Results for 'legitimate expectations'

965 found
Order:
  1.  33
    Legitimate Expectations in Theory, Practice, and Punishment.Matt Matravers - 2017 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 4 (2):307-323.
    This paper is concerned with how we ought to think about legitimate expectations in the non-ideal, ‘real’ world. In one (dominant) strand of contemporary theories of justice, justice requires not that each gets what she deserves, but that each gets that to which she is entitled in accordance with what Rawls calls ‘the public rules that specify the scheme of cooperation’. However, that is true only if those public rules are part of a fully just scheme and it (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  36
    Legitimate Expectations, Legal Transitions, and Wide Reflective Equilibrium.Fergus Green - 2017 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 4 (2):177-205.
    Recent scholarly attention to ‘legitimate expectations’ and their role in legal transitions has yielded widely varying principles for distinguishing between legitimate and non-legitimate expectations. This article suggests that methodological reflection may facilitate substantive progress in the debate. Specifically, it proposes and defends the use of a wide reflective equilibrium methodology for constructing, justifying and critiquing theories of legitimate expectations and other kinds of normative theories about legal transitions. The methodology involves three levels of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  62
    Legitimate Expectations, Historical Injustice, and Perverse Incentives for Settlers.Timothy Waligore - 2016-0032 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 4 (2):207-228.
    This article argues against privileging the expectations of settlers over those of dispossessed peoples. I assume in this article that historical rights to occupancy do not persist through all changes in circumstances, but a theory of justice should reduce perverse incentives to unjustly settle on land in hopes of legitimating occupancy. Margaret Moore, in her 2015 book, A Political Theory of Territory, tries to balance these intuitions through an argument based on legitimate expectations. I argue that Moore’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4.  1
    A Theory of Legitimate Expectations for Public Administration.Alexander Brown - 2017 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    It is an unfortunate but unavoidable feature of even well-ordered democratic societies that governmental administrative agencies often create legitimate expectations (procedural or substantive) on the part of non-governmental agents (individual citizens, groups, businesses, organizations, institutions, and instrumentalities) but find themselves unable to fulfil those expectations for reasons of justice, the public interest, severe financial constraints, and sometimes harsh political realities. How governmental administrative agencies, operating on behalf of society, handle the creation and frustration of legitimate (...) implicates a whole host of values that we have reason to care about, including under non-ideal conditions-not least justice, fairness, autonomy, the rule of law, responsible uses of power, credible commitments, reliance interests, security of expectations, stability, democracy, parliamentary supremacy, and legitimate authority. -/- This book develops a new theory of legitimate expectations for public administration drawing on normative arguments from political and legal theory. Brown begins by offering a new account of the legitimacy of legitimate expectations. He argues that it is the very responsibility of governmental administrative agencies for creating expectations that ought to ground legitimacy, as opposed to the justice or the legitimate authority of those agencies and expectations. He also clarifies some of the main ways in which agencies can be responsible for creating expectations. Moreover, he argues that governmental administrative agencies should be held liable for losses they directly cause by creating and then frustrating legitimate expectations on the part of non-governmental agents and, if liable, have an obligation to make adequate compensation payments in respect of those losses. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  90
    How legitimate expectations matter in climate justice.Lukas H. Meyer & Pranay Sanklecha - 2014 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 13 (4):369-393.
    Expectations play an important role in how people plan their lives and pursue their projects. People living in highly industrialized countries share a way of life that comes with high levels of emissions. Their expectations to be able to continue their projects imply their holding expectations to similarly high future levels of personal emissions. We argue that the frustration or undermining of these expectations would cause them significant harm. Further, the article investigates under what conditions people (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  6.  44
    Legitimate Expectations and Land.Margaret Moore - 2017 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 4 (2):229-255.
    This paper focuses on land as a domain in which legitimate expectations can give rise to entitlements. The central argument is that people are connected to other people and to projects, which are symbolically and materially rooted in particular places. This gives rise to an interest – an interest that is sufficiently weighty that it imposes obligations on other people – to protect stability of place. There are two ways in which legitimate expectations structure argument about (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  7.  82
    Moral desert, fairness and legitimate expectations in the market.N.-H. Hsieh - 2000 - Journal of Political Philosophy 8 (1):91–114.
