Results for 'correction of naming'

968 found
Order:
  1. Names for Ficta, for intentionalia, and for nothing.Alberto Voltolini - 2007 - In María José Frápolli (ed.), Saying, meaning and referring: essays on François Recanati's philosophy of language. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 183-197.
    In his Oratio Obliqua, Oratio Recta, Recanati maintains two main theses regarding meta-representational sentences embedding allegedly empty proper names. The first thesis concerns both belief sentences embedding allegedly empty names and (internal) meta-fictional sentences (i.e., sentences of the form “in the story S, p”) embedding fictional, hence again allegedly empty, names. It says that such sentences primarily have fictive truth-conditions: that is, conditions for their fictional truth. The second thesis is that a fictive ascription of a singular belief, assigning to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  14
    Correction to: Analyzing Leadership Attributes in Faith-Based Organizations: Idealism Versus Reality.Krystin Zigan, YingFei Héliot & Alan Le Grys - 2020 - Journal of Business Ethics 170 (4):759-759.
    The name of the second author was incorrect in the initial online publication. The original article has been corrected.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  23
    A System For Identifying Named Entities in Biomedical Text: How Results From Two Evaluations Reflect on Both the System and the Evaluations.Christopher Manning - unknown
    We present a maximum-entropy based system for identifying Named Entities (NEs) in biomedical abstracts and present its performance in the only two biomedical Named Entity Recognition (NER) comparative evaluations that have been held to date, namely BioCreative and Coling BioNLP. Our system obtained an exact match f-score of 83.2% in the BioCreative evaluation and 70.1% in the BioNLP evaluation. We discuss our system in detail including its rich use of local features, attention to correct boundary identification, innovative use of external (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  14
    Correction to: Moral and Vocational Dilemmas Meet the Common Currency Hypothesis: a Contribution to Value Commensurability.Eleonora Viganò & Edoardo Lombardi Vallauri - 2020 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 11 (1):103-103.
    In the initial online publication, the second author’s given name should have been displayed in full and in the running head the names were not properly abbreviated.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Naming and saying.Wilfrid Sellars - 1962 - Philosophy of Science 29 (1):7-26.
    The essay adopts the Tractarian view that configurations of objects are expressed by configurations of names. Two alternatives are considered: The objects in atomic facts are (1) without exception particulars; (2) one or more particulars plus a universal (Gustav Bergmann). On (1) a mode of configuration is always an empirical relation: on (2) it is the logical nexus of 'exemplification.' It is argued that (1) is both Wittgenstein's view in the Tractatus and correct. It is also argued that exemplification is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  6.  13
    My name is Saajin Singh.Kuljinder Kaur Brar - 2022 - Berkeley: Annick Press. Edited by Samrath Kaur.
    A debut picture book that explores the importance of pronouncing names properly and celebrates cultural identity. Saajin loves his name--he loves it so much that he sees it spelled out in the world around him in his snacks, in the sky and sometimes he even sings it aloud. On his first day of school, Saajin is excited to meet his new classmates, but things take a turn when the teacher mispronounces his name as Say-jin and he is not sure how--or (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  87
    Using Proper Names as Intermediaries Between Labelled Entity Representations.Hans Kamp - 2015 - Erkenntnis 80 (2):263-312.
    This paper studies the uses of proper names within a communication-theoretic setting, looking at both the conditions that govern the use of a name by a speaker and those involved in the correct interpretation of the name by her audience. The setting in which these conditions are investigated is provided by an extension of Discourse Representation Theory, MSDRT, in which mental states are represented as combinations of propositional attitudes and entity representations . The first half of the paper presents the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  8.  38
    Correction to: The Big 5 Personality Traits and Willingness to Justify Unethical Behavior—A Cross-National Examination.Aditya Simha & K. Praveen Parboteeah - 2020 - Journal of Business Ethics 167 (3):473-473.
    The name of the second author was incorrect in the initial online publication. The original article has been corrected.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  37
    Correction to: Scientific Mind and Objective World: Thomas Kuhn Between Naturalism and Apriorism.Thodoris Dimitrakos - 2020 - Erkenntnis 86 (1):255-255.
