Results for 'Sanctions (Law)'

412 found
Order:
  1.  16
    Constitutional Customary Law and Constitutional Sanction: an Antinomy?Eleonora Bottini - 2020 - Noesis 34:143-158.
    In constitutional scholarship, legal sanctions and customary law seem to be opposed to each other: customary law is often defined precisely as law without sanctions. Applied to the constitutional field, it is possible to better define those two elements of discourse: constitutional sanctions are essentially procedures of constitutional review of legislation, while customary law is more frequently referred to as constitutional conventions. While insisting on the presence of the element of sanction is typical of the normative discourse (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  21
    Lawlessness, law, and sanction: a dissertation.Miriam Theresa Rooney - 1937 - Littleton, Colo.: F.B. Rothman.
    The author argues that both Maine & Holmes were overly influenced by others, which prevented both of their works from being as significant as they could have been.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  82
    The sanctions of the criminal law.Michael Clark - 1997 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 97 (1):25–39.
    Michael Clark; II*—The Sanctions of the Criminal Law, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 97, Issue 1, 1 June 1997, Pages 25–40, https://doi.org/10.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. Sanction and obligation in Hart's theory of law.Danny Priel - 2008 - Ratio Juris 21 (3):404-411.
    Abstract. The paper begins by challenging Hart's argument aimed to show that sanctions are not part of the concept of law. It shows that in the "minimal" legal system as understood by Hart, sanctions may be required for keeping the legal system efficacious. I then draw a methodological conclusion from this argument, which challenges the view of Hart (and his followers) that legal philosophy should aim at discovering some general, politically neutral, conceptual truths about law. Instead, the aim (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  25
    Criminal Law Without Punishment: How Our Society Might Benefit From Abolishing Punitive Sanctions.Valerij Zisman - 2023 - De Gruyter.
    How can criminal punishment be morally justified? Zisman addresses this classical question in legal philosophy. He provides two maybe surprising answers to the question. First, as for a methodological claim, it argues that this question cannot be answered by philosophers and legal scholars alone. Rather, we need to take into account research from social psychology, economy, anthropology, and so on in order to properly analyze the arguments in defense of criminal punishment. Second, the book argues that when such research is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Defending the Criminal Law: Reflections on the Changing Character of Crime, Procedure, and Sanctions.Andrew Ashworth & Lucia Zedner - 2008 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 2 (1):21-51.
    Recent years have seen mounting challenge to the model of the criminal trial on the grounds it is not cost-effective, not preventive, not necessary, not appropriate, or not effective. These challenges have led to changes in the scope of the criminal law, in criminal procedure, and in the nature and use of criminal trials. These changes include greater use of diversion, of fixed penalties, of summary trials, of hybrid civil–criminal processes, of strict liability, of incentives to plead guilty, and of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  7. Sanctions: An Essential Element of Law?Nicoletta Bersier Ladavac, Christoph Bezemek & Frederick Schauer (eds.) - forthcoming - Springer.
  8. Regulatory and sanctioning powers of independent administrative authorities in French law.Alice Pezard - 2009 - In Albert Breton (ed.), Multijuralism: manifestations, causes, and consequences. Burlington. VT: Ashgate.
  9.  27
    Wrongs and Sanctions in the Pure Theory of Law.Luís Duarte D’Almeida - 2022 - Ratio Juris 35 (3):247-257.
    This short paper addresses a well‐known difficulty in the Pure Theory of Law: the definition of a legal wrong. Kelsen was unable to offer a suitable one, critics say. I agree. But the critics misdiagnosed the problem, and prescribed for it a fruitless solution. The reason for Kelsen’s failure, the critics say, was that he thought the law consists only of sanction‐stipulating norms addressed to officials, and does not comprise duty‐imposing norms addressed to citizens. But the critics are wrong, exegetically (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Unilateral Economic Sanctions, International Law, and Human Rights.Idriss Jazairy - 2019 - Ethics and International Affairs 33 (3):291-302.
