Results for 'Rights to nature'

979 found
Order:
  1. The nature and value of the.Moral Right To Privacy - 2002 - Public Affairs Quarterly 16 (4):329.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  52
    Justice and rights to natural resources. Chris Armstrong. Oxford: Oxford university press, 2017.Petra Gümplová - 2018 - Constellations 25 (1):175-177.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Children's Human Rights to Natural Biological Origins and Family Structure.Margaret Somerville - 2011 - Bioethics Research Notes 23 (1):1.
    Somerville, Margaret Over the millennia of human history, the idea that children - at least those born into a marriage - had rights with respect to their biological parents was taken for granted and reflected in law and public policy. But with same-sex marriage, which gives same-sex spouses the right to found a family, that is no longer the case. Likewise, children's rights with respect to their biological origins were not an issue when there was no technoscience that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  25
    Peoples’ right to self-determination and self-governance over natural resources: Possible and desirable?Hans Morten Haugen - 2013 - Etikk I Praksis - Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics 1 (1):3-21.
    he article combines Elinor Ostrom’s design principles for common-pool resources and human rights provisions, including subsequent clarifications and jurisprudence. It analyses whether stronger local self-governance, embedded in the natural resource dimension of peoples’ rights to self-determination is a recommendable approach. Two changes in understanding are noted. First, the universal approval of indigenous peoples’ right to self-determination as specified in the UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples. Second, the wide endorsement of the specific principle of free (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5. Natural Rights to Welfare.Siegfried Van Duffel - 2011 - European Journal of Philosophy 21 (4):641-664.
    : Many people have lamented the proliferation of human rights claims. The cure for this problem, it may be thought, would be to develop a theory that can distinguish ‘real’ from ‘supposed’ human rights. I argue, however, that the proliferation of human rights mirrors a deep problem in human rights theory itself. Contemporary theories of natural rights to welfare are historical descendants from a theory of rights to subsistence which was developed in twelfth-century Europe. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  90
    Rights of Nature: A Re-examination.Daniel P. Corrigan & Markku Oksanen (eds.) - 2021 - Routledge.
    Rights of nature is an idea that has come of age. In recent years, a diverse range of countries and jurisdictions have adopted these norms, which involve granting legal rights to nature or natural objects, such as rivers, forests, or ecosystems. This book critically examines the idea of natural objects as right-holders, and analyses legal cases, policies, and philosophical issues relating to this development. -/- Drawing on contributions from a range of experts in the field, (...) of Nature: A Re-examination investigates the potential for this innovative idea to revolutionize the concepts of rights, standing, and recognition as traditionally understood in many legal systems. Taking as its starting point Stone’s influential 1972 article ‘Should Trees Have Standing?’, the book examines the progress rights of nature have made since that time, by identifying central themes, unifying principles, and key distinctions in how rights of nature discourse has been operationalized in the disciplines of law, philosophy, and the social sciences. These themes and principles are illustrated through a wide variety of examples, including ecosystem services, indigenous thinking, and ecological restoration, demonstrating how the relationship between humanity and the natural world may be transforming. -/- Taking a philosophical, political, and legal perspective, this book will be of great interest to students and scholars of environmental law and policy, environmental ethics, and philosophy. (shrink)
  7.  11
    The Natural Right to Property as an Instrumental Right.Matěj Křížecký - 2024 - Human Affairs 34 (3):408-420.
    I argue that Robert Nozick, in his well-known book “Anarchy, State, Utopia”, is working with Locke’s notion of the natural right to property merely instrumentally. I use the term “instrumentally” in the sense that the pieces of the source are not used within the context of the original work but are used atomically to support one’s argument or theory. Instrumental use of Locke’s theory causes incoherence in his theory. This paper introduces the incoherence in the question and explains how this (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  14
    From Civil Rights to Nature’s Rights.J. Baird Callicott - 2020 - Journal of World Philosophies 5 (1):183-187.
