Results for 'Mirja Johanson'

94 found
Order:
  1.  33
    Level and contents of consciousness in connection with partial epileptic seizures.Mirja Johanson, Antii Revonsuo, John Chaplin & Jan-Eric Wedlund - 2003 - Epilepsy and Behavior 4 (3):279-285.
  2. The zombies among us: Consciousness and automatic behaviour.Antti Revonsuo, Mirja Johanson, Jan-Eric Wedlund & John Chaplin - 2000 - In Yves Rossetti, Beyond Dissociation: Interaction Between Dissociated Implicit and Explicit Processing. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  60
    Apuleius and the Square of Opposition.Carmen Johanson & David Londey - 1984 - Phronesis 29 (2):165-173.
  4.  25
    Husserl and Mathematics.Mirja Hartimo - 2021 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    Husserl and Mathematics explains the development of Husserl's phenomenological method in the context of his engagement in modern mathematics and its foundations. Drawing on his correspondence and other written sources, Mirja Hartimo details Husserl's knowledge of a wide range of perspectives on the foundations of mathematics, including those of Hilbert, Brouwer and Weyl, as well as his awareness of the new developments in the subject during the 1930s. Hartimo examines how Husserl's philosophical views responded to these changes, and offers (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5.  6
    Principia Practica: The Logic of Practice.Arnold A. Johanson - 2000 - Upa.
    Principa Practica is a provocative work in which author Arnold Johanson maintains that philosophers since Socrates have been asking the wrong questions, like "What is good?" and "What is right?" The reason for this, according to the author, is that moral philosophers have based their work on a logical framework more suitable to science than to ethics and politics. Striking out in a new direction, the author bases his work on the concept of requirement which he finds not only (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  46
    Imperative logic as based on a Galois connection.Arnold Johanson - 1988 - Theoria 54 (1):1-24.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  37
    What Does Children's Spatial Language Reveal About Spatial Concepts? Evidence From the Use of Containment Expressions.Megan Johanson & Anna Papafragou - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (5):881-910.
    Children's overextensions of spatial language are often taken to reveal spatial biases. However, it is unclear whether extension patterns should be attributed to children's overly general spatial concepts or to a narrower notion of conceptual similarity allowing metaphor‐like extensions. We describe a previously unnoticed extension of spatial expressions and use a novel method to determine its origins. English‐ and Greek‐speaking 4‐ and 5‐year‐olds used containment expressions (e.g., Englishinto, Greekmesa) for events where an object moved into another object but extended such (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  59
    A proof of Hume's separation thesis based on a formal system for descriptive and normative statements.Arnold A. Johanson - 1973 - Theory and Decision 3 (4):339-350.
  9.  13
    A unified Turkic script system: A short note on the sudden end of a long dream.Lars Johanson - 2009 - In Hendrik Fenz, Strukturelle Zwänge – Persönliche Freiheiten: Osmanen, Türken, Muslime: Reflexionen Zu Gesellschaftlichen Umbrüchen. Gedenkband Zu Ehren Petra Kapperts. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 211-218.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  95
    Bergson e a busca metódica do tempo perdido.Izilda Johanson - 2004 - Trans/Form/Ação 27 (2):21-29.
    Tendo como ponto de referência o pensamento de Henri Bergson e, a partir dele, a relação de identidade entre liberdade e criação, ação livre e ação criadora, este trabalho tem como propósito levantar algumas questões relativas à função do método em relação a uma filosofia que encara a arte, o artista e a atividade artística como exemplos de que o conhecimento acerca do real e do verdadeiro é possível e, justamente em virtude disso, os toma como paradigmas da própria filosofia. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  17
    Cicero On Propositions: Academica Ii.95.Carmen Johanson & David Londey - 1988 - Mnemosyne 41 (3-4):325-332.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Ethics, human adaptation, and social bond.A. Johanson & R. Puligand - 1972 - Journal of Thought 7 (1):7-18.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  39
    O não lugar como lugar da experiência.Izilda Johanson - 2017 - Trans/Form/Ação 40 (2):89-102.
