Results for 'Tad Lemieux'

314 found
Order:
  1.  27
    Combat–Débat: Parataxis and the Unavowable Community; or, The Joke.Stuart J. Murray & Tad Lemieux - 2019 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 52 (1):78-85.
    ◆ Writing is per se already violence: the rupture there is in each fragment, the break, the splitting, the tearing of the shred—acute singularity, steely point. And yet this combat is, for patience, debate. The name wears away [s'use], the fragment fragments, erodes.There is much talk today but little speech, or rather, little speech that could be received and responded to absent the vows of the unavowable community of its speakers. There is combat but debate is foreclosed by the absence (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  29
    The Metaphysics of the Material World: Suárez, Descartes, Spinoza.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2019 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This study traces the development of the metaphysics of the material world in early modern thought. It starts with the scholastic innovator Suárez, proceeds to a consideration of Suárez's connections to Descartes, and ends with an examination of Spinoza's fundamental re-conceptualization of the Cartesian material world.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  3. The Stoic life: emotions, duties, and fate.Tad Brennan - 2005 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Tad Brennan explains how to live the Stoic life--and why we might want to. Stoicism has been one of the main currents of thought in Western civilization for two thousand years: Brennan offers a fascinating guide through the ethical ideas of the original Stoic philosophers, and shows how valuable these ideas remain today, both intellectually and in practice. He writes in a lively informal style which will bring Stoicism to life for readers who are new to ancient philosophy. The Stoic (...)
  4.  47
    Suárez and Descartes on the Mode(s) of Union.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2020 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 58 (3):471-492.
    in a january 1642 letter, rené descartes advises his correspondent—his then-follower, the Utrecht medical professor Henricus Regius—to consistently endorse the view that the human mind is related to its body by means of a "substantial union": Whenever the occasion arises, as much privately as publicly, you ought to profess that you believe a human to be a true ens per se and not per accidens and the mind to be really and substantially united to the body not through position or (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  84
    Discours magistériel et discours du maître : l’aporie est-elle surmontable ?Raymond Lemieux - 2013 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 69 (3):483-498.
    Raymond Lemieux | Résumé : Entre le discours du maître et le discours magistériel, la proximité est évidente. Pourtant le magis formant leur élément commun peut aussi bien s’avérer un facteur d’abrutissement, un producteur d’esclave, qu’un porteur d’émancipation. Comment le discours magistériel, qui se veut émancipateur, peut-il gérer cette ambiguïté ? Comment le maître peut-il être un maître de liberté ? L’article interroge tour à tour les pratiques éducatives et les pratiques psychanalytiques qui affrontent le même type d’aporie. Il (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  19
    Early Modern Cartesianisms: Dutch and French Constructions.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2016 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press USA.
    There is a general sense that the philosophy of Descartes was a dominant force in early modern thought. Since the work in the nineteenth century of French historians of Cartesian philosophy, however, there has been no fully contextualized comparative examination of the various receptions of Descartes in different portions of early modern Europe. This study addresses the need for a more current understanding of these receptions by considering the different constructions of Descartes's thought that emerged in the Calvinist United Provinces (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  7. Descartes on Causation.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2006 - Studia Leibnitiana 38 (2):248-250.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  8.  91
    Descartes on Causation.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2007 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    This book is a systematic study of Descartes' theory of causation and its relation to the medieval and early modern scholastic philosophy that provides its proper historical context. The argument presented here is that even though Descartes offered a dualistic ontology that differs radically from what we find in scholasticism, his views on causation were profoundly influenced by scholastic thought on this issue. This influence is evident not only in his affirmation in the Meditations of the abstract scholastic axioms that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  9.  48
    Radical Cartesianism: The French Reception of Descartes.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2002 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This is a book-length study of two of Descartes's most innovative successors, Robert Desgabets and Pierre-Sylvain Regis, and of their highly original contributions to Cartesianism. The focus of the book is an analysis of radical doctrines in the work of these thinkers that derive from arguments in Descartes: on the creation of eternal truths, on the intentionality of ideas, and on the soul-body union. As well as relating their work to that of fellow Cartesians such as Malebranche and Arnauld, the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  10.  11
    The hardest constraint problems: A double phase transition.Tad Hogg & Colin P. Williams - 1994 - Artificial Intelligence 69 (1-2):359-377.