    In the original publication of the article, the author name in the seventh reference in the reference section has been misspelled. Now the same has been provided in this correction.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  32
    Correction to: Medical Students’ Efforts to Integrate and/or Reclaim Authentic Identity: Insights from a Mask-Making Exercise.Johanna Shapiro, Julie Youm, Michelle Heare, Anju Hurria, Gabriella Miotto, Bao-Nhan Nguyen, Tan Nguyen, Kevin Simonson & Atur Turakhia - 2022 - Journal of Medical Humanities 43 (2):207-207.
    The authors would like to correct a misspelling in the name of one of the authors due to a typographical error. The name should read Atur Turakhia, not Artur Turakhia. This does not change the conclusions or interpretations presented.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  32
    Correction to: Multiple diversity concepts and their ethical-epistemic implications.Daniel Steel, Sina Fazelpour, Kinley Gillette, Bianca Crewe & Michael Burgess - 2018 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 8 (3):781-781.
    The original version of this article unfortunately contained a mistake. The fourth author’s name is Bianca Crewe, not Bianca Crew. The original article has been corrected.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  36
    Learning correction grammars.Lorenzo Carlucci, John Case & Sanjay Jain - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):489-516.
    We investigate a new paradigm in the context of learning in the limit, namely, learning correction grammars for classes of computably enumerable (c.e.) languages. Knowing a language may feature a representation of it in terms of two grammars. The second grammar is used to make corrections to the first grammar. Such a pair of grammars can be seen as a single description of (or grammar for) the language. We call such grammars correction grammars. Correction grammars capture the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  37
    Correction to: Don Ihde: Husserl’s Missing Technologies.Lee Hardy - 2018 - Husserl Studies 34 (3):313-313.
    In the original publication of an article the name “Idhe” occurs incorrectly including in the very beginning, in the title of the review. Now the correct name has been published in this correction.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  26
    Can Linguistic Correctness Provide Us with Categorical Semantic Norms?Sara Papic - 2023 - Phenomenology and Mind 24:182-191.
    Saul Kripke’s paradoxical argument in Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (1982) has generated an extravagant number of responses. A major debate prompted by this book has focused on the plausibility and role of the supposed normative character of meaning; the argument itself is often taken to rely on the assumption that meaning is irreducibly normative. Following Boghossian (1989), the normativity of meaning has been understood as closely tied to the existence of semantic correctness conditions. After a brief introduction to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  17
    Correcting the Doppler Effect.Denis Thomas - 2023 - Science and Philosophy 11 (1):133-139.
    Christian Doppler, an Austrian physicist, described in 1842 the apparent change in frequency of a wave when motion of the source or the observer is involved. Named after him, this change in observational frequencies is known as the Doppler Effect. The formula for calculating the frequency change is taught in universities, textbooks, Youtube, and on the internet. Understanding the Doppler effect is used in applications such as radar. Yet, the formula is wrong, yielding a different result when applying the same (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  23
    Correction to: Dianne Otto : Queering International Law: Possibilities, Alliances, Complicities, Risks: Routledge, 2017, ISBN: 978-1-138-28991-8.Emily Jones - 2019 - Feminist Legal Studies 27 (1):121-121.
    In the original publication of the article, the name “Tamsin Phillipa Paige” has been incorrectly cited throughout the article as “Tasmin Phillipa Page”. The correct name should read as Tamsin Phillipa Paige.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  72
    Names and Pseudonyms.Lloyd Humberstone - 1995 - Philosophy 70 (274):487 - 512.
    Was there such a person as Lewis Carroll? An affirmative answer is suggested by the thought that Lewis Carroll was Charles Dodgson, and since there was certainly such a person as Charles Dodgson, there was such a person as Lewis Carroll. A negative answer is suggested by the thought that in arguing thus, the two names ‘Lewis Carroll’ and ‘Charles Dodgson’ are being inappropriately treated as though they were completely on a par: a pseudonym is, after all, a false or (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18.  29
    Networked names: synonyms in eighteenth-century botany.Bettina Dietz - 2019 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 41 (4):1-20.
    This paper addresses early modern botanical nomenclature, the practices of identifying and publishing synonyms in particular, as a collaborative “information science”. Before Linnaean nomenclature became the lingua franca of botany, it was inevitable that, over time, the same plant was given several names by different people, which created confusion and made communication among botanists increasingly difficult. What names counted as synonyms and actually referred to the same plant had to be identified by meticulously comparing living and dried specimens of this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. (1 other version)Does naming and necessity refute descriptivism?Josep Macià - 1998 - Theoria 13 (3):445-476.