    Do people morally deserve what they earn in the market? More specifically, can people legitimately claim to deserve what they earn in the market in a way that counts against redistributing those earnings? As most liberal political philosophers do, I argue that the answer is no. Unlike many of these philosophers, however, I do not focus on whether or not people can be deserving. Instead, I focus on the relationship between social institutions and moral desert, and advance two claims. First, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  8.  51
    Conventionalism and Legitimate Expectations.C. M. Melenovsky - 2020 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 18 (2):1-23.
    To be a conventionalist about a specific obligation or right is to believe that the obligation or right is dependent on the existence of a social practice. A conventionalist about property, for example, believes that a moral right to property is generated by conventional norms rather than by any natural right. One problem with dominant conventionalist theories is that they do not adequately justify conventional moral claims. They can justify why it is wrong to steal, for example, but they do (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  65
    Justifying Compensation for Frustrated Legitimate Expectations.Alexander Brown - 2011 - Law and Philosophy 30 (6):699-728.
    That government agencies and public bodies can be liable for damages when they induce and then frustrate people’s legitimate expectations is an important and distinctive feature of administrative law in Europe. This article sets out to establish a set of moral principles and ideals that might justify this legal institution. The notion of security of expectations found in the work of utilitarian writers provides a starting point. Having examined the strengths and weaknesses of this approach, I then (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  10.  20
    Arendt and the Legitimate Expectation for Hospitality and Membership Today.Michael D. Weinman - 2018 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 5 (1):127-149.
    What does the growing tide of displaced persons today teach us about the ongoing paradoxes of human rights regimes, which rely on the particular sovereignty of nation-states for their constitution and application but are framed and normatively justified as universal? Working with Arendt’s defense of ‘the right to have rights’ in response to the problem of statelessness which is the practical lynchpin of these historical and theoretical tensions, I specify that and why any person on earth, regardless of their legal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  51
    Guarantee of Principles of Legitimate Expectations, Legal Certainty and Legal Security in the Territorial Planning Process.Birutė Pranevičienė & Kristina Mikalauskaitė-Šostakienė - 2012 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 19 (2):643-656.
    The article discusses the issue of realisation of the principles of legitimate expectations, legal certainty and legal security in the specific area of administrative activity – detailed territorial planning process. During this long and complex process, it is very important to ensure the protection of personal constitutional rights and guarantee the security of legitimate expectations, legal certainty and other essential principles. The article analyses the circumstances conditioning violation of the principles of legitimate expectations, legal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  50
    Introduction to the Special Issue on Legitimate Expectations.Lukas H. Meyer, Thomas Pölzer & Pranay Sanklecha - 2017 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 4 (2):173-175.
    In this short introduction, we will briefly sketch some central features of the problem of legitimate expectations and then lead over to the papers of our special issue.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. NIMBYism and Legitimate Expectations.Travis Quigley - 2023 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 40 (4):708-724.
    An increasing portion of contemporary politics revolves around a set of claims made by those (typically derisively) referred to as NIMBYs. Despite its practical significance, NIMBYism has not received significant attention in academic philosophy. I attempt a charitable but limited reconstruction of NIMBYism in terms of legitimate expectations. I argue that, despite NIMBY expectations being somewhat vague and at least moderately unjust, they may be legitimate. This does not imply that they are decisive, or entail a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  34
    Legal Transitions without Legitimate Expectations.Fergus Green - 2020 - Journal of Political Philosophy 28 (4):397-420.
    Journal of Political Philosophy, EarlyView.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  67
    A Theory of Legitimate Expectations.Alexander Brown - 2017 - Journal of Political Philosophy 25 (4):435-460.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  16. Distributive justice and legitimate expectations.Allen Buchanan - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 28 (6):419 - 425.
  17.  33
    Institutions, Automation, and Legitimate Expectations.Jelena Belic - 2024 - The Journal of Ethics 28 (3):505-525.
    Debates concerning digital automation are mostly focused on the question of the availability of jobs in the short and long term. To counteract the possible negative effects of automation, it is often suggested that those at risk of technological unemployment should have access to retraining and reskilling opportunities. What is often missing in these debates are implications that all of this may have for individual autonomy understood as the ability to make and develop long-term plans. In this paper, I argue (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  84
    Rawls, Buchanan, and the Legal Doctrine of Legitimate Expectations.Alexander Brown - 2012 - Social Theory and Practice 38 (4):617-644.