    As part of the roundtable “Economic Sanctions and Their Consequences,” this essay examines unilateral coercive measures. These types of sanctions are applied outside the scope of Chapter VII of the United Nations Charter, and were developed and refined in the West in the context of the Cold War. Yet the eventual collapse of the Berlin Wall did not herald the demise of unilateral sanctions; much to the contrary. While there are no incontrovertible data on the extent of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  20
    (2 other versions)Lawlessness, Law, and Sanction. [REVIEW]Edwin Garlan - 1937 - Journal of Philosophy 34 (20):558-558.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Was Austin right after all? On the role of sanctions in a theory of law.Frederick Schauer - 2010 - Ratio Juris 23 (1):1-21.
    In modern jurisprudence it is taken as axiomatic that John Austin's sanction-based account of law and legal obligation was demolished in H.L.A. Hart's The Concept of Law, but Hart's victory and the deficiencies of the Austinian account may not be so clear. Not only does the alleged linguistic distinction between being obliged and having an obligation fail to provide as much support for the idea of a sanction-independent legal obligation as is commonly thought, but the soundness of Hart's claims, as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  13.  16
    From research misconduct to disciplinary sanction: an empirical examination of French higher education case law.Olivier Leclerc & Nicolas Klausser - 2025 - Research Ethics 21 (1):34-55.
    Reporting and investigating research misconduct can lead to disciplinary proceedings being initiated, and ultimately to disciplinary sanctions being imposed on convicted scientists. The conversion of research misconduct findings into disciplinary sanctions is poorly understood. This article analyses all the disciplinary decisions handed down on appeal by the Conseil national de l'enseignement supérieur et de la recherche (CNESER) between 1991 and 2023, concerning breaches of research integrity by academics and doctoral students ( n = 333). Three findings are highlighted. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Economic Sanctions, Morality and Escalation of Demands on Yugoslavia.Jovan Babić & Aleksandar Jokic - 2002 - International Peackeeping (No. 4):119-127.
    Economic sanctions are envisaged as a sort of punishment, based on what should be an institutional decision not unlike a court ruling. Hence, the conditions for their lifting should be clearly stated and once those are met sanctions should be lifted. But this is generally not what happens, and perhaps is precluded by the very nature of international sanctioning. Sanctions clearly have political, economic, military and strategic consequences, but the question raised here is whether sanctions can (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Sanctioning.Lucas Miotto - 2018 - Jurisprudence 9 (2):236-250.
    Up until recently, most legal philosophers have argued that an action is a token of sanctioning if, and only if, (i) its performance brings about unwelcome consequences to the targets, and (ii) it is performed as a response to the breach of a duty. In this paper I take issue with this account. I first add some qualifications to it in order to present it in its most plausible form. After doing this, I advance a series of hypothetical cases which (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  39
    Medical Sanctions Against Russia: Arresting Aggression or Abrogating Healthcare Rights?Michael L. Gross - forthcoming - American Journal of Bioethics:1-14.
    Since 2022, the EU, US, and other nations have imposed medical sanctions on Russia to block the export of pharmaceuticals and medical devices and curtail clinical trials to degrade Russia’s military capabilities. While international law proscribes sanctions that cause a humanitarian crisis, an outcome averted in Russia, the military effects of medical sanctions have been lean. Strengthening medical sanctions risks violating noncombatant and combatant rights to healthcare. Each group’s claim is different. Noncombatants and severely injured soldiers (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  25
    Economic Sanctions on Iraq: Tool for Peace, or Travesty?Sheila Zurbrigg - 2007 - Muslim World Journal of Human Rights 4 (2).
    Despite triggering one of the largest civilian death tolls in modern history, the policy and human consequences of economic sanctions on Iraq between 1990-2003 remain largely unexamined. This lack of scrutiny mirrors the euphemism and mis-information surrounding the embargo itself and the Oil-for-Food program ostensibly adopted to protect Iraq's civilian population. But it also reflects incomprehension among Western publics - long removed from the realities of hunger and economic destitution - of the intimate link between economic conditions and mortality. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  91
    Sanction and Obligation.Russell Hardin - 1985 - The Monist 68 (3):403-418.
    H. L. A. Hart’s criticism of Austin’s theory of law is that it is essentially false to the facts. Austin asserts that “Every positive law simply and strictly so called, is set by a sovereign person, or sovereign body of persons, to a … person or persons in a state of subjection to its author.” Laws get their force from the threat of sanction. This view, which we may call “the gunman theory of law,” is what Hart criticizes. Too many (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  91
    Aquinas on God-Sanctioned Stealing.Matthew Shea - 2018 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 92 (2):277-293.