    In Naming and Necessity Saul Kripke offers a number of arguments in order to show that no descriptivist theory of proper names is correct. We present here a certain version of descriptivist theory -we will characterize it as an individual-use reference-fixing descriptivist theory that appeals to descriptions regarding how a name is used by other speakers. This kind of theory can successfully answer all the objections Kripke puts forward in Naming and Necessity. Such sort of descriptivist theory is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  56
    Proper names as connoting expressions.John David Stone - 1982 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):233-239.
    Close attention to the meanings of certain sentences--Counterfactual-Identity sentences--Reveals that no theory in which proper names are simple designators can be a complete and correct semantics of english. An account of connotation is outlined according to which connotation varies with the linguistic environment and with the context of utterance: this accounts for the fact that no proper name is synonymous with a cluster of descriptions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Names for Ficta, for intentionalia, and for nothing.Alberto Voltolini - 2007 - In María José Frápolli (ed.), Saying, meaning and referring: essays on François Recanati's philosophy of language. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 183-197.
    In his Oratio Obliqua, Oratio Recta, Recanati maintains two main theses regarding meta-representational sentences embedding allegedly empty proper names. The first thesis concerns both belief sentences embedding allegedly empty names and (internal) meta-fictional sentences (i.e., sentences of the form “in the story S, p”) embedding fictional, hence again allegedly empty, names. It says that such sentences primarily have fictive truth-conditions: that is, conditions for their fictional truth. The second thesis is that a fictive ascription of a singular belief, assigning to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  54
    Scientific retractions and corrections related to misconduct findings.David B. Resnik & Gregg E. Dinse - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (1):46-50.
    We examined all 208 closed cases involving official findings of research misconduct published by the US Office of Research Integrity from 1992 to 2011 to determine how often scientists mention in a retraction or correction notice that there was an ethical problem with an associated article. 75 of these cases cited at least one published article affected by misconduct for a total of 174 articles. For 127 of these 174, we found both the article and a retraction or (...) statement. Since eight of the 127 published statements consisted of simply the word ‘retracted,’ our analysis focused on the remaining 119 for which a more detailed retraction or correction was published. Of these 119 statements, only 41.2% mentioned ethics at all (and only 32.8% named a specific ethical problem such as fabrication, falsification or plagiarism), whereas the other 58.8% described the reason for retraction or correction as error, loss of data or replication failure when misconduct was actually at issue. Among the published statements in response to an official finding of misconduct (within the time frame studied), the proportion that mentioned ethics was significantly higher in recent years than in earlier years, as was the proportion that named a specific problem. To promote research integrity, scientific journals should consider adopting policies concerning retractions and corrections similar to the guidelines developed by the Committee on Publication Ethics. Funding agencies and institutions should take steps to ensure that articles affected by misconduct are retracted or corrected. (shrink)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  23.  17
    Naming and Believing.James E. Tomberlin - 1986 - Springer Verlag.
    The relationship between thought, language, and the world is an intimate one. When we have an idea or thought about the world and we wish to express that idea or thought to others we utter a sentence or make a statement. If the statement correctly describes the world then it is true. Moreover, it seems as though our ability to have more complex or sophisticated thoughts about the world increases as the complexity of our language or our ability to use (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  5
    Cratylus’ Silence About Linguistic Correctness.Sean Driscoll - 2025 - Ancient Philosophy 45 (1):107-128.
    This article addresses the longstanding puzzle of what Cratylus’ silence means. It argues that Plato’s Cratylus goes silent to convey his position regarding the correctness of names, and it does this by demonstrating how Cratylus is silent in imitation of a literary trope for portraying the significance of a character’s silence. The philosophical payoff of this imitation is that, for Cratylus, correctness consists not in saying, but in showing.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  3
    A Rose by Another Name? Odor Misnaming is Associated with Linguistic Properties.Thomas Hörberg, Murathan Kurfalı, Maria Larsson, Erika Jonsson Laukka, Pawel Herman & Jonas K. Olofsson - 2024 - Cognitive Science 48 (10):e70003.