    Hailing from the American South, I was a slow student, awakened by Plato in high school and introduced to philosophy in college. Alienated from analytic trivia and minutia, I did graduate work in Greek philosophy at Syracuse University. My first academic job at Memphis State University involved me in the Southern Civil Rights Movement; my second at the Wisconsin State University-Stevens Point involved me in the environmental movement and inspired me to create first environmental ethics and then, in collaboration (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Is there a natural right to healthcare?Sean Rife - 2012 - Human Affairs 22 (4):613-622.
    In recent years, policy debates in the United States have focused heavily on rising healthcare costs and what measures can be taken to ensure greater provision of healthcare to individuals of limited means. Much of the rhetoric on this subject has taken on an explicitly moral character, and one common sentiment is that healthcare is or should be viewed as a basic human right. However, the notion of a right to healthcare has not been well articulated, and critics have failed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. Natural rights to migration?Christopher Bertram - unknown
    It is often claimed that states enjoy, as a consequence of their sovereign status, the right to control the passage of outsiders through their territory and that they have a discretion to admit or to refuse to admit outsiders, whether those outsiders be tourists, business travelers, would-be economic migrants, or even refugees. Or, to be more exact, such limitations on that right to control are derived from the agreement of states to treaties and conventions, agreement which they could have withheld (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  5
    Natural Right to Grow and Die in the Form of Wholeness: A Philosophical Interpretation of the Ontological Status of Brain-dead Children.Naoshi Yamawaki - 2010 - Diogenes 57 (3):103-116.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  36
    The Right to Education in the Fichtean Theory of Natural Right.Héctor Oscar Arrese Igor - 2015 - Philosophical Forum 46 (4):403-420.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. The right to ignore: An epistemic defense of the nature/culture divide.Maria Kronfeldner - 2017 - In Joyce Richard (ed.), Handbook of Evolution and Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 210-224.
    This paper addresses whether the often-bemoaned loss of unity of knowledge about humans, which results from the disciplinary fragmentation of science, is something to be overcome. The fragmentation of being human rests on a couple of distinctions, such as the nature-culture divide. Since antiquity the distinction between nature (roughly, what we inherit biologically) and culture (roughly, what is acquired by social interaction) has been a commonplace in science and society. Recently, the nature/culture divide has come under attack (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  65
    Human Nature and the Right to Coerce in Kant’s Doctrine of Right.Alice Pinheiro Walla - 2014 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 96 (1):126–139.
    This paper explores the alleged role of a conception of human nature for Kant’s justification of the duty to leave the state of nature and the related right to coerce others to enter the civil condition in the Doctrine of Right (1797). I criticise the interpretation put forward by Byrd and Hruschka, according to which Kant’s postulate of public right is a preventive measure based on a “presumption of badness” of human beings. Although this reading seems to be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  16
    The Natural Right to Liberty and the Need for a Social Contract.Jeffrey Reiman - 2012 - In As Free and as Just as Possible: The Theory of Marxian Liberalism. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 67–93.
    This chapter contains sections titled: A Lockean Argument for the Right to Liberty Our Rational Moral Competence From Liberty to Lockean Contractarianism.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16. Natural Right to Grow and Die in the Form of Wholeness: A Philosophical Interpretation of the Ontological Status of Brain-dead Children.Masahiro Morioka - 2010 - Diogenes 57 (3):103-116.
    In this paper, I would like to argue that brain-dead small children have a natural right not to be invaded by other people even if their organs can save the lives of other suffering patients. My basic idea is that growing human beings have the right to grow in the form of wholeness, and dying human beings also have the right to die in the form of wholeness; in other words, they have the right to be protected from outside invasion, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  41
    The Right to Refuse Treatment and Natural Death Legislation.Jane A. Raible - 1977 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 5 (4):6-8.
  18.  13
    On the natural right to private property: Rousseau’s reading of Locke.Lucas Mello Carvalho Ribeiro - 2024 - Griot 24 (2):1-14.
