partiality, on the grounds that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  12.  77
    Bodily Influences on Emotional Feelings: Accumulating Evidence and Extensions of William James’s Theory of Emotion.James D. Laird & Katherine Lacasse - 2014 - Emotion Review 6 (1):27-34.
    William James’s theory of emotion has been controversial since its inception, and a basic analysis of Cannon’s critique is provided. Research on the impact of facial expressions, expressive behaviors, and visceral responses on emotional feelings are each reviewed. A good deal of evidence supports James’s theory that these types of bodily feedback, along with perceptions of situational cues, are each important parts of emotional feelings. Extensions to James’s theory are also reviewed, including evidence of individual differences in the effect of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  13. Loving truly: An epistemic approach to the doxastic norms of love.Katherine Dormandy - 2022 - Synthese 200 (3):1-23.
    If you love someone, is it good to believe better of her than epistemic norms allow? The partiality view says that it is: love, on this view, issues norms of belief that clash with epistemic norms. The partiality view is supposedly supported by an analogy between beliefs and actions, by the phenomenology of love, and by the idea that love commits us to the loved one’s good character. I argue that the partiality view is false, and defend what I call (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14. Evidence-Seeking as an Expression of Faith.Katherine Dormandy - 2018 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 92 (3):409-428.
    Faith is often regarded as having a fraught relationship with evidence. Lara Buchak even argues that it entails foregoing evidence, at least when this evidence would influence your decision to act on the proposition in which you have faith. I present a counterexample inspired by the book of Job, in which seeking evidence for the sake of deciding whether to worship God is not only compatible with faith, but is in fact an expression of great faith. One might still think (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  15. Disagreement from the Religious Margins.Katherine Dormandy - 2018 - Res Philosophica 95 (3):371-395.
    Religious communities often discourage disagreement with religious authorities, on the grounds that allowing it would be epistemically detrimental. I argue that this attitude is mistaken, because any social position in a community—including religious authority—comes with epistemic advantages as well as epistemic limitations. I argue that religious communities stand to benefit epistemically by engaging in disagreement with people occupying other social positions. I focus on those at the community’s margins and argue that religious marginalization is apt to yield religiously important insights; (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  16.  57
    Memory for “mean” over “nice”: The influence of threat on children’s face memory.Katherine D. Kinzler & Kristin Shutts - 2008 - Cognition 107 (2):775-783.
  17.  24
    “Frequently Asked Questions” About Genetic Engineering in Farm Animals: A Frame Analysis.Katherine E. Koralesky, Heidi J. S. Tworek, Marina A. G. von Keyserlingk & Daniel M. Weary - 2024 - Food Ethics 9 (1):1-20.
    Calls for public engagement on emerging agricultural technologies, including genetic engineering of farm animals, have resulted in the development of information that people can interact and engage with online, including “Frequently Asked Questions” (FAQs) developed by organizations seeking to inform or influence the debate. We conducted a frame analysis of FAQs webpages about genetic engineering of farm animals developed by different organizations to describe how questions and answers are presented. We categorized FAQs as having a regulatory frame (emphasizing or challenging (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  39
    Shouldn't Dead Be Dead?: The Search for a Uniform Definition of Death.Ariane Lewis, Katherine Cahn-Fuller & Arthur Caplan - 2017 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 45 (1):112-128.
    In 1968, the definition of death in the United States was expanded to include not just death by cardiopulmonary criteria, but also death by neurologic criteria. We explore the way the definition has been modified by the medical and legal communities over the past 50 years and address the medical, legal and ethical controversies associated with the definition at present, with a particular highlight on the Supreme Court of Nevada Case of Aden Hailu.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  19.  19
    "The Lust to Kill" and the Arnhem Land Sorcerer: An Exercise in Integrative Anthropology.Victoria Katherine Burbank - 2000 - Ethos: Journal of the Society for Psychological Anthropology 28 (3):410-444.
  20. Critical Notice of Every Thing Must Go.Katherine Hawley - 2010 - Metascience 19 (2):174-179.
    This is a critical notice of Ladyman and Ross et al's Every Thing Must Go. I argue that they mischaracterise much of so-called 'analytic metaphysics', and that they could have usefully drawn upon the resources of current metaphysics in order to articulate their own views more clearly. The piece appears in a symposium which also includes contributions by Kyle Stanford and Paul Humphreys, with responses from Ladyman and Ross.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  21. Special Relativity, Multiple B-series, and the Passage of Time.Fazekas Katherine - 2016 - American Philosophical Quarterly 53 (3):215-229.