    Resumo: Um dos principais temas postos pela filosofia bergsoniana, no âmbito da subjetividade, é o da distinção entre consciência interior e exterior, entre uma interioridade, um eu interior, profundo, e uma exterioridade, um eu superficial, periférico. Ainda que o lugar seja, em princípio, algo pertinente apenas a um dos dois polos do eu - a saber, aquele relativo à exterioridade, à extensão e ao espaço -, a discussão acerca da natureza própria da interioridade reconfigura a ideia de lugar, no pensamento (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Outro sem eu? Por uma filosofia não identitária, feminista, global e pluriversal.Izilda Johanson - 2024 - Trans/Form/Ação 47 (2):e02400288.
    The paper aims to investigate the relationship between knowledge production and coloniality, guided by the question of alterity in the epistemological context of modern subjectivity. Seeking to understand how the relationship between subjectivity and identity (or sameness) occurs, consequently, between objectivity and alterity (or otherness) in modernity, we will seek to critically answer questions essential to philosophical practice in contemporaneity: a) what does the counterpart of the “I” consist of in this philosophy more consecrated among us and for whom the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  56
    O tempo musical da consciência: pensamento e invenção na filosofia de Henri Bergson.Izilda Johanson - 2007 - Discurso 37:261-280.
    Em sonsonância com a arte de seu tempo, o esforço de criação, sob a perspectiva bergsoniana, se constitui em meio a uma elaboração material, corporal, relacionada, por sua vez, a uma construção musical. A noção bergsoniana de tempo musical como produção criadora diz respeito, assim, a um meio particular de conhecimento: a intuição. Ela se desdobra, no caso da arte, em obra e, na filosofia, em metafísica.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  14
    Por uma metafísica selvagem ou sobre Bergson a partir de Lévi-Strauss.Izilda Cristina Johanson - 2017 - Doispontos 14 (2).
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  25
    Was the Magician of Madaura a Logician?Carmen Johanson - 1983 - Apeiron 17 (2):131 - 134.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  94
    Husserl on Kant and the critical view of logic.Mirja Hartimo - 2022 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 65 (6):707-724.
    ABSTRACT This paper seeks to clarify Husserl’s critical remarks about Kant’s view of logic by comparing their respective views of logic. In his Formal and Transcendental Logic Husserl criticizes Kant for not asking transcendental questions about formal logic, but rather ascribing an ‘extraordinary apriority’ to it. He thinks the reason for Kant’s uncritical attitude to logic lies in Kant’s view of logic as directed toward the subjective, instead of being concerned with a ‘“world” of ideal Objects’. Whereas for Kant, general (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19. Towards completeness: Husserl on theories of manifolds 1890–1901.Mirja Helena Hartimo - 2007 - Synthese 156 (2):281-310.
    Husserl’s notion of definiteness, i.e., completeness is crucial to understanding Husserl’s view of logic, and consequently several related philosophical views, such as his argument against psychologism, his notion of ideality, and his view of formal ontology. Initially Husserl developed the notion of definiteness to clarify Hermann Hankel’s ‘principle of permanence’. One of the first attempts at formulating definiteness can be found in the Philosophy of Arithmetic, where definiteness serves the purpose of the modern notion of ‘soundness’ and leads Husserl to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  20.  80
    Husserl on completeness, definitely.Mirja Hartimo - 2018 - Synthese 195 (4):1509-1527.
    The paper discusses Husserl’s notion of definiteness as presented in his Göttingen Mathematical Society Double Lecture of 1901 as a defense of two, in many cases incompatible, ideals, namely full characterizability of the domain, i.e., categoricity, and its syntactic completeness. These two ideals are manifest already in Husserl’s discussion of pure logic in the Prolegomena: The full characterizability is related to Husserl’s attempt to capture the interconnection of things, whereas syntactic completeness relates to the interconnection of truths. In the Prolegomena (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  21.  86
    Mathematical roots of phenomenology: Husserl and the concept of number.Mirja Hartimo - 2006 - History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (4):319-337.