    A serious challenge to religious believers in the Abrahamic traditions is that the God of the Old Testament seems to command immoral actions. Thomas Aquinas addresses this objection using the biblical story of God ordering the Israelites to plunder the Egyptians, which threatens to create an inconsistency among four of Aquinas’s views: God did indeed command this action; God is perfectly good and cannot command any evil actions; the objective moral goodness or badness of actions is not based on arbitrary (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  14
    The Law of Good People: Challenging States' Ability to Regulate Human Behavior.Yuval Feldman - 2018 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    Currently, the dominant enforcement paradigm is based on the idea that states deal with 'bad people' - or those pursuing their own self-interests - with laws that exact a price for misbehavior through sanctions and punishment. At the same time, by contrast, behavioral ethics posits that 'good people' are guided by cognitive processes and biases that enable them to bend the laws within the confines of their conscience. In this illuminating book, Yuval Feldman analyzes these paradigms and provides a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  71
    Why only the state may inflict criminal sanctions: The case against privately inflicted sanctions: Alon Harel.Alon Harel - 2008 - Legal Theory 14 (2):113-133.
    Criminal sanctions are typically inflicted by the state. The central role of the state in determining the severity of these sanctions and inflicting them requires justification. One justification for state-inflicted sanctions is simply that the state is more likely than other agents to determine accurately what a wrongdoer justly deserves and to inflict a just sanction on those who deserve it. Hence, in principle, the state could be replaced by other agents, for example, private individuals. This hypothesis (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  22.  26
    Criminal Law Scholarship: Three Illusions.Paul H. Robinson - 2001 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 2 (1).
    The paper criticizes criminal law scholarship for helping to construct and failing to expose analytic structures that falsely claim a higher level of rationality and coherence than current criminal law theory deserves. It offers illustrations of three such illusions of rationality. First, it is common in criminal law discourse for scholars and judges to cite any of the standard litany of "the purposes of punishment" -- just deserts, deterrence, incapacitation of the dangerous, rehabilitation, and sometimes other purposes -- as a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. (1 other version)Sanctions for acts or sanctions for actors?Frederick Shauer - 2020 - In Jordi Ferrer Beltrán & Carmen Vázquez (eds.), Evidential Legal Reasoning: Crossing Civil Law and Common Law Traditions. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  64
    Law and Coercion Introduction.Lucas Miotto - 2016 - Jurisprudence 7 (3):523-524.
  25.  23
    The Autonomy of Science as a Civilian Casualty of Economic Warfare: Inadvertent Censorship of Science Resulting from Unilateral Economic Sanctions.Behzad Ataie-Ashtiani & Hossein Esmaeili - 2021 - Science and Engineering Ethics 27 (4):1-9.
    Unilateral coercive international political, diplomatic, and economic sanctions are regular events of international relations and international law within the landscape of foreign affairs. However, while they may be prescribed by international law, or national legal systems, for peace and security reasons they have also been imposed for political grounds by powerful States such as the United States. The US sanctions are now targeting science, academic and university domains. When applied in this way, these sanctions violate international law, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  10
    Law and Reputation: How the Legal System Shapes Behavior by Producing Information.Roy Shapira - 2020 - Cambridge University Press.
    The legal system affects behavior not just directly, by imposing sanctions, but also indirectly, by producing information on how people behave. For example, internal company documents exposed during litigation will help third parties assess whether they trust a company and want to keep doing business with it. The law therefore affects behavior by shaping reputations. Drawing on economics, communications, and a nascent multidisciplinary literature on reputation, Roy Shapira highlights how reputation works, and how information from the courtroom affects the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  35
    Law’s Virtue: Fostering Autonomy and Solidarity in American Society by Cathleen Kaveny.Eric E. Schnitger - 2015 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 35 (1):212-213.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Law’s Virtue: Fostering Autonomy and Solidarity in American Society by Cathleen KavenyEric E. SchnitgerLaw’s Virtue: Fostering Autonomy and Solidarity in American Society By Cathleen Kaveny WASHINGTON, DC: GEORGETOWN UNIVERSITY PRESS, 2012. 304 PP. $29.95In Law’s Virtue, Cathleen Kaveny calls those in Western liberal countries to rethink their fundamental framework of ethics and law through the guiding principles of autonomy and solidarity, understood through the Catholic context of Thomistic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  13
    Is law possible during the war? Specificity of the corporeal experience.Oleksiy Stovba - 2023 - Phenomenology and Mind 25 (25):216.
