Results for 'Mark-Nelson Youngerman'

955 found
Order:
  1.  30
    Hermeneutics of Poetic Sense. [REVIEW]Mark-Nelson Youngerman - 2004 - International Studies in Philosophy 36 (1):331-332.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  60
    The Postmodern Turn. [REVIEW]Mark-Nelson Youngerman - 2003 - International Studies in Philosophy 35 (4):159-162.
  3.  14
    [Book review] the priority of prudence, virtue and natural law in Thomas Aquinas and the implications for modern ethics. [REVIEW]Mark Nelson Daniel - 1994 - In Peter Singer (ed.), Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 401-402.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  8
    Paul Crowther., Critical Aesthetics and Postmodernity.Mark Youngerman - 1996 - International Studies in Philosophy 28 (2):122-124.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  14
    Could there be an Atheistic Political Theology?Mark T. Nelson - 2021 - Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 26 (2):303-327.
    “Only a God can save us.” So says Martin Heidegger in his pessimistic assessment of merely human philosophy’s ability to change the world. The thought is not unique to Heidegger: another thinker who arrived at a similar conclusion was Heidegger’s contemporary and sometime admirer, Carl Schmitt, in his idea of “political theology.” I take up Schmitt’s version of the idea and use it to examine the New Atheism, a relatively recent polemical critique of religion by an informal coalition of English-speaking (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. We Have No Positive Epistemic Duties.Mark T. Nelson - 2010 - Mind 119 (473):83-102.
    In ethics, it is commonly supposed that we have both positive duties and negative duties, things we ought to do and things we ought not to do. Given the many parallels between ethics and epistemology, we might suppose that the same is true in epistemology, and that we have both positive epistemic duties and negative epistemic duties. I argue that this is false; that is, that we have negative epistemic duties, but no positive ones. There are things that we ought (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  7.  87
    Is it Always Fallacious to Derive Values From Facts?Mark T. Nelson - 1995 - Argumentation 9 (4):553-562.
    Charles Pigden has argued for a logical Is/Ought gap on the grounds of the conservativeness of logic. I offer a counter-example which shows that Pigden’s argument is unsound and that there need be no logical gap between Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion. My counter-example is an argument which is logically valid, has only Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion, does not purport to violate the conservativeness of logic, and does not rely on controversial assumptions about Aristotelian biology or 'institutional facts.'.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  8. Morally serious critics of moral intuitions.Mark Nelson - 1999 - Ratio 12 (1):54–79.
    I characterise moral intuitionism as the methodological claim that one may legitimately appeal to moral judgments in the course of moral reasoning even when those judgments are not supported by inference from other judgments. I describe two patterns of criticism of this method: ‘morally unserious’ criticisms, which hold that ‘morality is bunk’, so appeals to moral intuitions are bunk as well; and ‘morally serious’ criticisms, which hold that morality is not bunk, but that appeals to moral intuition are nonetheless misguided. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9. The Priority of Prudence: Virtue and Natural Law in Thomas Aquinas and the Implications for Modern Ethics.Daniel Mark Nelson - 1992 - Pennsylvania State University Press.
    In _The Priority of Prudence_, Daniel Mark Nelson proposes a reappropriation of a moral perspective that focuses on the cardinal virtues of courage, temperance, justice, and prudence. The study aims to recover and rehabilitate the virtue of prudence as a way of resuming a moral conversation that has been stalemated for too long. Nelson's main source for reviving the virtue of prudence is St. Thomas Aquinas's account of the cardinal virtues in the _Summa Theologica_. A primary problem (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10.  21
    Editors' Introduction.Nelson Potter & Mark Timmons - 1998 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 36 (S1):i-i.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Moral realism and program explanation.Mark T. Nelson - 2006 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (3):417 – 428.
    Alexander Miller has recently considered an ingenious extension of Frank Jackson and Philip Pettit's account of 'program explanation' as a way of defending non-reductive naturalist versions of moral realism against Harman's explanatory criticism. Despite the ingenuity of this extension, Miller concludes that program explanation cannot help such moral realists in their attempt to defend moral properties. Specifically, he argues that such moral program explanations are dispensable from an epistemically unlimited point of view. I show that Miller's argument for this negative (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  12.  39
    Commentary: Practical Wisdom and Theory.Mark T. Nelson - 2012 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 21 (3):404-408.