    B- theorists frequently argue that the A- theoretic views are incompatible with the Special Theory of Relativity (STR) and that this is a problem for the A- theoretic views. however, the B- theory needs to be revised in light of implications of STR. in particular, it follows from STR that some events stand in genuine temporal relations to each other while others do not. Consequently, there isn’t a single temporal order of all events. instead, there are multiple B- series. Some (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22. Introduction: What is Ontology for?Katherine Munn - 2008 - In Katherine Munn & Barry Smith (eds.), Applied Ontology: An Introduction. Frankfurt: ontos. pp. 7-19.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  23. Rational Faith: How Faith Construed as Trust Does, and Does Not, Go Beyond Our Evidence.Katherine Dormandy - 2023 - The Monist 106 (1):72-82.
    I argue that faith is a type of trust. It is also part of a relationship in which both parties are called on to be faithful, where faithfulness is a type of trustworthiness. What distinguishes faith relationships from trust relationships is that both parties value the faith relationship intrinsically. I discuss how faith on this account can, and cannot, be rational when it goes beyond a person’s evidence. It turns out that faith has the same rationality conditions as trust, differing (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  28
    Can Psychoanalytic Theories Explain the Pakistani Woman? Intrapsychic Autonomy and Interpersonal Engagement in the Extended Family.Katherine P. Ewing - 1991 - Ethos: Journal of the Society for Psychological Anthropology 19 (2):131-160.
  25.  31
    Toward Neo-Precaution: A New Approach to Applying the Precautionary Principle to Public Health.Kumanan Wilson & Katherine Atkinson - 2017 - American Journal of Bioethics 17 (3):44-46.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  24
    Applying the feminist agrifood systems theory (fast) to U.S. organic, value-added, and non-organic non-value-added farms.Katherine Dentzman, Ryanne Pilgeram & Falin Wilson - 2023 - Agriculture and Human Values 40 (3):1185-1204.
    The population of women farm operators continues to increase in the U.S. That growth, however, is mediated by research showing that women in agriculture experience persistent barriers to equality with men. The Feminist Agriculture Food Theory (FAST) developed by Sach et al. (The Rise of Women Farmers and Sustainable Agriculture, University of Iowa Press, Iowa City, (Sachs et al., The rise of women farmers and sustainable agriculture, University of Iowa Press, 2016) posits that in the face of these barriers, women (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27. N eo-F regeanism and Q uantifier V ariance.Katherine Hawley - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):233-249.
    In his paper in the same volume, Sider argues that, of maximalism and quantifier variance, the latter promises to let us make better sense of neo-Fregeanism. I argue that neo-Fregeans should, and seemingly do, reject quantifier variance. If they must choose between these two options, they should choose maximalism.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  28. Persistence and Determination.Katherine Hawley - 2008 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 62:197-212.
    Roughly speaking, perdurantism is the view that ordinary objects persist through time by having temporal parts, whilst endurantism is the view that they persist by being wholly present at different times. (Speaking less roughly will be important later.) It is often thought that perdurantists have an advantage over endurantists when dealing with objects which appear to coincide temporarily: lumps, statues, cats, tail-complements, bisected brains, repaired ships, and the like. Some cases – personal fission, for example – seem to involve temporary (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29. The development of perceptual grouping biases in infancy: a Japanese-English cross-linguistic study.Katherine A. Yoshida, John R. Iversen, Aniruddh D. Patel, Reiko Mazuka, Hiromi Nito, Judit Gervain & Janet F. Werker - 2010 - Cognition 115 (2):356-361.
    Perceptual grouping has traditionally been thought to be governed by innate, universal principles. However, recent work has found differences in Japanese and English speakers' non-linguistic perceptual grouping, implicating language in non-linguistic perceptual processes (Iversen, Patel, & Ohgushi, 2008). Two experiments test Japanese- and English-learning infants of 5-6 and 7-8 months of age to explore the development of grouping preferences. At 5-6 months, neither the Japanese nor the English infants revealed any systematic perceptual biases. However, by 7-8 months, the same age (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  30. Gatekeeping in Science: Lessons from the Case of Psychology and Neuro-Linguistic Programming.Katherine Dormandy & Bruce Grimley - 2024 - Social Epistemology 38 (3):392-412.