    In the theory and philosophy of law, war is often considered as a legal remedy. For example, according to H. Kelsen, war is a sanction of international law. These sanctions, like sanctions in national law, consist in the forcible deprivation of life, liberty, and other goods, notably of economic value. In war, human beings are killed, maimed, imprisoned, and national or private property is destroyed. By way of reprisals, national or private property is confiscated and other legal rights (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  25
    Agency law and odious debts.Cristian Dimitriu - 2017 - Ethics and Global Politics 10 (1):77-97.
    Because of the way that the international lending system works, poor nations have been forced to repay sovereign debts without having a moral obligation to do so. Suppose a corrupt public official borrows money from an international agency, or from private investors, and later on embezzles this money, or uses it to oppress the population. Suppose, further, that the lender is aware of the potential of this situation and still lends. Typically, the international community considers that successor governments have the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30.  14
    Law, Orientalism and Postcolonialism: The Jurisdiction of the Lotus-Eaters.Piyel Haldar - 2007 - Routledge-Cavendish.
    Focusing on the ‘problem’ of pleasure _Law, Orientalism and Postcolonialism_ uncovers the organizing principles by which the legal subject was colonized. That occidental law was complicit in colonial expansion is obvious. What remains to be addressed, however, is the manner in which law and legal discourse sought to colonize individual subjects as subjects of law. It was through the permission of pleasure that modern Western subjects were refined and domesticated. Legally sanctioned outlets for private and social enjoyment instilled and continue (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  34
    Natural Law & Lawlessness: Modern Lessons from Pirates, Lepers, Eskimos, and Survivors.Paul H. Robinson - unknown
    The natural experiments of history present an opportunity to test Hobbes' view of government and law as the wellspring of social order. Groups have found themselves in a wide variety of situations in which no governmental law existed, from shipwrecks to gold mining camps to failed states. Yet the wide variety of situations show common patterns among the groups in their responses to their often difficult circumstances. Rather than survival of the fittest, a more common reaction is social cooperation and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  86
    Strategic coordination and the law.Nicholas Almendares & Dimitri Landa - 2007 - Law and Philosophy 26 (5):501-529.
    We re-examine the relationship between coordination, legal sanctions, and free-riding in light of the recent controversy regarding the applicability of the coordination problem paradigm of law-making. We argue that legal sanctions can help solve coordination problems by eliminating socially suboptimal equilibrium outcomes. Once coordination has taken place, however, free-riding can not lead to the breakdown of coordination outcomes, even if sanctions may still be effective at increasing the equity of such outcomes. Finally, we argue that it is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. The Grotius Sanction: Deus Ex Machina. The legal, ethical, and strategic use of drones in transnational armed conflict and counterterrorism.James Welch - 2019 - Dissertation, Leiden University
    The dissertation deals with the questions surrounding the legal, ethical and strategic aspects of armed drones in warfare. This is a vast and complex field, however, one where there remains more conflict and debate than actual consensus. -/- One of the many themes addressed during the course of this research was an examination of the evolution of modern asymmetric transnational armed conflict. It is the opinion of the author that this phenomenon represents a “grey-zone”; an entirely new paradigm of warfare. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  11
    Law and Order in Ancient Athens.Adriaan Lanni - 2016 - Cambridge University Press.
    The classical Athenian 'state' had almost no formal coercive apparatus to ensure order or compliance with law: there was no professional police force or public prosecutor, and nearly every step in the legal process depended on private initiative. And yet Athens was a remarkably peaceful and well-ordered society by both ancient and contemporary standards. Why? Law and Order in Ancient Athens draws on contemporary legal scholarship to explore how order was maintained in Athens. Lanni argues that law and formal legal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. Law and Coercion.Robert C. Hughes - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (3):231-240.