    The paper examines the roots of Husserlian phenomenology in Weierstrass's approach to analysis. After elaborating on Weierstrass's programme of arithmetization of analysis, the paper examines Husserl's Philosophy of Arithmetic as an attempt to provide foundations to analysis. The Philosophy of Arithmetic consists of two parts; the first discusses authentic arithmetic and the second symbolic arithmetic. Husserl's novelty is to use Brentanian descriptive analysis to clarify the fundamental concepts of arithmetic in the first part. In the second part, he founds the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  22. From geometry to phenomenology.Mirja Helena Hartimo - 2008 - Synthese 162 (2):225-233.
    Richard Tieszen [Tieszen, R. (2005). Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXX(1), 153–173.] has argued that the group-theoretical approach to modern geometry can be seen as a realization of Edmund Husserl’s view of eidetic intuition. In support of Tieszen’s claim, the present article discusses Husserl’s approach to geometry in 1886–1902. Husserl’s first detailed discussion of the concept of group and invariants under transformations takes place in his notes on Hilbert’s Memoir Ueber die Grundlagen der Geometrie that Hilbert wrote during the winter 1901–1902. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  23. Husserl on 'Besinnung' and formal ontology.Mirja Helena Hartimo - 2019 - In Frode Kjosavik & Camilla Serck-Hanssen, Metametaphysics and the Sciences: Historical and Philosophical Perspectives. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 200-215.
  24.  42
    No Magic: From Phenomenology of Practice to Social Ontology of Mathematics.Mirja Hartimo & Jenni Rytilä - 2023 - Topoi 42 (1):283-295.
    The paper shows how to use the Husserlian phenomenological method in contemporary philosophical approaches to mathematical practice and mathematical ontology. First, the paper develops the phenomenological approach based on Husserl's writings to obtain a method for understanding mathematical practice. Then, to put forward a full-fledged ontology of mathematics, the phenomenological approach is complemented with social ontological considerations. The proposed ontological account sees mathematical objects as social constructions in the sense that they are products of culturally shared and historically developed practices. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  44
    “To Be is To Inter-Be”: Thich Nhat Hanh on Interdependent Arising.Mirja Annalena Holst - 2021 - Journal of World Philosophies 6 (2):17-30.
    This paper presents the metaphysics of the Vietnamese Buddhist Zen monk Thich Nhat Hanh. He interprets the Buddhist principle of interdependent arising in terms of interbeing, the idea that everything depends for its existence on everything else. On his view, everything “inter-is” with everything else, or “to be is to inter-be.” His interpretation is particularly interesting in light of the contemporary debate on fundamentality in western metaphysics. By embracing the idea of interbeing, he opposes the view that there are fundamental (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  25
    Husserl and Hilbert.Mirja Hartimo - 2017 - In Stefania Centrone, Essays on Husserl’s Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics. Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
    The paper examines Husserl’s phenomenology and Hilbert’s view of the foundations of mathematics against the backdrop of their lifelong friendship. After a brief account of the complementary nature of their early approaches, the paper focuses on Husserl’s Formale und transzendentale Logik viewed as a response to Hilbert’s “new foundations” developed in the 1920s. While both Husserl and Hilbert share a “mathematics first,” nonrevisionist approach toward mathematics, they disagree about the way in which the access to it should be construed: Hilbert (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27. Radical Besinnung in Formale und transzendentale Logik.Mirja Hartimo - 2018 - Husserl Studies 34 (3):247-266.