  11.  12
    Propositional Versus Structural Semantic Analyses of Medical Diagnostic Thinking.Madeleine Lemieux & Georges Bordage - 1992 - Cognitive Science 16 (2):185-204.
    Two approaches to the study of diagnostic thinking are compared, one mainly propositional, namely that of Patel and Groen (1986), the other mainly semantic, that of Lemieux and Bordage (1986). Patel and Groen analyzed the linear dimension of cardiologists' discourses while solving a case of acute bacterial endocarditis, that is, the before and after propositional rules. A secondary analysis of two of their pothophysiological protocols is done using structural semantic techniques from Lemieux and Bordage where the vertical dimension (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12. Sensation, Occasionalism, and Descartes' Causal Principles.Tad M. Schmaltz - 1992 - In Phillip D. Cummins (ed.), Minds, Ideas, and Objects: Essays on the Theory of Representation in Modern Philosophy. Ridgeview Publishing Company.
  13. Malebranche and Leibniz on the best of all possible worlds.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 48 (1):28-48.
    In this article I explore Leibniz's claim in the Theodicy that on the essential points Malebranche's theodicy "reduces to" his own view. This judgment may seem to be warranted given that both thinkers emphasize that evils are justified by the fact that they follow from the simple and uniform laws that govern that world which is worthy of divine creation. However, I argue that Leibniz's theodicy differs in several crucial respects from Malebranche's. I begin with a qualified endorsement of Charles (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  4
    Descartes’s Critique of Scholastic Teleology.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2017 - In . pp. 54-73.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  88
    Malebranche's theory of the soul: a Cartesian interpretation.Tad M. Schmaltz - 1996 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book offers a provocative interpretation of the theory of the soul in the writings of the French Cartesian, Nicolas Malebranche (1638-1715). Though recent work on Malebranche's philosophy of mind has tended to emphasize his account of ideas, Schmaltz focuses rather on his rejection of Descartes' doctrine that the mind is better known than the body. In particular, he considers and defends Malebranche's argument that this rejection has a Cartesian basis. Schmaltz reveals that this argument not only provides a fresh (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  16. 13 short pieces, but not the whole [t]ruth.Kristina L. Lemieux - 2006 - Hypatia 21 (1):74-79.
    : This essay is a collection of my experiences of and reflections on being pregnant and choosing to place the child for open adoption. The piece was started late in the term of my pregnancy and completed about a week before the birth.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  46
    What Has Cartesianism To Do with Jansenism?Tad M. Schmaltz - 1999 - Journal of the History of Ideas 60 (1):37-56.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:What Has Cartesianism To Do with Jansenism?Tad M. SchmaltzMy title is modeled on the famous query of the third-century theologian, Tertullian: “What has Athens to do with Jerusalem?” Tertullian’s question asks what pagan Greek learning has to do with the theology of the early Church. By comparison my question asks what philosophical Cartesianism has to do with theological Jansenism, and more specifically what these movements had to do with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18. Descartes on innate ideas, sensation, and scholasticism: The response to Regius.Tad M. Schmaltz - 1997 - In Michael Alexander Stewart (ed.), Studies in seventeenth-century European philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19.  12
    Beyond the bottom line: how business leaders are turning principles into profits.Tad Tuleja - 1985 - New York, NY: Penguin Books.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20.  37
    Brennan on Mitsis on Long.Tad Brennan - 2005 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 43 (S1):250-256.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  34
    (1 other version)Simplicius: on Epictetus' Handbook 1-26.Tad Brennan & Charles Brittain (eds.) - 2002 - Duckworth & Cornell.
    Originally published by Duckworth in 2002.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  29
    Science and man.Tad S. Clements - 1968 - Springfield, Ill.,: Thomas.
  23.  14
    Discernment of Stories.Tad Dunne - 2019 - The Lonergan Review 10:21-42.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  15
    CHAUSSÉ, Gilles, Jean-Jacques Lartigue, premier évêque de Montréal.Raymond Lemieux - 1982 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 38 (2):214-215.
  25.  41
    FALISE, Michel, RÉGNIER, Jérôme, Économie et foiFALISE, Michel, RÉGNIER, Jérôme, Économie et foi.Raymond Lemieux - 1994 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 50 (2):459-460.