    Naming common odors is a surprisingly difficult task: Odors are frequently misnamed. Little is known about the linguistic properties of odor misnamings. We test whether odor misnamings of old adults carry information about olfactory perception and its connection to lexical-semantic processing. We analyze the olfactory–semantic content of odor source naming failures in a large sample of older adults in Sweden (n = 2479; age 58–100 years). We investigate whether linguistic factors and semantic proximity to the target odor name (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  34
    Correction to: The Perfect Moral Storm: Diverse Ethical Considerations in the COVID-19 Pandemic.Vicki Xafis, G. Owen Schaefer, Markus K. Labude, Yujia Zhu & Li Yang Hsu - 2020 - Asian Bioethics Review 12 (2):85-85.
    Regrettably, in the original version of this article the name of one of the authors was spelt incorrectly. "Li Yan Hsu" should be "Li Yang Hsu".
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  12
    Correction to: Book Review. [REVIEW]Fergus Green - forthcoming - Law and Philosophy:1-1.
    In the original publication of the article, the corresponding author name was inadvertently missed out. The corresponding author name is ‘‘Fergus Green’’. The original article has been corrected.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  30
    Theopompos Not Theophrastos: Correcting an Attribution in Plutarch Demosthenes 14.4.Brad L. Cook - 2000 - American Journal of Philology 121 (4):537-547.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Theopompos Not Theophrastos:Correcting an Attribution in Plutarch Demosthenes 14.4Brad L. CookModern reconstructions of Theopompos' presentation of Demosthenes are based on five passages, all of which are found in Plutarch's Demosthenes.1 Of these passages, two are favorable to the orator and two are starkly negative, with the fifth being neutral.2 In the negative passages Theopompos attacked the orator with such harshness, branding him unstable, unjust, and unworthy, that the two (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Corrective justice and reputation.Geoffrey Scarre - 2006 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 3 (3):305-319.
    Courts of criminal jurisdiction commonly allow for mitigating circumstances when determining the punishment of convicted wrongdoers. This paper looks at some of the moral issues raised by mitigation, and asks in particular whether the damage that arraignment or conviction does to the good name of a previously well-reputed person may ever reasonably be considered as a circumstance justifying the imposition of a penalty lighter than is standard for the offence. It is argued that making an allowance for the loss of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. 'Latinos', 'hispanics', and 'iberoamericans': Naming or describing?Susana Nuccetelli - 2001 - Philosophical Forum 32 (2):175–188.
    In some ways that have been largely ignored, ethnic-group names might be similar to names of other kinds. If they are, for instance, analogous to proper names, then a correct semantic account of the latter could throw some light on how the meaning of ethnic-group names should be construed. Of course, proper names, together with definite descriptions, belong to the class of singular terms, and an influential view on the semantics of such terms was developed, at the turn of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  68
    How to Use Proper Names.Henri Lauener - 1994 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 49 (1):101-119.
    According to relativized transcendentalism, the meaning of expressions, consisting in their intension and extension, is provided by a set of (syntactical, semantical and pragmatical) rules which prescribe their correct use in a context. We interpret a linguistic system by fixing a domain (of the values of the variables) and by assigning exactly one object to each individual constant and n-tuples of objects to predicates. The theory says that proper names have a purely referential role and that their meaning is therefore (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  14
    How to Use Proper Names.Henri Lauener - 1994 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 49 (1):101-119.
    According to relativized transcendentalism, the meaning of expressions, consisting in their intension and extension, is provided by a set of (syntactical, semantical and pragmatical) rules which prescribe their correct use in a context. We interpret a linguistic system by fixing a domain (of the values of the variables) and by assigning exactly one object to each individual constant and n-tuples of objects to predicates. The theory says that proper names have a purely referential role and that their meaning is therefore (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  19
    "Divine Person" as Analogous Name.Dylan Schrader - 2023 - Nova et Vetera 21 (1):217-237.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:"Divine Person" as Analogous NameDylan SchraderThe position of St. Thomas Aquinas and the Thomistic school that human beings cannot name God and creatures univocally is well-known.1 This includes the term "person," which is predicated of the Trinity, of angels, and of human beings truly but analogically. In contrast, it might seem that, when speaking of the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit in respect of one another, "divine person" must (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Character, proper names, and Frege's Puzzle.Filipe Martone - 2016 - Filosofia Unisinos 17 (1):75-80.