    This paper explicates Husserl’s usage of what he calls “radical Besinnung” in Formale und transzendentale Logik. Husserl introduces radical Besinnung as his method in the introduction to FTL. Radical Besinnung aims at criticizing the practice of formal sciences by means of transcendental phenomenological clarification of its aims and presuppositions. By showing how Husserl applies this method to the history of formal sciences down to mathematicians’ work in his time, the paper explains in detail the relationship between historical critical Besinnung and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  11
    The Logic of Apuleius: Including a Complete Latin Text and English Translation of the Peri Hermeneias of Apuleius of Madaura.David George Londey & Carmen J. Johanson - 1987 - Brill Archive.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  29.  53
    (1 other version)On the Origins of Scientific Objectivity.Mirja Hartimo - 2018 - In Frode Kjosavik, Christian Beyer & Christel Fricke, Husserl’s Phenomenology of Intersubjectivity : Historical Interpretations and Contemporary Applications. New York: Routledge. pp. 302-321.
  30. Constitution and Construction.Mirja Hartimo - 2019 - In Christina Weiss, Constructive Semantics: Meaning in Between Phenomenology and Constructivism. Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag. pp. 123-133.
  31.  87
    Syntactic reduction in Husserl’s early phenomenology of arithmetic.Mirja Hartimo & Mitsuhiro Okada - 2016 - Synthese 193 (3):937-969.
    The paper traces the development and the role of syntactic reduction in Edmund Husserl’s early writings on mathematics and logic, especially on arithmetic. The notion has its origin in Hermann Hankel’s principle of permanence that Husserl set out to clarify. In Husserl’s early texts the emphasis of the reductions was meant to guarantee the consistency of the extended algorithm. Around the turn of the century Husserl uses the same idea in his conception of definiteness of what he calls “mathematical manifolds.” (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  44
    The development of mathematics and the birth of phenomenology.Mirja Hartimo - 2010 - In Phenomenology and mathematics. London: Springer. pp. 107--121.
  33.  82
    Logic as a Universal Medium or Logic as a Calculus? Husserl and the Presuppositions of “the Ultimate Presupposition of Twentieth Century Philosophy”.Mirja Hartimo - 2006 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 44 (4):569-580.
    This paper discusses Jean van Heijenoort’s (1967) and Jaakko and Merrill B. Hintikka’s (1986, 1997) distinction between logic as auniversal language and logic as a calculus, and its applicability to Edmund Husserl’s phenomenology. Although it is argued that Husserl’s phenomenology shares characteristics with both sides, his view of logic is closer to the model-theoretical, logic-as-calculus view. However, Husserl’s philosophy as transcendental philosophy is closer to the universalist view. This paper suggests that Husserl’s position shows that holding a model-theoretical view of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  34.  86
    Phenomenology and mathematics.Mirja Hartimo (ed.) - 2010 - London: Springer.
    This volume aims to establish the starting point for the development, evaluation and appraisal of the phenomenology of mathematics.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  29
    Husserl’s Transcendentalization of Mathematical Naturalism.Mirja Hartimo - 2020 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 1 (3):289-306.
    The paper aims to capture a form of naturalism that can be found “built-in” in phenomenology, namely the idea to take science or mathematics on its own, without postulating extraneous normative “molds” on it. The paper offers a detailed comparison of Penelope Maddy’s naturalism about mathematics and Husserl’s approach to mathematics in Formal and Transcendental Logic. It argues that Maddy’s naturalized methodology is similar to the approach in the first part of the book. However, in the second part Husserl enters (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. Radical Besinnung as a method for phenomenological critique.Mirja Helena Hartimo - 2022 - In Andreea Smaranda Aldea, David Carr & Sara Heinämaa, Method Matters: Phenomenology as Critique.
    The paper discusses Husserl’s method of historical reflection, radical Besinnung, as defined and used in Formale und transzendentale Logik (1929). Whereas Formal and Transcendental Logic introduces and displays Husserl’s usage of Besinnung in the context of the exact sciences, the paper seeks to develop it as a more general critical method with which to approach any rational goal-directed activity. Husserl defines Besinnung as a method that enables understanding agents and their actions by explicating agents’ typically implicit goals. It leads to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Formal and Transcendental Logic- Husserl's most mature reflection on mathematics and logic.Mirja Helena Hartimo - 2021 - In Hanne Jacobs, The Husserlian Mind. New Yor, NY: Routledge. pp. 50-59.