    The article responds to an overlooked objection put by Allen Buchanan to John Rawls’s theory of justice: that implementing the Difference Principle over time may require gross and frequent disruptions of people’s framing and execution of long-term plans. Having strengthened Buchanan’s objection to resolve significant weaknesses in his main counterexample, I argue that the best response to this objection draws on the concept of the rule of law, specifically, the legal doctrine of legitimate expectations, which can be found (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  19.  89
    The Illusion of Merit and the Demons of Economic Meritocracy: Which are the Legitimate Expectations of the Market?Luigino Bruni & Paolo Santori - 2021 - Journal of Business Ethics 176 (3):415-427.
    Meritocracy is gaining momentum in public discourse, being close to the determinants of people’s demand of social justice. Conversely, in Academia meritocracy is the object of harsh critiques. The meritocratic rhetoric brings people to overlook the factors which contributed to their success over their individual actions, legitimating socioeconomic inequalities. Recently, it has been argued that market-driven societies foster the problems related to meritocracy. The concept of merit, conceived as the value of the individual contribution to the common good of society, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  24
    Multilingualism, Divergent Authentic Versions of a Legal Rule and Legitimate Expectations Of Individuals.Rafał Mańko - 2016 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 45 (1):141-159.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric Jahrgang: 45 Heft: 1 Seiten: 141-159.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  6
    Do expectations of fossil fuel owners matter?Rutger Lazou - 2024 - Journal of Global Ethics 20 (2):232-250.
    To avoid the disastrous effects of climate change, a rapid and drastic transition toward a low-carbon society and economy is required. This transition imposes significant transitional losses on some agents given the benefits they can no longer realize. In economic terms, it leads to the stranding of their assets. This article investigates whether fossil fuel owners could refer to their expectations about the benefits of producing their reserves to justify transitional measures such as exemptions from new rules or financial (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Legitimate, but unjust; just, but illegitimate.Silje A. Langvatn - 2016 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 42 (2):132-153.
    The article offers a reconstruction of John Rawls views on political legitimacy, from A Theory of Justice to his late writings on political liberalism. It argues that Rawls had three conceptions of legitimacy, not two as one might expect based on the distinction between his two major works. Its argument is that the most radical change in Rawls’ thinking about legitimacy occurs in ‘Introduction to the Paperback Edition’ and ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’. Here Rawls assumes that there can (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  23.  18
    Interpersonal helping in the workplace: social expectation predicts anticipated guilt and intention to help a coworker.Claudia Gherghel - 2024 - Cognition and Emotion 38 (7):986-1000.
    Promoting interpersonal helping among coworkers is an important aim for any organisation that cares about employee well-being. Drawing on guilt aversion hypothesis, this research focuses on the power of social expectations in promoting prosocial behaviour among employees and investigates the role of anticipated guilt for failing to meet coworkers’ expectations. In two preregistered studies, the effect of beneficiary expectation on benefactors’ anticipated guilt and intention to help was investigated. In Study 1, Japanese participants (n = 284) recalled a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Natural Hazards and the Normative Significance of Expectations in Protecting Alpine Communities.Thomas Pölzler, Florian Ortner, Oliver Sass & Lukas Meyer - 2017 - Geophysical Research Abstracts: Abstracts of the European Geosciences Union General Assembly.
  25.  46
    Legitimate Power, Illegitimate Automation: The problem of ignoring legitimacy in automated decision systems.Jake Iain Stone & Brent Mittelstadt - forthcoming - The Association for Computing Machinery Conference on Fairness, Accountability, and Transparency 2024.
    Progress in machine learning and artificial intelligence has spurred the widespread adoption of automated decision systems (ADS). An extensive literature explores what conditions must be met for these systems' decisions to be fair. However, questions of legitimacy -- why those in control of ADS are entitled to make such decisions -- have received comparatively little attention. This paper shows that when such questions are raised theorists often incorrectly conflate legitimacy with either public acceptance or other substantive values such as fairness, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  60
    Individual Expectations and Climate Justice.Lukas H. Meyer & Pranay Sanklecha - 2011 - Analyse & Kritik 33 (2):449-472.
    Many people living in highly industrialised countries and elsewhere emit greenhouse gases at a certain high level as a by-product of their activities, and they expect to be able to continue to emit at that level. This level is far above the just per capita level. We investigate whether that expectation is legitimate and permissible. We argue that the expectation is epistemically legitimate. Given certain assumptions, we can also think of it as politically legitimate. Also, the expectation (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  27.  28
    The failed institutionalization of “complexity science”: A focus on the Santa Fe Institute’s legitimization strategy.Fabrizio Li Vigni - 2020 - History of Science 59 (3):344-369.