    Gatekeeping, or determining membership of your group, is crucial to science: the moniker ‘scientific’ is a stamp of epistemic quality or even authority. But gatekeeping in science is fraught with dangers. Gatekeepers must exclude bad science, science fraud and pseudoscience, while including the disagreeing viewpoints on which science thrives. This is a difficult tightrope, not least because gatekeeping is a human matter and can be influenced by biases such as groupthink. After spelling out these general tensions around gatekeeping in science, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. How physics flew the philosophers' nest.Katherine Brading - 2021 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 88 (C):312-20.
  32.  28
    Many-to-one and one-to-many associative learning in a naturalistic task.Mark A. McDaniel, Katherine Hannah Nuefeld & Sandra Damico-Nettleton - 2001 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 7 (3):182.
  33. The Annual Review of Women in World Religions.Arvind Sharma & Katherine K. Young - 1995 - Philosophy East and West 45 (3):439-445.
    As a forum for philosophical discourse of religious studies as related to the world's women, the "Annual Review of Women in World Religions" fails. The first three issues display an unfortunately limited approach. Certain articles are promising, but editorial intellectual constraints appear to have circumscribed the philosophical latitude provided to contributors. In spite of the potential of the journal's topic area, it is doubtful it will soon succeed in emerging as a publication with adequate inclusionary liberality and ideal discursive freedom.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Religious Evidentialism.Katherine Dormandy - 2013 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 5 (2):63--86.
    Should religious believers proportion their religious beliefs to their evidence? They should: Religious faith is better, ceteris paribus, when the beliefs accompanying it are evidence-proportioned. I offer two philosophical arguments and a biblical argument. The philosophical arguments conclude that love and trust, two attitudes belonging to faith, are better, ceteris paribus, when accompanied by evidence-proportioned belief, and that so too is the faith in question. The biblical argument concludes that beliefs associated with faith, portrayed in the Hebrew Bible and the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. Argument from Personal Narrative: A Case Study of Rachel Moran's Paid For: My Journey Through Prostitution.Katherine Dormandy - 2016 - Res Philosophica 93 (3):601-620.
    Personal narratives can let us in on aspects of reality which we have not experienced for ourselves, and are thus important sources for philosophical reflection. Yet a venerable tradition in mainstream philosophy has little room for arguments which rely on personal narrative, on the grounds that narratives are particular and testimonial, whereas philosophical arguments should be systematic and transparent. I argue that narrative arguments are an important form of philosophical argument. Their testimonial aspects witness to novel facets of reality, but (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  44
    The Nuffield Council’s green light for genome editing human embryos defies fundamental human rights law.Katherine Drabiak - 2020 - Bioethics 34 (3):223-227.
    In July 2018, the Nuffield Council on Bioethics released the report Genome editing and human reproduction: Social and ethical issues, concluding that human germline modification of human embryos for implantation is not ‘morally unacceptable in itself’ and could be ethically permissible in certain circumstances once the risks of adverse outcomes have been assessed and the procedure appears ‘reasonably safe’. The Nuffield Council set forth two main principles governing anticipated uses and envisions applications that may include health enhancements as a public (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. Social Networks and Social Complexity in Female-bonded Primates.Julia Lehmann, Katherine Andrews & Robin Dunbar - 2010 - In Lehmann Julia, Andrews Katherine & Dunbar Robin (eds.), Social Brain, Distributed Mind. pp. 57.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38. Accessibilism and the Challenge from Implicit Bias.Katherine Puddifoot - 2015 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97 (3):421-434.
    Recent research in social psychology suggests that many beliefs are formed as a result of implicit biases in favour of members of certain groups and against members of other groups. This article argues that beliefs of this sort present a counterexample to accessibilism in epistemology because the position cannot account for how the epistemic status of a belief that is the result of an implicit bias can differ from that of a counterpart belief that is the result of an unbiased (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  44
    Achieving widespread democratic education in the united states: Dewey's ideas reconsidered.Elizabeth Meadows Katherine Blatchford - 2009 - Education and Culture 25 (1):pp. 36-51.