    Kaplan’s solution to the indexical version of Frege’s Puzzle in terms of the character of linguistic expressions has been greatly influential and much discussed. Many philosophers regard it as being correct, or at least as being on the right track. However, little has been said about how character is supposed to apply to proper names, and how it could account for the name version of the Puzzle. In this paper I want to fill this gap. I sketch some solutions to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  7
    Character, proper names, and Frege’s Puzzle.Filipe Martone - 2016 - Filosofia Unisinos 17 (1).
    Kaplan’s (1989a) solution to the indexical version of Frege’s Puzzle in terms of the character of linguistic expressions has been greatly influential and much discussed. Many philosophers regard it as being correct, or at least as being on the right track. However, little has been said about how character is supposed to apply to proper names, and how it could account for the name version of the Puzzle. In this paper I want to fill this gap. I sketch some solutions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  51
    Was Aristotle Named 'Aristotle'?Anne C. Minas - 1976 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 6 (4):643 - 653.
    Yes, Aristotle was named ‘Aristotle’. I want to show that since ‘Aristotle’ is a proper name, this is true by definition. My theory of proper names is a version of Russell's, a theory that a name is equivalent in meaning to definite description which single out the individual, if there is one, to which the name refers. Braithwaite at one time said that the proper name ‘Aristotle’ meant the description ‘the individual named “Aristotle” ’. This theory, which makes it contradictory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. An Observation on Common Names and Proper Names.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (2):73 - 76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name. This contrast is misleading. After all, we might (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Competence and proper names.Diego Marconi - unknown
    This paper is concerned with the semantics of proper names from two different points of view. As everyboy knows, there is a standard account of the semantics of proper names - it is Kripke's account, essentially. And there is a certain amount of neuropsychological research on proper names, or on the mental representation, or processing of proper names -not too small an amount, at this point. There is a certain amount of evidence, and there are a few theories, none of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Dynamic "Might" and Correct Belief.Patrick Skeels - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    Veltman’s test semantics and developments thereof reject the canon about semantic contents and attitude ascriptions in favor of dynamic alternatives. According to these theories the semantic content of a sentence is not a proposition, but a context change potential (CCP). Similarly, beliefs are not taken to be relations between agents and propositions, but agents and CCPs. These deviations from the canon come at the cost of an elegant explanation about the correctness of belief. Standardly, it is taken that the content (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  45
    Living by the Cratylus Hermeneutics and Philosophic Names in the Roman Empire.Harold Tarrant - 2009 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 3 (1):1-25.
    This paper is about an aspect of philosophic life, showing, in the case of one Platonic dialogue in particular, that the texts that later Platonists employed in a quasi-scriptural capacity could influence their lives in important ways. The Cratylus was seen as addressing the question of how names could be regarded as 'correct', raising the role of the name-giver to the level of the law-giver. It begins with the question of how a personal name could be correct. The ancient text (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  30
    Anti-Libidinal Interventions in Sex Offenders: Medical or Correctional?Lisa Forsberg & Thomas Douglas - 2017 - Medical Law Review 24 (4):453-473.
    Sex offenders are sometimes offered or required to undergo pharmacological interventions intended to diminish their sex drive (anti-libidinal interventions or ALIs). In this paper, we argue that much of the debate regarding the moral permissibility of ALIs has been founded on an inaccurate assumption regarding their intended purpose—namely, that ALIs are intended solely to realise medical purposes, not correctional goals. This assumption has made it plausible to assert that ALIs may only permissibly be administered to offenders with their valid consent, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. Epistemicism, parasites, and vague names.Brian Weatherson - 2003 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (2):276 – 279.