    “Complexity sciences” are an interdisciplinary and transnational domain of study that aims at modeling natural and social “complex systems.” They appeared in the 1970s in Europe and the United States, but were boosted in the mid-1980s by the Santa Fe Institute (SFI) under the formula of “science of complexity.” This small but famous institution is the object of the present article. According to their promissory ambitions and to the enthusiastic claims of some scientific journalists, complexity sciences were going to revolutionize (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28. Why and Where to Fund Carbon Capture and Storage.Kian Mintz-Woo & Joe Lane - 2021 - Science and Engineering Ethics 27 (6):70.
    This paper puts forward two claims about funding carbon capture and storage. The first claim is that there are moral justifications supporting strategic investment into CO2 storage from global and regional perspectives. One argument draws on the empirical evidence which suggests carbon capture and storage would play a significant role in a portfolio of global solutions to climate change; the other draws on Rawls' notion of legitimate expectations and Moellendorf's Anti-Poverty principle. The second claim is that where to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  97
    Do Promises Towards Fossil Fuel Owners Matter?Rutger Lazou - 2024 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 11 (1):169-194.
    While the energy transition is needed more than ever, for some agents it brings significant losses. This article investigates whether fossil fuel owners could refer to promises to avoid having their assets stranded. It explains how authors, in the context of just transitions, have argued for the normative relevance of Rawlsian legitimate expectations, which refer to promissory entitlements. However, it argues that the normative relevance of promises towards fossil fuel owners is limited, because there are only few promises (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. How Autonomy Can Legitimate Beneficial Coercion.Lucie White - 2017 - In Jakov Gather, Tanja Henking, Alexa Nossek & Jochen Vollmann (eds.), Beneficial Coercion in Psychiatry?: Foundations and Challenges. Münster: Mentis. pp. 85-99.
    Respect for autonomy and beneficence are frequently regarded as the two essential principles of medical ethics, and the potential for these two principles to come into conflict is often emphasised as a fundamental problem. On the one hand, we have the value of beneficence, the driving force of medicine, which demands that medical professionals act to protect or promote the wellbeing of patients or research subjects. On the other, we have a principle of respect for autonomy, which demands that we (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31. The reality of moral expectations: A sociology of situated judgement.Luc Boltanski & Laurent Thévenot - 2000 - Philosophical Explorations 3 (3):208 – 231.
    The paper offers a modelling of the sense of justice as it is displayed in ordinary situated disputes. While this model accounts for a plurality of legitimate forms of evaluation which are used in the process of critique and justification, it escapes a relativism of values by demonstrating that all these forms satisfy a set of common requirements. The reasonable character of the everyday sense of justice is also anchored in a reality test involving the engagement of objects which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  32.  15
    Revelation Remembered and Expected: Memory, Anticipation and Agency in the Early Barth.Bryan L. Wagoner - 2010 - Journal for the History of Modern Theology/Zeitschrift für Neuere Theologiegeschichte 17 (1):112-129.
    The early theology of Karl Barth exhibits a seemingly incongruous emphasis on concepts like “origins” and “memory,” which would seem to suggest a point of contact between God and humanity. Although memory and anticipation are both ambiguous and tend towards self-reference, this article suggests that revelation is mediated through this ambiguity in Barth's theology through the early 1930s. Recollection can legitimately function as the basis of individual and ecclesial anticipation only when it is interpreted through the lens of the character (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. In defence of normic de minimis expected utility theory.Martin Smith - forthcoming - Logique Et Analyse.
    In a recent paper, Björn Lundgren and H. Orri Stefánsson (forthcoming) present three objections to normic de minimis expected utility theory (NDEUT) – a decision theoretic framework defended in Smith (2024). In this paper, I respond to these objections and outline some possible ways in which NDEUT might be modified or further developed. Like any de minimis framework, NDEUT employs a risk threshold to sort possibilities into those that must be considered when making a decision, and those that can be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  30
    The Moral Entitlements of Future Persons: Expectancies and Prospective Beneficiaries.Andre Santos Campos - 2024 - The Journal of Ethics 28 (1):125-143.
    This paper develops a future-oriented and person-centred normative argument based on expectancies that is immune to most of the problems identified in the rights of future persons. The argument unfolds in four parts. The first draws on the notion of expectancies present in inheritance law and maintains that it is possible to formulate a rule of prospective beneficiaries that correlates with entitlements and legitimate claims without necessarily acquiring the status of rights. The second extends expectancies to future persons and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. The puzzle of competitive fairness.Oisin Suttle - 2022 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 21 (2):190-227.