    The emergence of private property is an inflexion point in the hypothetical history conceived by Rousseau. Social relations, recently constituted, are completely restructured by this event. More specifically, it is only due to the accentuated economic inequality that stems from the partition of land between proprietors and supernumeraries that an exacerbated conflict arises between men, thus demanding the celebration of a contract able to stabilize social interactions via the erection of a sovereign political power. Given the importance of the matter, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. The right to life-nature and work in Fichte, jg.Carla De Pascale - 1988 - Archives de Philosophie 51 (4):597-612.
  20.  60
    The Right to Resist and the Right of Rebellion.Yulia Razmetaeva - 2014 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 21 (3):758-784.
    The right to resist and the right to rebel have again become relevant as legal problems. Their justifications traditionally derive from natural law, human rights, the principle of the lesser evil or of the social contract. Interpretation of the right to resist expresses the tendencies to the law of people, in particular, the right to self-determination, distinguishing national and international understanding, and underscores the special nature of such right. Also, two-level research of the right to resist should be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21. Foundation for a Natural Right to Health Care.Jason T. Eberl, Eleanor K. Kinney & Matthew J. Williams - 2011 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36 (6):537-557.
    Discussions concerning whether there is a natural right to health care may occur in various forms, resulting in policy recommendations for how to implement any such right in a given society. But health care policies may be judged by international standards including the UN Universal Declaration of Human Rights. The rights enumerated in the UDHR are grounded in traditions of moral theory, a philosophical analysis of which is necessary in order to adjudicate the value of specific policies designed (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22.  83
    Why a Right to an Explanation of Algorithmic Decision-Making Should Exist: A Trust-Based Approach.Tae Wan Kim & Bryan R. Routledge - 2022 - Business Ethics Quarterly 32 (1):75-102.
    Businesses increasingly rely on algorithms that are data-trained sets of decision rules (i.e., the output of the processes often called “machine learning”) and implement decisions with little or no human intermediation. In this article, we provide a philosophical foundation for the claim that algorithmic decision-making gives rise to a “right to explanation.” It is often said that, in the digital era, informed consent is dead. This negative view originates from a rigid understanding that presumes informed consent is a static and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  23. The right to privacy unveiled.Samuel C. Rickless - 2007 - San Diego Law Review 44 (1):773-799.
    The vast majority of philosophers and legal theorists who have thought about the issue agree that there is such a thing as a moral right to privacy. However, there is little or no theoretical consensus about the nature of this right. According to reductionists, the right to privacy amounts to nothing more than a cluster of property rights and rights over the person, and therefore plays no autonomous explanatory role in moral theory (Thomson 1975, Davis 1959). Among (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  24.  15
    Rights to Punish for Libertarians.Jordan Howard Sobel - 1995 - Dialogue 34 (4):675-.
    Thomas Hurka derives rights to punish from what I will term the Libertarian Rights Principle, which is “that there is really only one natural right, namely the equal right of all persons to the most extensive liberty compatible with a like liberty for other persons, and that all other natural rights are species or instances of the right to liberty.” These rights to punish, he says, extend only to punishing violators of rights, never to “punishing” (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  82
    Natural Law and the Right to Know in a Democracy.Jeffrey J. Maciejewski & David T. Ozar - 2005 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 20 (2-3):121-138.
    This article places the concept of "right to know," which is normally associated with law, in a moral framework. It outlines multiple meanings of the concept, emphasizing the institutional nature of "right to know." Then the article imbeds this understanding in moral thinking, including a discussion of the moral elements of rights, and applies that understanding in specific journalistic situations.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26. The Conventionalist Challenge to Natural Rights Theory.Ben Bryan - 2017 - Social Theory and Practice 43 (3):569-587.
    Call the conventionalist challenge to natural rights theory the claim that natural rights theory fails to capture the fact that moral rights are shaped by social and legal convention. While the conventionalist challenge is a natural concern, it is less than clear what this challenge amounts to. This paper aims to develop a clear formulation strong enough to put pressure on the natural rights theorist and precise enough to clarify what an adequate response would require.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27. The Right to Punish in Thomas Hobbes’s Leviathan.Arthur Yates - 2014 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 52 (2):233-254.