    This essay presents Husserl’s Formal and Transcendental Logic (1929) in three main sections following the layout of the work itself. The first section focuses on Husserl’s introduction where he explains the method and the aim of the essay. The method used in FTL is radical Besinnung and with it an intentional explication of proper sense of formal logic is sought for. The second section is on formal logic. The third section focuses on Husserl’s “transcendental logic,” which is needed to make (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Incomplete descriptions and (reverse) Sobel sequences.Mirja Annalena Holst - 2013 - Analysis 73 (1):26-32.
    A challenge for theories of incomplete descriptions is to capture the consistency of ‘Sobel sequences’ and to account for an asymmetry in the acceptability of utterances of Sobel sequences and ‘reverse Sobel sequences’. David Lewis’s theory of incomplete descriptions answers, unlike many other theories, the challenge from Sobel sequences, but it does not answer the challenge from reverse Sobel sequences. This article presents another asymmetry in the availability of anaphoric readings of Sobel sequences and reverse Sobel sequences, and proposes an (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39. Husserl and Peirce and the Goals of Mathematics.Mirja Hartimo - 2019 - In Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen & Mohammad Shafiei, Peirce and Husserl: Mutual Insights on Logic, Mathematics and Cognition. Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag.
    ABSTRACT. The paper compares the views of Edmund Husserl (1859-1938) and Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914) on mathematics around the turn of the century. The two share a view that mathematics is an independent and theoretical discipline. Both think that it is something unrelated to how we actually think, and hence independent of psychology. For both, mathematics reveals the objective and formal structure of the world, and both think that modern mathematics is a Platonist enterprise. Husserl and Peirce also share a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. Epistemic values and their phenomenological critique.Mirja Helena Hartimo - 2022 - In Sara Heinämaa, Mirja Hartimo & Ilpo Hirvonen, Contemporary Phenomenologies of Normativity: Norms, Goals, and Values. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 234-251.
    Husserl holds that the theoretical sciences should be value-free, i.e., free from the values of extra-scientific practices and guided only by epistemic values such as coherence and truth. This view does not imply that to Husserl the sciences would be immune to all criticism of interests, goals, and values. On the contrary, the paper argues that Husserlian phenomenology necessarily embodies reflection on the epistemic values guiding the sciences. The argument clarifies Husserl’s position by comparing it with the pluralistic position developed (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  14
    (1 other version)Acceptability of operations as an indicator of corporate social performance.Mirja Mikkilä - 2003 - Business Ethics: A European Review 12 (1):78-87.
    There has been much theoretical debate on issues of business ethics during the last decades, but there has been little research which could concretise the content of these issues in terms of practical business. Although business life must frequently deal with concepts such as corporate social performance, business ethics and the acceptability of operations, the content and meaning of these concepts has remained flexible. In addition, rapid internationalisation and globalisation have introduced a number of new phenomena related to corporate social (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  5
    Rudolf Carnap (1891-1970).Mirja Hartimo - 2025 - Encyclopedia of Phenomenology.
    This entry aims to explain briefly why Rudolf Carnap is an interesting philosopher, and so especially from the phenomenological point of view. There are two primary reasons for why this should be the case: First, there is a historical connection between the two. Carnap developed many of his philosophical ideas in Freiburg while attempting (in vain) to habilitate with Husserl. This may explain why interesting Husserlian themes can be found especially in Carnap’s early works. Philosophically more exciting is the second (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  90
    Husserl and gödel’s incompleteness theorems.Mirja Hartimo - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):638-650.