    Politics, Philosophy & Economics, Volume 21, Issue 2, Page 190-227, May 2022. There is a sense of fairness that is distinctive of markets. This is fairness among economic competitors, competitive fairness. We regularly make judgments of competitive fairness about market participants, public policies and institutions. However, it is not clear to what these judgments refer, or what moral significance they have. This paper offers a rational reconstruction of competitive fairness in terms of non-domination. It first identifies competitive fairness as a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  12
    Freedom of Religion and Non-discrimination Based on Gender Identity and Sexual Orientation in Ukraine: Corporate Policy Commitments in Situations of Conflicting Social Expectations.Tamara Horbachevska, Olena Uvarova & Dmytro Vovk - 2024 - Human Rights Review 25 (2):205-231.
    Conflicting social expectations in a particular state affect the interpretation and implementation of international human rights law. Ideological, religious, and legal factors related to the protection of freedom of religion or belief (FoRB) and freedom from discrimination based on sexual orientation and gender identity (SOGI) in Ukraine put businesses under social pressure. Businesses thus face a legitimate dilemma whether to follow national social expectations perceiving FoRB and freedom from discrimination based on SOGI as rights in conflict or (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  15
    On Sovereignty, Legitimacy, and Solidarity Or: How Can a Solidaristic Idea of Legitimate Sovereignty Be Justified?Sergio Dellavalle - 2015 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 16 (2):367-398.
    The traditional concept of sovereignty is largely independent of democratic legitimacy and completely indifferent to any obligation towards non-national citizens. But can this traditional concept meet the normative expectations of a post-traditional understanding of political authority as well as the challenges of an ever more interconnected world? In order to respond to this question, the Article analyzes the conceptual presuppositions that lie at the basis of the notion of “sovereignty,” first regarding its sources, and second regarding the ideas of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  12
    Balance of a generation: Continuity of the intellectual self-legitimation strategies in the late production of Manuel Ugarte.Marcos Olalla - 2013 - Estudios de Filosofía Práctica E Historia de Las Ideas 15 (1):65-74.
    Destacamos el balance ugarteano de la contribución histórica del modernismo hispanoamericano. El lugar que ocupa la llamada “generación de Darío” en la historia intelectual de América Latina es significativo por su papel determinante en la construcción de la figura del intelectual latinoamericano. La dinámica estatuida por la modernización continental a fines del siglo XIX y principios del XX promovió la autonomización del campo literario. Este hecho produjo una serie de modificaciones de la práctica de los intelectuales que operó como condición (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  29
    Official Disobedience: Bureaucrats & Unjust Laws.Mario I. Juarez-Garcia - 2024 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 18 (3):743-763.
    A legitimate expectation in a liberal democracy is that public officials enforce the law regardless of its content; when they don’t do so, their actions tend to be publicly condemned. This expectation puts street-level bureaucrats in a moral dilemma when they consider that a certain law is unjust: either they don’t enforce the law and violate their duties to the citizenry, or they enforce it and become complicit in injustices. This paper argues for the legal permission of public officials (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  98
    Some Reflections upon the Supposed Moral Distinction between Terrorism and the Legitimate Use of Military Force.Simon Glynn - 2007 - The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 1:207-211.
    Defining "terrorism" as the intentional targeting of non-combatant civilians, the paper argues that, other things being equal, it is not possible to effectively distinguish morally between "terrorism" and use of military power against combatant targets which might reasonably be expected to produce some guesstimable quantity of "collateral" or non-combatant civilian casualties; that it is upon the expected likely consequences of actions rather than upon the intentions underlying them, that actors should be morally judged. Furthermore I argue that other attempts to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  37
    Ideals and institutions: Hans Kelsen's political theory.Gabriele De Angelis - 2009 - History of Political Thought 30 (3):524-546.
    Well known as a theorist of law as well as the main drafter of the 1920 Austrian Constitution, Hans Kelsen's contribution to political theory has been paid considerably less attention. Yet not only do his writings on politics offer a significant picture of the 1920s political dilemmas of both the German Weimar Republic and post- war Austria, they also can be of considerable importance for contemporary political theory in as far as Kelsen opens up new perspectives on the links between (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  21
    Apparent Authority in Positive Law and Court Practice.Vytautas Pakalniškis & Vaidas Jurkevičius - 2011 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 18 (4):1443-1466.