    There is an apparent ambiguity in Thomas Hobbes’s account in Leviathan1 of the source of the sovereign’s right to punish. Hobbes appears to both claim and deny that the prospective sovereign is granted the right to punish by prospective subjects. In claiming that the sovereign is granted the right to punish, we understand Hobbes to hold that the acquisition of the right follows from authorization—a process by which a representative is commissioned to act on the behalf of another person. In (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  42
    Rights to life? On nature, property and biotechnology.John M. Meyer - 2000 - Journal of Political Philosophy 8 (2):154–175.
  29.  47
    On environmental justice, Part II: non-absolute equal division of rights to the natural world.Joseph Mazor - 2023 - Economics and Philosophy 39 (2):256-284.
    This article considers whether any interpretation of the idea of equal claims to the natural world can resolve the Canyon Dilemma (i.e. can justify protecting the Grand Canyon but not a small canyon from mining by a poor generation). It first considers and ultimately rejects the idea of subjecting natural resource rights to an intergenerational equal division. It then demonstrates that a pluralist theory of environmental justice committed to both respect for the separateness of persons and to the collective (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  49
    The ‘Right to Have Rights’ 65 Years Later: Justice Beyond Humanitarianism, Politics Beyond Sovereignty.Katherine Howard - 2017 - Global Justice: Theory Practice Rhetoric 10 (1).
    Readers of Hannah Arendt’s now classic formulation of the statelessness problem in her 1951 book The Origins of Totalitarianism abound at a moment when the number of stateless peoples worldwide continues to rise exponentially. Along with statelessness, few concepts in Arendt scholarship have spawned such a volume of literature, and perhaps none have provoked as much interest outside of the field of philosophy, as ‘the right to have rights.’ Interpreting this enigmatic term exposes the heart of our beliefs about (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  34
    The right to remain silent: before and after Joan of Arc.H. Ansgar Kelly - 1993 - Speculum 68 (4):992-1026.
    The beginning of the typical Miranda warning—“You have the right to remain silent. Anything you say can be used against you in a court of law”—is also a fair statement of the medieval right to silence that can be deduced from the canonical rules of due process, and such a warning could and should have been given to arrestees in inquisitorial proceedings. In such proceedings the judge was obliged to give any detained or summoned person a precise statement of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  27
    Answering the Conventionalist Challenge to Natural Rights Theory.Billy Christmas - 2020 - Res Publica 27 (3):329-345.
    Ben Bryan argues that the strongest challenge to natural rights theory is to explain how it overcomes the Problem of Authority. Given that our natural rights are multiply realisable by a range of equally reasonable social conventions, how or why ought one particular realisation have authority? I argue that Thomistic and Kantian solutions to this problem do not count as solutions from natural rights theory, and therefore offer my own solution. When theories of natural rights describe (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  67
    Hobbes, Kant, and the Universal ‘right to all things’, or Why We Have to Leave the State of Nature.Daniel Eggers - 2019 - Hobbes Studies 32 (1):46-70.
    This paper discusses the juridical interpretation of Hobbes’s state of nature argument, which has been defended by commentators such as Georg Geismann, Dieter Hüning or Peter Schröder. According to the juridical interpretation, the primary reason why the Hobbesian state of nature needs to be abandoned is not that everybody’s self-preservation is constantly threatened. It is that, due to the universal right to all things, the jural order of the state of nature includes some kind of logical contradiction. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  12
    The right to privacy.Janet E. Smith - 2008 - San Francisco: Ignatius Press.
    Foreword by Robert H. Bork -- Culture wars -- A distorted understanding of rights -- The right to privacy -- Griswold and contraception -- Roe and abortion -- Assisted suicide and homosexuality -- Political connections and natural consequences.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  46
    Rights to the Oceans: Foundational Arguments Reconsidered.Cara Nine - 2018 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 36 (4):626-642.