    This paper is an ethical reflection on the real-life case of "Angela", a highly intelligent but severely anorexic young woman who wishes to refuse all but palliative treatment. It is part of CQHE's "Ethics Committees and Consultants at Work" series, in response to the essay, "Starving for Perfection.".
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  44
    Discoveries of the Other. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1998 - International Studies in Philosophy 30 (4):147-148.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  21
    The Institution of Theory. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1996 - International Studies in Philosophy 28 (4):119-121.
  15.  26
    The Persistence of Modernity. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1995 - International Studies in Philosophy 27 (4):149-150.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  45
    Who are the best judges of theistic arguments?Mark T. Nelson - 1996 - Sophia 35 (2):1-12.
    The best judge of the soundness of a philosophical argument is the philosopher with the greatest philosophical aptitude, the deepest knowledge of the relevant subject matter, the most scrupulous character, and a disinterested position with respect to the subject matter. This last feature is important because even a highly intelligent and scrupulous judge may find it hard to reach the right conclusion about a subject in which he or she has a vested interest. When the subject of inquiry is the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  31
    Introduction to Special Issue on the Problem of the Criterion.Mark T. Nelson - 2011 - Philosophical Papers 40 (3):279-283.
    Philosophical Papers, Volume 40, Issue 3, Page 279-283, November 2011.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  40
    (1 other version)Eliminative materialism and substantive commitments.Mark T. Nelson - 1991 - International Philosophical Quarterly (March) 39 (March):39-49.
    This paper is an attempt to bring some order to a classic debate over the mind/body problem. I formulate the dualist, identity, and eliminativist positions and then examine the disagreement between eliminativists and their critics. I show how the apparent impasse between eliminativists and non-eliminativists can be helpfully interpreted in the light of the higher-order debate over methodological versus substantive commitments in philosophy. I argue that non-eliminativist positions can be defended using Roderick Chisholm's defense of what he calls "particularism" in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  74
    What justification could not be.Mark T. Nelson - 2002 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 10 (3):265 – 281.
    I begin by asking the meta-epistemological question, 'What is justification?', analogous to the meta-ethical question, 'What is rightness?' I introduce the possibility of non-cognitivist, naturalist, non-naturalist, and eliminativist answers in meta-epistemology,corresponding to those in meta-ethics. I devote special attention to the naturalistic hypothesis that epistemic justification is identical to probability, showing its antecedent plausibility. I argue that despite this plausibility, justification cannot be identical with probability, under the standard interpretation of the probability calculus, for the simple reason that justification can (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20.  45
    Is/Ought Fallacy.Mark T. Nelson - 2018-05-09 - In Robert Arp, Steven Barbone & Michael Bruce (eds.), Bad Arguments. Wiley. pp. 360–363.
    This chapter focuses on one of the common fallacies in Western philosophy called the 'is/ought fallacy (IOF)'. Some philosophers conclude that the IOF is not a logical problem but an epistemological one, meaning that even if inferences like this one are logically valid, they cannot be used epistemologically to warrant anyone's real‐life moral beliefs. Arguments do not warrant their conclusions unless the premises of those arguments are themselves warranted, and in the real world, they say, no one would ever be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  96
    Utilitarian Eschatology.Mark T. Nelson - 1991 - American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (4):339-47.
    Traditional utilitarianism, when applied, implies a surprising prediction about the future, viz., that all experience of pleasure and pain must end once and for all, or infinitely dwindle. Not only is this implication surprising, it should render utilitarianism unacceptable to persons who hold any of the following theses: that evaluative propositions may not imply descriptive, factual propositions; that evaluative propositions may not imply contingent factual propositions about the future; that there will always exist beings who experience pleasure or pain.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  22. Paley before Hume: How Not to Teach the Design Argument.Mark T. Nelson - 2024 - American Philosophical Association Studies on Teaching Philosophy 24 (1):2-10.
    Abstract: “Paley before Hume: How Not to Teach the Design Argument” Most philosophy of religion classes discuss the classic design argument for the existence of God, and many of these treat Paley’s Natural Theology (1802) before Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1779). Following the syllabus of several leading anthologies, I did this for many years, but I now think that is a mistake, because it creates the impression that Hume was responding to Paley. Not only is it obvious on chronological (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  28
    The Hermeneutics of Postmodernity. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1991 - International Studies in Philosophy 23 (3):131-131.
  24.  94
    Intuitionism and subjectivism.Mark T. Nelson - 1991 - Metaphilosophy 22 (1-2):115-121.