    Though political philosophers often presuppose that coercive enforcement is fundamental to law, many legal philosophers have doubted this. This article explores doubts of two types. Some legal philosophers argue that given an adequate account of coercion and coerciveness, the enforcement of law in actual legal systems will generally not count as coercive. Others accept that actual legal systems enforce many laws coercively, but they deny that law has a necessary connection with coercion. There can be individual laws that lack coercive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36. Skepticism and Sanction: The Benefits of Rejecting Moral Responsibility.Neil Levy - 2012 - Law and Philosophy 31 (5):477-493.
    It is sometimes objected that we cannot adopt skepticism about moral responsibility, because the criminal justice system plays an indispensable social function. In this paper, I examine the implications of moral responsibility skepticism for the punishment of those convicted of crime, with special attention to recent arguments by Saul Smilansky. Smilansky claims that the skeptic is committed to fully compensating the incarcerated for their detention, and that this compensation would both be too costly to be practical and would remove the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  37.  23
    The depoliticization of law in the news: BBC reporting on US use of extraterritorial or ‘long-arm’ law against China. Le Cheng, Xiaobin Zhu & David Machin - 2023 - Critical Discourse Studies 20 (3):306-319.
    ABSTRACT In this paper we explore how a public national media outlet, the British BBC, represents an international legal case which has a highly political nature. The case is US versus Huawei/meng Wanzhou, which took place between 2018 and 2021. Accusations were that the Chinese technology company committed fraud, leading the global HSBC bank to breach US sanctions against Iran. The charges were made by the US using what is called an ‘extraterritorial law’, which, while rejected as law by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. pt. II. Regulating abortion: international perspectives. The criminal sanction as it relates to human reproduction: the genesis of the statutory prohibition of abortion / Shelley Gavigan ; Abortion laws: comparative and feminist perspectives in Australia, England and the United States / Kerry Petersen ; Unenumerated rights: whether and how Roe should be overruled / Ronald Dworkin ; Member state sovereignty and women's reproductive rights: the European Union's response / Peta-Gaye Miller ; Making abortions safe: a matter of good public health policy and practice / Marge Berer ; The problem of coerced abortion in China and related ethical issues. [REVIEW]Jing-Bao Nie - 2004 - In Belinda Bennett (ed.), Abortion. Burlington, VT: Ashgate/Dartmouth.
  39.  30
    Sir Charles Grandison, Natural Law and the Fictionalised English Gentleman.Lisa O'Connell - 2013 - Intellectual History Review 23 (3):349-363.
    This article enquires into the relation between enlightened humanist conceptions of natural law and the period novel's fictionalization of the English gentleman in the context of its marriage plot. Marriage played a key role in enlightened theorisations of natural law precisely as an institution capable of grounding familial and civil life in an emerging concept of human nature. Yet public debate about the state's role in the regulation of marriage in mid-eighteenth-century England demonstrates that natural law lent itself to very (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  76
    Law and Coercion: Some Clarification.Lucas Miotto - 2021 - Ratio Juris 34 (1):74-87.
    The relationship between law and coercion has been, and still is, a central topic in legal philosophy. Despite this, discussion about it is immersed in confusion. Some philosophers have noticed this, but hardly any work has been done to attempt to solve or even identify the confusions. This paper aims to fill this gap. Here I propose distinctions and qualifications that help us clarify the relationship between law and coercion and avoid confusion. Building on the clarificatory work, I then argue (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  76
    Two rules of legality in criminal law.Peter Westen - 2006 - Law and Philosophy 26 (3):229-305.
    Criminal law scholars approach legality in various ways. Some scholars eschew over-arching principles and proceed directly to one or more distinct “rules”: (1) the rule against retroactive criminalization; (2) the rule that criminal statutes be construed narrowly; (3) the rule against the judicial creation of common-law offenses; and (4) the rule that vague criminal statutes are void. Other scholars seek a single principle, i.e., the “principle of legality,” that they claim underlies the four rules. In contrast, I believe that both (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  29
    The Impact of the Size of Bribes on Criminal Sanctions: An Integrated Philosophical and Economic Analysis.Leora Dahan Katz & Adi Libson - 2024 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 37 (1):31-46.