    This article examines theories of ocean rights based on the works of Hugo Grotius and Samuel von Pufendorf. Grotius's object‐centred view uses features of the natural world to justify claims to external objects. I show that Grotius's view is inadequate, because it relies on an outdated claim that oceanic resources are sufficiently abundant for anybody to use. Further, adaptations of his view are wanting, because they either rely on arbitrary distinctions or disregard the values of cultural minorities. Pufendorf's relational (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  15
    The Right to Mental Autonomy.William Ratoff - 2024 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 27 (2).
    A number of moral philosophers and legal scholars have now recognized that we possess a natural, or moral, right to mental autonomy. This right is standardly characterized as our right against significant, nonconsensual interference with our minds. However, the precise scope of this right remains under-theorized: what makes some ways of influencing someone’s thinking—rational argumentation, say—permissible, but other ways—pharmacological manipulation—impermissible? Here I argue that the right to mental autonomy should be analyzed as the right to form attitudes in light of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  37
    Rights to Ecosystem Services.Marc D. Davidson - 2014 - Environmental Values 23 (4):465-483.
    Ecosystem services are the benefits people obtain from ecosystems. Many of these services are provided outside the borders of the land where they are produced. This article investigates who is entitled to these non-excludable ecosystem services from a libertarian perspective. Taking a right-libertarian perspective, it is concluded that the beneficiaries generally hold the right to use non-excludable ecosystem services and the right to landowners not converting ecosystems. Landowners are only at liberty to convert ecosystems if they appropriated their land before (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38. Doctors Have no Right to Refuse Medical Assistance in Dying, Abortion or Contraception.Julian Savulescu & Udo Schuklenk - 2017 - Bioethics 30 (9):162-170.
    In an article in this journal, Christopher Cowley argues that we have ‘misunderstood the special nature of medicine, and have misunderstood the motivations of the conscientious objectors’. We have not. It is Cowley who has misunderstood the role of personal values in the profession of medicine. We argue that there should be better protections for patients from doctors' personal values and there should be more severe restrictions on the right to conscientious objection, particularly in relation to assisted dying. We (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  39. No Right to Resist? Elise Reimarus's Freedom as a Kantian Response to the Problem of Violent Revolt.Lisa Curtis-Wendlandt - 2012 - Hypatia 27 (4):755-773.
    One of the greatest woman intellectuals of eighteenth‐century Germany is Elise Reimarus, whose contribution to Enlightenment political theory is rarely acknowledged today. Unlike other social contract theorists, Reimarus rejects a people's right to violent resistance or revolution in her philosophical dialogue Freedom. Exploring the arguments in Freedom, this paper observes a number of similarities in the political thought of Elise Reimarus and Immanuel Kant. Both, I suggest, reject violence as an illegitimate response to perceived political injustice in a way that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  30
    A Right to Understand Injustice: Epistemology and the “Right to the Truth” in International Human Rights Discourse.Ian Werkheiser - 2020 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 58 (1):186-199.
    People's “right to truth” or their “right to know” about their government's human rights abuses is a growing consensus in human rights discourses and a fertile area of work in international and humanitarian law. In most discussions of this right to know the truth, it is commonly seen as requiring the state or international institutions to provide access to evidence of the violations. In this paper, I argue that such a right naturally has many epistemic aspects, and the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  41
    From Natural Law to Natural Rights? Protestant Dissent and Toleration in the Late Eighteenth Century.Martin Hugh Fitzpatrick - 2016 - History of European Ideas 42 (2).
    SummaryThe toleration gained by Protestant Dissenters, the Toleration Act of 1689, was far from comprehensive. It insisted that Dissenting authorities should subscribe to the doctrinal articles of the Church of England. It suspended anti-Dissent legislation rather than repealing it and the sacramental requirement for civil officials remained in place. The situation of Dissent under the law was ambiguous and, at least in theory, the freedom of worship gained under the act was incomplete. This article examines Dissenter attempts to clarify their (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. The Right to Religious Freedom: Thomistic Principles of Nature and Grace.Thomas Joseph White - 2015 - Nova et Vetera 13 (4).