  40.  8
    Tocqueville’s Moderate Penal Reform.Emily Katherine Ferkaluk - 2018 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    This book presents an interpretive analysis of the major themes and purpose of Alexis de Tocqueville’s and Gustave de Beaumont’s first work, On the Penitentiary System, thereby offering new insights into Tocqueville as a moderate liberal statesman. The book explores Tocqueville’s thinking on penitentiaries as the best possible solution to recidivism, his approach to colonial imperialism, and his arguments on moral reformation of prisoners through a close reading of Tocqueville’s first published text. The unifying political concept of all three discussions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  14
    Women’s Attitudes Toward Biomedical Technology for Infertility: The Case for Technological Salience.Richard M. Simon & Katherine M. Johnson - 2012 - Gender and Society 26 (2):261-289.
    Research has consistently revealed gender differences in attitudes toward science and technology. One explanation is that women are more personally affected by particular technologies, so they consider them differently. However, not all women universally experience biomedical technologies. We use the concept of technological salience to address how differences in subjective implications of a technology might explain differences in women’s attitudes toward biotechnology. In a sample of U.S. women from the National Survey of Fertility Barriers, we examine how women with and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  33
    From technician to professional: Integrating spirituality into medical practice.Chad F. Slieper, Katherine Wasson & Lois M. Ramondetta - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):26 – 27.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Socialism in Western Europe at Mid-Century.Katherine S. Van Eerde - forthcoming - Social Research: An International Quarterly.
  44.  22
    INTRODUCTION: Medical-Legal Partnerships: Equity, Evolution, and Evaluation – CORRIGENDUM.Katherine L. Kraschel, James Bhandary-Alexander, Yael Z. Cannon, Vicki W. Girard, Abbe R. Gluck, Jennifer L. Huer & Medha D. Makhlouf - 2024 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 52 (1):208-208.
  45.  48
    Untangling the Promises of Human Genome Editing.Katherine Drabiak - 2018 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 46 (4):991-1009.
    This article traces the rapid progression of policy pertaining to human genome germline modifications using genome editing. It provides an overview of how one fertility physician implemented and advertised experimental techniques as part of his fertility clinic services, examines US law and policy, and assesses the impact of rhetoric influencing global policy and interpretation of the law. This article provides an in-depth examination of the medical rationale driving the acceptance of genome editing human embryos in two contexts: to cure disease (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  40
    The Doxastic Norms of Faith: Reply to Commentators.Katherine Dormandy - 2021 - Australasian Philosophical Review 5 (1):104-115.
    This paper responds to comments on the paper "True Faith: Against Doxastic Partiality about Faith (in God and Religious Communities) and in Defense of Evidentialism" (Australasian Philosophical Review). I begin with some clarifications on faith and its normativity (section 1). I then zero in on doxastic normativity (section 2), where an ideological rift emerges between evidentialism and partialist critiques (section 3). I then discuss evidentialist reason and its relationship to objectivity (section 4), and the sort of norms at issue (section (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. (1 other version)Metaphysical and Historical Claims in The Birth of Tragedy.Katherine Harloe - 2008 - In Manuel Dries (ed.), Nietzsche on Time and History. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 275.
  48.  38
    In response to Ballantyne and Schaefer’s ‘Consent and the ethical duty to participate in health data research’.Nilay Hepgul, Katherine E. Sleeman, Alice M. Firth, Anna Johnston, James T. H. Teo, William Bernal, Richard J. B. Dobson & Irene J. Higginson - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (5):351-352.
    We welcome Ballantyne & Schaefer’s discussion of the issues concerning consent and use of health data for research. In response to their acknowledgement of the need for public debate and discussion, we provide evidence from our own public consultation on this topic.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  29
    The affect disruption hypothesis: The effect of analytic thought on the fluency and appeal of art.Jamin Halberstadt & Katherine Hooton - 2008 - Cognition and Emotion 22 (5):964-976.
  50.  31
    Claude Ollier at Times Square.Raymond Jean & Katherine Passias - 1976 - Substance 5 (13):52.
1 — 50 / 975