    I define ethical intuitionism as the view that it is appropriate to appeal to inferentially unsupported moral beliefs in the course of moral reasoning. I mention four common objections to this view, including the view that all such appeals to intuitionism collapse into “subjectivism”, i.e., that they make truth in ethical theory depend on what people believe. I defend intuitionism from versions of this criticism expressed by R.M. Hare and Peter Singer.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  21
    Conjoined Twins of Malta.Mark S. Latkovic & Timothy A. Nelson - 2001 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 1 (4):585-614.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  33
    Prefaces to the Diaphora. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1993 - International Studies in Philosophy 25 (3):106-107.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. More bad news for the logical autonomy of ethics.Mark T. Nelson - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):203-216.
    Are there good arguments from Is to Ought? Toomas Karmo has claimed that there are trivially valid arguments from Is to Ought, but no sound ones. I call into question some key elements of Karmo’s argument for the “logical autonomy of ethics”, and show that attempts to use it as part of an overall case for moral skepticism would be self-defeating.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28. The Fourth Meditation1.Alan Nelson, Ram Neta, Nelson Pike & Mark van Roojen - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (3):559-591.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  32
    Conjoined Twins of Malta.Mark S. Latkovic & M. D. Nelson - 2001 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 1 (4):585-614.
  30.  18
    Knowledge and Evidence. [REVIEW]Mark T. Nelson - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly 43 (171):242-244.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  31.  87
    An aristotelian business ethics?Mark T. Nelson - 1998 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 15 (1):89–104.
    Elaine Sternberg's Just Business is one of the first book-length Aristotelian treatments of business ethics. It is Aristotelian in the sense that Sternberg begins by defining the nature of business in order to identify its end, and, thence, normative principles to regulate it. According to Sternberg, the nature of business is 'the selling of goods or services in order to maximise long-term owner value', therefore all business behaviour must be evaluated with reference to the maximisation of long-term owner value, constrained (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  52
    Andrew J. McKenna., Violence and Difference: Girard, Derrida, and Deconstruction.Andrew J. Mckenna & Mark Youngerman - 1994 - International Studies in Philosophy 26 (4):149-150.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  33
    Lunar Voices. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 2000 - International Studies in Philosophy 32 (2):148-149.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  20
    Reading the Postmodern Polity. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1994 - International Studies in Philosophy 26 (1):134-135.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  87
    Who Needs Valid Moral Arguments?Mark T. Nelson - 2003 - Argumentation 17 (1):35-42.
    Why have so many philosophers agonised over the possibility of valid arguments from factual premises to moral conclusions? I suggest that they have done so, because of worries over a sceptical argument that has as one of its premises, `All moral knowledge must be non-inferential, or, if inferential, based on valid arguments or strong inductive arguments from factual premises'. I argue that this premise is false.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36.  61
    Bald Lies.Mark Nelson - 1996 - Cogito 10 (3):235-237.
    I present a short, informal vignette that poses the question of whether altering one's appearance by wearing a wig counts as deception, since in both cases one (apparently) tries to bring about false beliefs in others. The bald-headed wig-wearer tries to get others to believe falsely that he has a thick head of hair. If deception is generally wrong, why isn't wig-wearing wrong also?
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Y and Z Are Not Off the Hook: The Survival Lottery Made Fairer.Mark T. Nelson - 2010 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 35 (4):396-401.
    In this article I show that the argument in John Harris's famous "Survival Lottery" paper cannot be right. Even if we grant Harris's assumptions—of the justifiability of such a lottery, the correctness of maximizing consequentialism, the indistinguishability between killing and letting die, the practical and political feasibility of such a scheme—the argument still will not yield the conclusion that Harris wants. On his own terms, the medically needy should be less favored (and more vulnerable to being killed), than Harris suggests.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. A problem for conservatism.Mark T. Nelson - 2009 - Analysis 69 (4):620-630.
    I present a problem for a prominent kind of conservatism, viz., the combination of traditional moral & religious values, patriotic nationalism, and libertarian capitalism. The problem is that these elements sometimes conflict. In particular, I show how libertarian capitalism and patriotic nationalism conflict via a scenario in which the thing that libertarian capitalists love – unregulated market activity – threatens what American patriots love – a strong, independent America. Unrestricted libertarian rights to buy and sell land would permit the sale (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  66
    On the lack of ‘true philosophic spirit’ in Aquinas: Commitment V. tracking in philosophic method.Mark T. Nelson - 2001 - Philosophy 76 (2):283-296.