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  8
    Technology and Human Rights, Friends or Foes?: Highlighting Innovations Applying to Natural Resources and Medicine.Hans Morten Haugen - 2012 - Rol.
    Hans Morten Haugen offers an analysis of the intersection of intellectual property with health, traditional knowledge and biodiversity against a backdrop of established and emerging human rights. How those rights interface and who decides are among the most difficult issues in international intellectual property, and there is no doubt that there is room for fresh ideas on how to simultaneously achieve the goals of innovation, development and access. 0Also part of series: Library of Human Rights; 2.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Moral rights to life, both natural and non-natural: reflections on James Griffin.Hugh V. McLachlan - 2010 - Diametros 26:58-76.
  45.  56
    Conceptualizing Human Stewardship in the Anthropocene: The Rights of Nature in Ecuador, New Zealand and India.Stefan Knauß - 2018 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 31 (6):703-722.
    In this text I investigate the increasing usage of the Rights of Nature to approach the task of Stewardship for the Earth. The Ecuadorian constitution of 2008 introduces the indigenous concept of Pachamama and interpretes nature as a subject of rights. Reflecting the two 2017 cases of the Whanganui River and the Gangotri and Yamunotri Glaciers, my main argument is that, although the language of individual rights relies on modern subjectivity as well as the constitutionalism (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46. The Right to Know Your Genetic Parents: From Open-Identity Gamete Donation to Routine Paternity Testing.An Ravelingien & Guido Pennings - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (5):33-41.
    Over the years a number of countries have abolished anonymous gamete donation and shifted toward open-identity policies. Donor-conceived children are said to have a fundamental “right to know” the identity of their donor. In this article, we trace the arguments that underlie this claim and question its implications. We argue that, given the status attributed to the right to know one's gamete donor, it would be discriminatory not to extend this right to naturally conceived children with misattributed paternity. One way (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  47.  6
    Rights of Nature Through a Legal Expressivist Lens: Legal Recognition of Non-Anthropocentric Values.Patrik Baard - forthcoming - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice:1-17.
    The shortcomings of existing legal tools to abate species extinctions and habitat losses raise the attractiveness of recognizing rights of nature (RoN), in effect granting legal standing directly to non-human entities and collectives. RoN have been recognized in several domestic legislations and attract increasing popularity and enthusiasm. Yet, from an analytical and general perspective RoN rely on a contentious relation between concepts such as intrinsic value and interests, respectively, as justifying RoN. Consequently, a general analytical defense of RoN (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  21
    Should be justified as including the right to demand fetal death, not merely fetal evacuation.Natural Meaning & Arda Denkel - 1992 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (3).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  22
    A child’s right to a father.C. L. Ten - 2000 - Monash Bioethics Review 19 (4):33-37.
    Recently a child’s right to a father was invoked to justify the prevention of single women from obtaining access to IVF. This article explores the conceptual and normative issues about the nature of the right and its conflict with a woman’s right to procreative autonomy. The discussion relates the conceptual issues to those raised in the context of ‘wrongful life’ tort cases. It concludes that the right to be born with a father, although conceptually sound, does not justify the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  6
    Environmental Protection, Rights of Nature, and Religious Beliefs in Europe.Ikechukwu P. Ugwu - forthcoming - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique:1-22.
    This paper examines the rights of nature (RoN) as a product of religious beliefs and how the increasing abandonment of religious beliefs in Europe could impact the development of RoN on the continent. As a concept rooted in religious and Indigenous peoples’ practices, this article argues that there are no religious and Indigenous peoples’ ideologies in Europe upon which RoN of nature could be anchored. Furthermore, since hardly any groups in Europe identify as Indigenous peoples in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 979