    John Burgess has recently argued that Timothy Williamson’s attempts to avoid the objection that his theory of vagueness is based on an untenable metaphysics of content are unsuccessful. Burgess’s arguments are important, and largely correct, but there is a mistake in the discussion of one of the key examples. In this note I provide some alternative examples and use them to repair the mistaken section of the argument.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  43. Is Clayton correct to say that parental power should be constrained in the same way as state power, and for the same reasons?Marie Oldfield - manuscript
    This paper discusses Claytons theory on Comprehensive enrolment of children by their parents. This paper supports Claytons view that we should not enrol children. However, Cameron raises objections which cause problems for the application of this framework. Namely, the cost of giving up a belief, choices made for us in childhood and the application of the PRR (Public Reason Restriction) to the way the parent-child relationship should function. Some modifications to Clayton’s framework and further debate is required to fully address (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  18
    EFL Students' Preferences for Written Corrective Feedback: Do Error Types, Language Proficiency, and Foreign Language Enjoyment Matter?Tiefu Zhang, Xuemei Chen, Jiehui Hu & Pattarapon Ketwan - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Using both quantitative and qualitative approaches, this study investigated the preference of learners of English as a foreign language for four types of written corrective feedback, which are often discussed in the literature, on grammatical, lexical, orthographic, and pragmatic errors. In particular, it concerned whether such preference is influenced by two learner variables, namely, foreign language enjoyment and proficiency level. The preference for selective vs. comprehensive WCF was also examined. The participants in the study were 117 University students in a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  74
    Correction to: Pain priors, polyeidism, and predictive power: a preliminary investigation into individual differences in ordinary thought about pain.Harriet Wilkinson, Tim V. Salomons, Deepak Ravindran, Richard Harrison, Nat Hansen, Sarah A. Fisher & Emma Borg - 2021 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 44 (1):101-102.
    According to standard philosophical and clinical understandings, pain is an essentially mental phenomenon. In a challenge to this standard conception, a recent burst of empirical work in experimental philosophy, such as that by Justin Sytsma and Kevin Reuter, purports to show that people ordinarily conceive of pain as an essentially bodily phenomenon—specifically, a quality of bodily disturbance. In response to this bodily view, other recent experimental studies have provided evidence that the ordinary concept of pain is more complex than previously (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. “Logical Positivism”—“Logical Empiricism”: What's in a Name?Thomas Uebel - 2013 - Perspectives on Science 21 (1):58-99.
    Do the terms “logical positivism” and “logical empiricism” mark a philosophically real and significant distinction? There is, of course, no doubt that the first term designates the group of philosophers known as the Vienna Circle, headed by Moritz Schlick and including Rudolf Carnap, Herbert Feigl, Philipp Frank, Hans Hahn, Otto Neurath, Friedrich Waismann and others. What is debatable, however, is whether the name “logical positivism” correctly distinguishes their doctrines from related ones called “logical empiricism” that emerged from the Berlin Society (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  47.  21
    The Markus way with dichotomies: Corrective and distributive justice.Arthur Glass - 2020 - Thesis Eleven 160 (1):43-57.
    How should we understand the categorical distinction Aristotle draws between praxis and poesis? If this distinction gains its meaning only in a specific social and cultural context, what does this tell us about another famous Aristotelian distinction, namely, the distinction he draws between two types of justice: corrective and distributive? In particular, what is the orienting role of this distinction (and what should we make of this) in accounts of justice based on Kantian right and accounts based on Rawls’ principles (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  25
    ‘IP’ Moral Rights Breaches are Deception Offences, Not Property Offences: Correcting a Category Error.James McKeahnie - 2016 - Res Publica 22 (2):193-207.
    In March of 2014 Nature Publishing Group, responsible for the publication of journals such as Nature and ScientificAmerican, was subject to criticism for its requirement that contributing authors waive their moral rights in relation to their published articles. Some of the rights included under the umbrella term ‘moral rights’ are the right to have any copies of one’s work reproduced accurately and without alteration; the right to the accurate attribution of one’s work under one’s own name; and the right not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Kripke’s Puzzle and Belief ‘Under’ a Name.Alan McMichael - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (1):105 - 125.
    Recently Saul Kripke has drawn attention to a puzzle about belief and proper names, a puzzle of which philosophers have been aware for a long time, but which has never been completely resolved. Kripke gives a new, bilingual illustration of the puzzle:1 Pierre, while living in his native France, learns much about the city of London, which he calls ‘Londres,’ and comes to believe something which he would express in French with the words, ‘Londres est jolie.’ Using standard principle of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  30
    The Undercutter, the Woodcutter, and Greek Demon Names Ending in -tomos (Hom. Hymn to Dem 228-29).Christopher A. Faraone - 2001 - American Journal of Philology 122 (1):1-10.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Undercutter, the Woodcutter, and Greek Demon Names Ending in -tomos (Hom. Hymn to Dem 228-29)Christopher A. FaraoneEarly in the homeric Hymn to Demeter, the disguised goddess, when offered employment as a nurse for a young child, responds with the following boast about her knowledge of protective magic (lines 227-30):1228 M: Ignarra, DelatteI will nurse him, and I do not expect—through any weak-mindedness of his nurse—that witchcraft or an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 968