  26.  65
    (1 other version)Hume et Bergson, une pratique de la méthode chez Deleuze.René Lemieux - 2009 - Symposium 13 (2):68-96.
    Sous le thème de la « méthode », l’auteur se propose de formuler une éthique de la lecture à partir de Gilles Deleuze. L’analyse est fondée sur un dédoublement de la lecture : d’abord la lecture qu’a fait De-leuze de David Hume tel qu’exprimé dans Empirisme et subjectivité (1953) et celle de Henri Bergson dans Le bergsonisme (1966), ensuite par la lecture que l’auteur fait de ces deux livres de Deleuze. Par l’entremise de l’empirisme (Hume) et de l’intuition (Bergson), l’auteur (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  56
    Introduction.Ernest Lemieux - 1953 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 9 (1):15.
  28.  23
    Introduction générale.Ernest Lemieux - 1953 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 9 (1):11.
  29.  18
    Luther : mythe et réalitéLuther : mythe et réalité.Raymond Lemieux - 1986 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 42 (2):284-285.
  30.  29
    MAISONNEUVE, Henri, L'InquisitionMAISONNEUVE, Henri, L'Inquisition.Raymond Lemieux - 1990 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 46 (2):283-283.
  31.  36
    NADEAU, Jean-Guy, dir., La praxéologie pastorale : orientations et parcoursNADEAU, Jean-Guy, dir., La praxéologie pastorale : orientations et parcours.Raymond Lemieux - 1989 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 45 (3):469-469.
  32.  24
    Paresser, dans les craquelures de la vie.Raymond Lemieux - 2017 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 73 (3):399-413.
    Laziness is a borderline phenomenon. It may cause the withdrawal from any commitment or allow the human being a space and a time for reflexing the conditions of his actions. If it is undoubtedly a capital sin when source of mindless, could not it be also a tool for the self-construction of life and identity? Then how could it play such a role? The paper intends to clarify the possible misunderstanding hidden under this dilemma. For this purpose, it proposes a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  20
    Théologie de l’Écriture et écriture théologique : l’invention de l’Autre.Raymond Lemieux - 2002 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 58 (2):221-241.
    Résumé Au point de départ, l’acte théologique se constitue par la lecture des Écritures. Mais cette lecture, par laquelle se produit un sujet théologien, ne peut elle-même se résoudre que dans une écriture par laquelle ce sujet fait trace, à son tour, de son expérience. Le présent article investigue ces rapports complexes de la théologie aux Écritures et à l’écriture pour tenter d’en définir l’acte théologique comme traversée des textes et production d’un sens. La théologie, argumente-t-il, suppose que le lecteur-écrivain (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  21
    Toward a theory of alienation: futurelessness in financial capitalism.Tad Skotnicki & Kelly Nielsen - 2021 - Theory and Society 50 (6):837-865.
    There is an extensive body of literature detailing the forces behind and experiences of alienation in a modern capitalist world. However, social scientific interest in alienation had become parochial and balkanized by the 1970s. To reconstruct a unifying theory of alienation that addresses general features of capitalism, such as compulsory growth and commodification, and particular phases like financialized capitalism, we begin with the notion of futurelessness. Futurelessness refers to a deficient relationship to the future in which people’s senses of possibility (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35. Spinoza's mediate infinite mode.Tad M. Schmaltz - 1997 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (2):199-235.
    Spinoza's Mediate Infinite Mode TAD M. SCHMALTZ IN PART I of the Ethics, Spinoza argued that a modification is infinite just in case it either "follows from the absolute nature of any attribute of God" or "follows from some attribute of God, as it is modified by such a modification" that is infinite. 1 The main purpose of this argument is to bolster the claim later in this text that a finite modification can follow from a divine attribute only insofar (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  36.  29
    Unseen suffering: slow violence and the phenomenological structure of social problems.Tad Skotnicki - 2019 - Theory and Society 48 (2):299-323.