    The paper examines Husserl’s interactions with logicians in the 1930s in order to assess Husserl’s awareness of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems. While there is no mention about the results in Husserl’s known exchanges with Hilbert, Weyl, or Zermelo, the most likely source about them for Husserl is Felix Kaufmann (1895–1949). Husserl’s interactions with Kaufmann show that Husserl may have learned about the results from him, but not necessarily so. Ultimately Husserl’s reading marks on Friedrich Waismann’s Einführung in das mathematische Denken: die (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Critical Views of Logic.Mirja Hartimo, Frode Kjosavik & Øystein Linnebo (eds.) - 2022
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Spielbedeutungen: Hussserl on Rule Following and the Mechanization of Thought.Mirja Hartimo - 2003 - Philosophy Today 47 (5):71-78.
  46.  36
    "What Is so Amazing about All This?": Buddhist Criticism of Christianity in Sixteenth-/Seventeenth-Century Japan.Mirja Dorothee Lange - 2023 - Buddhist-Christian Studies 43 (1):163-180.
    abstract: The first Christian missionaries arrived in Japan in the middle of the sixteenth century. They missionized quite a number of Japanese people but also angered many through their disrespectful behavior and destruction of temples and shrines. Less than 100 years later, Japan closed its borders, persecuted Christians, and banned Christianity in total. The reasons for this drastic step weren't solely political but also theological. Theological arguments concerning theism, eschatology, ethics, and theology of religion are found in official edicts, in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  26
    Swords and diamonds—Thich Nhat Hanh on the law of identity.Mirja Annalena Holst - 2023 - Asian Journal of Philosophy 2 (2):1-15.
    The Diamond Sutra is one of the earliest and most treasured of the Perfection of Wisdom Sutras and had a wide influence on the development of Zen Buddhism. There has been, in recent years, great interest in one particular form of sentences that repeatedly occur in the sutra, sentences of the form “A is not A, therefore it is A”. These sentences display what has been called the “logic of not” or the “logic of affirmation-in-negation”. They are of special interest (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Husserl and the Algebra of Logic: Husserl’s 1896 Lectures.Mirja Hartimo - 2012 - Axiomathes 22 (1):121-133.
    In his 1896 lecture course on logic–reportedly a blueprint for the Prolegomena to Pure Logic –Husserl develops an explicit account of logic as an independent and purely theoretical discipline. According to Husserl, such a theory is needed for the foundations of logic (in a more general sense) to avoid psychologism in logic. The present paper shows that Husserl’s conception of logic (in a strict sense) belongs to the algebra of logic tradition. Husserl’s conception is modeled after arithmetic, and respectively logical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The chimera of logicism: Husserl's criticism of Frege.Mirja Helena Hartimo - 2021 - In Francesca Boccuni & Andrea Sereni, Origins and Varieties of Logicism: On the Logico-Philosophical Foundations of Logicism. Routledge. pp. 197-214.
    The paper discusses Husserl’s criticism of Frege in Philosophy of Arithmetic (1891) and then his later attitude towards logicism as expressed in Logical Investigations (1900-01). In Philosophy of Arithmetic Husserl holds that logicists offer needless and artificial definitions of notions such as equivalence and number. Frege criticized Husserl’s approach in Philosophy of Arithmetic as psychological, thus shifting the focus of the debate away from logicism. However, Frege’s criticism could be seen to lead Husserl to his later transcendental phenomenological concept of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  7
    Vienna Circle. Shaping Contemporary Analytic Philosophy and its History.Mirja Hartimo & Anssi Korhonen (eds.) - 2024 - mdpi.
    An exciting trend in current analytic philosophy is the emergence of several topics that draw their inspiration partly from the work of Rudolf Carnap, a leading figure in the Vienna Circle. Approaches such as deflationary metaontology, conceptual engineering, logical pluralism, and related views on the normativity of logic are seen to have Carnapian roots; however, these topics are quite foreign to the once-prevalent but rather narrow reading of Carnap that derives from W. V. Quine’s and others’ appraisal of him in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 94