    This article analyzes the question of how the size of bribes should impact criminal sanctions. In contrast to the commonly held view that punishment should increase with the size of the bribe, we argue to the contrary: that the punishment of the bribee should decrease with the size of the bribe. Our conclusion is based both on a philosophical argument and an economic argument. We argue that all else being equal, as an agent’s reservation price for selling public interests (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  19
    Law and the Moral Order. [REVIEW]K. B. - 1982 - Review of Metaphysics 36 (1):175-176.
    Although the prevailing view that makes law simply an instrument of social control supports popular cynicism, it is, as an account of the relationship between law and morality, inadequate. The assurance of legal positivists regarding the logical distinctness of morals and legislation rests on the simplistic belief that moral sanctions are internal and not in conflict with free action while those of the law are external and coercive. With the development of pragmatism and its technology, behaviorism, both the independence (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Censure and Sanctions.Andrew Von Hirsch - 1996 - Law and Philosophy 15 (4):407-415.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  45.  12
    Responsibility in law and morality.Peter Cane - 2002 - Portland, Or.: Hart.
    Lawyers who write about responsibility tend to focus on criminal law at the expense of civil and public law; while philosophers tend to treat responsibility as a moral concept,and either ignore the law or consider legal responsibility to be a more or less distorted reflection of its moral counterpart. This book aims to counteract both of these biases. By adopting a comparative institutional approach to the relationship between law and morality, it challenges the common view that morality stands to law (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46.  28
    The Realignment of the Sources of the Law and their Meaning in an Information Society.Ugo Pagallo - 2015 - Philosophy and Technology 28 (1):57-73.
    The paper examines the realignment of the legal sources in an information society, by considering first of all the differences with the previous system of sources, dubbed as the “Westphalian model”. The current system is tripartite, rather than bipartite, for the sources of transnational law should be added to the traditional dichotomy between national and international law. In addition, the system is dualistic, rather than monistic, because the tools of legal constructivism, such as codes or statutes, have to be complemented (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Law in Plato's Late Politics (2nd edition).Rachana Kamtekar & Rachel Singpurwalla - 2022 - In David Ebrey & Richard Kraut (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 522-558.
    Throughout his political works, Plato takes the aim of politics to be the virtue and happiness of the citizens and the unity of the city. This paper examines the roles played by law in promoting individual virtue and civic unity in the Republic, Statesman, and Laws. Section 1 argues that in the Republic, laws regulate important institutions, such as education, property, and family, and thereby creating a way of life that conduces to virtue and unity. Section 2 argues that in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. A Child's Life or a “Little Bit of Torture”? State-Sanctioned Violence and Dignity.Doris Schroeder - 2006 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 15 (2):188-201.
    On September 28, 2002, 11-year-old Jakob von Metzler, a banker's son, was abducted on the way to his parents' house in Frankfurt. A sum of one million Euro was demanded for his release. Three days after Jakob's disappearance, Magnus Gäfgen, a 32-year-old law student, collected the ransom from the arranged tram stop in Frankfurt during the night. While under observation by the police, he ordered a new Mercedes and booked a holiday abroad. Seventy-six hours after Jakob's disappearance, the police arrested (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  68
    The Influence of Political Regime on State-Level Disciplinary Actions of CPAs Sanctioned by the PCAOB.Abdullah Al-Moshaigeh, Denise Dickins & Julia L. Higgs - 2021 - Journal of Business Ethics 176 (2):325-340.
    We investigate whether enforcement is influenced by politics by comparing the severity of PCAOB sanctions of individual CPAs to the severity of related state-level disciplinary actions imposed by boards of accountancy. Our results provide evidence that when responding to PCAOB sanctions, BOAs under Republican regimes impose less severe penalties than do BOAs under Democratic regimes. Our data and analyses inform the regulatory and enforcement practices of the accounting profession and other professions. Most directly, motivated by improvements in technology (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  36
    Criminal Law at the Margins.Douglas Husak - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (3):381-393.
    I describe how our understanding of some of the central principles long held dear by most criminal theorists may have to be interpreted in light of the need to devise lenient responses for low-level offenders. Several of the most plausible suggestions for how to deal with minor infractions force us to take seriously some ideas that many legal philosophers have tended to resist elsewhere. I briefly touch upon four topics: whether informal can substitute for or count against the appropriate state (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 412