    Social scientists have severed social problems from the study of framing work in social movements. This article proposes to rejoin problems and framing work via attention to the phenomenological structure of social problems. By describing basic 1) temporal, 2) spatial, and 3) experiential features of social problems, we facilitate comparisons of different kinds of movements across distinct historical periods and regions. The approach is demonstrated via the example of “slow violence” (Nixon 2011)—suffering that develops gradually across time and extends across (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Descartes and Malebranche on mind and mind-body union.Tad M. Schmaltz - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (2):281-325.
  38. What Has History of Science to Do with History of Philosophy?Tad M. Schmaltz - 2013 - In Mogens Laerke, Justin E. H. Smith & Eric Schliesser (eds.), Philosophy and Its History: Aims and Methods in the Study of Early Modern Philosophy. New York, US: Oxford University Press USA.
    In this chapter I consider the relation of history of philosophy to the history of science. I argue that though these two disciplines are naturally linked, they also have special commitments that distinguish each from the other. I begin with the history of the history of science, a discipline that was once allied with philosophy of science but that has increasingly evolved toward social history. Then I consider the debate over whether the history of philosophy is essential for, or rather (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39. Cartesian causation: body–body interaction, motion, and eternal truths.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (4):737-762.
    There is considerable debate among scholars over whether Descartes allowed for genuine body–body interaction. I begin by considering Michael Della Rocca’s recent claim that Descartes accepted such interaction, and that his doctrine of the creation of the eternal truths indicates how this interaction could be acceptable to him. Though I agree that Descartes was inclined to accept real bodily causes of motion, I differ from Della Rocca in emphasizing that his ontology ultimately does not allow for them. This is not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40.  72
    Body-specific representations of spatial location.Tad T. Brunyé, Aaron Gardony, Caroline R. Mahoney & Holly A. Taylor - 2012 - Cognition 123 (2):229-239.
  41.  7
    Refining the phase transition in combinatorial search.Tad Hogg - 1996 - Artificial Intelligence 81 (1-2):127-154.
  42.  47
    The indefinite in the Descartes-More correspondence.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2021 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 29 (3):453-471.
    In this article, I consider Descartes’ enigmatic claim that we must assert that the material world is indefinite rather than infinite. The focus here is on the discussion of this claim in Descartes’ late correspondence with More. One puzzle that emerges from this correspondence is that Descartes insists to More that we are not in a position to deny the indefinite universe has limits, while at the same time indicating that we conceive a contradiction in the notion that the universe (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Pyrrho on the Criterion.Tad Brennan - 1998 - Ancient Philosophy 18 (2):417-434.
    I argue that Pyrrho was an epistemological skeptic, rather than the possessor of a positive metaphysical view.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  44.  76
    Public Health Insurance under a Nonbenevolent State.P. Lemieux - 2008 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 33 (5):416-426.
    This paper explores the consequences of the oft ignored fact that public health insurance must actually be supplied by the state. Depending how the state is modeled, different health insurance outcomes are expected. The benevolent model of the state does not account for many actual features of public health insurance systems. One alternative is to use a standard public choice model, where state action is determined by interaction between self-interested actors. Another alternative—related to a strand in public choice theory—is to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  43
    Quantity and Extension in Suárez and Descartes.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2020 - Vivarium 58 (3):168-190.
    This paper compares the development of the notion of continuous quantity in the work of Francisco Suárez and René Descartes. The discussion begins with a consideration of Suárez’s rejection of the view – common to ‘realists’ such as Thomas Aquinas and ‘nominalists’ such as William of Ockham – that quantity is inseparable from the extension of material integral parts. Crucial here is Suárez’s view that quantified extension exhibits a kind of impenetrability that distinguishes it from other kinds of extension. This (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46. Oxford Philosophical Concepts: Efficient Causation.Tad Schmaltz (ed.) - 2014 - Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Learning from Six Philosophers: Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, Hume.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):367-373.
  48. Platonism and Descartes' View of Immutable Essences.Tad M. Schmaltz - 1991 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 73 (2):129-170.
  49. Occasionalism and mechanism: Fontenelle's objections to Malebranche.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2008 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16 (2):293 – 313.
    It is well known that the French Cartesian Nicolas Malebranche (1638–1715) was both an occasionalist in metaphysics and a mechanist in physics. He consistently argued that God is the only true caus...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  50.  52
    Galileo and Descartes on Copernicanism and the cause of the tides.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 51:70-81.
1 — 50 / 314