    Bertrand Russell famously disparaged Thomas Aquinas as having ‘little of the true philosophic spirit’, because ‘he does not, like the Platonic Socrates, set out to follow wherever the argument may lead.’ Like many of Russell's pronouncements, this is breathtakingly supercilious and unfair. Still, even an enthusiastic admirer of Aquinas may worry that there is something in it, that there is something wrong with religious ‘commitments’ in philosophy. I examine Russell's objection by comparing standards of permissibility in epistemology with standards of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  8
    Kant's Methaphysics of Morals.Nelson T. Potter & Mark Timmons - 1998 - University of Memphis, Dept. Of Philosophy.
  41.  28
    Morality and Universality.Nelson T. Potter & Mark Timmons - 1989 - Noûs 23 (4):555-557.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. Non-contradiction: Oh Yeah and So What?Mark T. Nelson - 2013 - Think 12 (34):87-91.
    The logical Law of Non-contradiction – that a proposition cannot be both true and false – enjoys a special, perhaps uniquely privileged, status in philosophy. Most philosophers think that finding a contradiction – the assertion of both P and not-P – in one's reasoning is the best possible evidence that something has gone wrong, the ultimate refutation of a position. But why should this be so? What reason do we have to believe it? In this paper, I address these questions.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  67
    Intuitionism and conservatism.Mark T. Nelson - 1990 - Metaphilosophy 21 (3):282-293.
    I define ethical intuitionism as the view that it is appropriate to appeal to inferentially unsupported moral beliefs in the course of moral reasoning. I mention four common objections to this view, including the view that all such appeals to intuition make ethical theory politically and noetically conservative. I defend intuitionism from versions of this criticism expressed by R.B. Brandt, R.M. Hare and Richard Miller.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. Absolutism, Utilitarianism and Agent-Relative Constraints.Mark T. Nelson - 2022 - International Philosophical Quarterly 62 (2):243-252.
    Absolutism—the idea that some kinds of acts are absolutely wrong and must never be done—plays an important role in medical ethics. Nicholas Denyer has defended it from some influential consequentialist critics who have alleged that absolutism is committed to “agent-relative constraints” and therefore intolerably complex and messy. Denyer ingeniously argues that, if there are problems with agent-relative constraints, then they are problems for consequentialism, since it contains agent-relative constraints, too. I show that, despite its ingenuity, Denyer’s argument does not succeed. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. What the Utilitarian Cannot Think.Mark T. Nelson - 2015 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (4):717-729.
    I argue that utilitarianism cannot accommodate a basic sort of moral judgment that many people want to make. I raise a real-life example of shockingly bad behavior and ask what can the utilitarian say about it. I concede that the utilitarian can say that this behavior caused pain to the victim; that pain is bad; that the agent’s behavior was impermissible; even that the agent’s treatment of the victim was vicious. However, there is still one thing the utilitarian cannot say, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  37
    Redeeming the Time.Mark Nelson - 1995 - The Personalist Forum 11 (1):17-32.
    I borrow an idea from the fiction of C. S. Lewis that future outcomes may affect the value of past events. I then defend this idea via the concept of a “temporal whole”, and show its promise as a partial theodicy and its resonance with both Christian theism and a robust personalism.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. The Priority of Prudence: Virtue and Natural Law in Thomas Aquinas and the Implications for Modern Ethics.Daniel Mark NELSON [[sic]] - 1992
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Robert Audi and the Method of Descriptive Manifestation. [REVIEW]Mark T. Nelson - 2003 - Philosophical Books 44 (1).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Sinnott–Armstrong's Moral Scepticism.Mark T. Nelson - 2003 - Ratio 16 (1):63-82.
    Walter Sinnott-Armstrong’s recent defence of moral scepticism raises the debate to a new level, but I argue that it is unsatisfactory because of problems with its assumption of global scepticism, with its use of the Sceptical Hypothesis Argument, and with its use of the idea of contrast classes and the correlative distinction between ‘everyday’ justification and ‘philosophical’ justification. I draw on Chisholm’s treatment of the Problem of the Criterion to show that my claim that I know that, e.g., baby-torture is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. Promises and Material Conditionals.Mark T. Nelson - 1993 - Teaching Philosophy 16 (2):155-156.
    Some beginning logic students find it hard to understand why a material conditional is true when its antecedent is false. I draw an analogy between conditional statements and conditional promises (especially between true conditional statements and unbroken conditional promises) that makes this point of logic less counter-intuitive.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 955