    According to the general rule explaining apparent authority, if the behaviour of a principal gives reasonable grounds for the third party to think that the principal has appointed the other person to be his agent, contracts concluded by the third party in the principal’s name shall be binding on the principal, notwithstanding the fact that the agent was not authorised by the principal to conclude particular contracts. In the absence of evidence of apparent authority the agent shall have to redress (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Two models of models in biomedical research.Hugh LaFollette & Niall Shanks - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (179):141-160.
    Biomedical researchers claim there is significant biomedical information about humans which can be discovered only through experiments on intact animal systems (AMA p. 2). Although epidemiological studies, computer simulations, clinical investigation, and cell and tissue cultures have become important weapons in the biomedical scientists' arsenal, these are primarily "adjuncts to the use of animals in research" (Sigma Xi p. 76). Controlled laboratory experiments are the core of the scientific enterprise. Biomedical researchers claim these should be conducted on intact biological systems, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  44.  17
    Legacies of Historical Injustice: What is Owed to the Victims of Past Injustices? Introduction to the Special Issue.Santiago Truccone - 2024 - Res Publica 30 (4):643-661.
    This introduction and the contributors to this volume advance the debate on the normative relevance of historical injustice. This introduction shows that discussions on this topic should consider four aspects: first, the temporal dimension of justice; second, the connection between current claimants for reparations and the putative duty-bearers with the original perpetrators and victims of historical injustice; third, how changes in circumstances might affect what is considered just; and fourth, the appropriate form of reparation. The introduction provides an overview of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  38
    Not All Political Lies Are Morally Equal.C. M. Melenovsky - 2018 - Journal of Social Philosophy 49 (2):294-314.
    This paper examines the conflict between conventional and non-conventional moral obligations by focusing on the specific case of political lies. It argues that political candidates are under a conventional obligation to try and win their election, and sometimes the most moral way to discharge this obligation involves lying. In such cases, candidates face a conflict between the conventional obligation to try and win and the non-conventional obligation to not lie. Oftentimes, candidates that face this conflict should lie because because voters, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  18
    Entrepreneurship and Progress: The Need for a Greater Integration of Kirzner's and Hayek's Insights.Pierre Garello - 2002 - Journal des Economistes Et des Etudes Humaines 12 (2).
    To improve on the argument presented by classical economists, many authors have tried to rely as much as possible on a value-free approach. In this paper, reasons to reject the propositions made by neoclassical economists are briefly recalled. We then turn toward Kirzner’s proposition which is to evaluate a policy, or a rule, according to the extent to which it promotes coordination. This proposition, however, must also be rejected because, if it introduces some dynamics in the picture, it is a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  37
    From method to hermeneutics: which epistemological framework for narrative medicine?Camille Abettan - 2017 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 38 (3):179-193.
    The past 10 years have seen considerable developments in the use of narrative in medicine, primarily through the emergence of the so-called narrative medicine. In this article, I question narrative medicine’s self-understanding and contend that one of the most prominent issues is its lack of a clear epistemological framework. Drawing from Gadamer’s work on hermeneutics, I first show that narrative medicine is deeply linked with the hermeneutical field of knowledge. Then I try to identify which claims can be legitimately expected (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  48.  83
    Special Issue: "Business Ethics in a Global Economy".Oliver F. Williams - 2004 - Business Ethics Quarterly 14 (4):755-774.
    The UN Global Compact is a voluntary initiative designed to help fashion a more humane world by enlisting business to follow ten principles concerning human rights, labor, the environment, and corruption. Although the four-year-old Compact is a relatively successful initiative, having signed up over eleven hundred companies and more than two hundred of the large multinationals, and having begun some important projects on globalization issues, there is a serious problem in that very few of the major U.S. companies have joined. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  49.  8
    Self-Determination in Health Care: A Property Approach to the Protection of Patients' Rights.Leroy C. Edozien - 2015 - Burlington, VT, USA: Routledge.
    This book proposes an alternative to the consent model which is currently at the heart of patient self-determination and which is shown here to have fundamental flaws that constrain its effectiveness. The proposed model is a property model in which the patient’s bodily integrity is protected from unauthorised invasion, and their legitimate expectation to be provided with the relevant information to make an informed decision is taken to be a proprietary right. This model enables the courts to overcome the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Should have known.Sanford C. Goldberg - 2017 - Synthese 194 (8):2863-2894.
    In this paper I will be arguing that there are cases in which a subject, S, should have known that p, even though, given her state of evidence at the time, she was in no position to know it. My argument for this result will involve making two claims. The uncontroversial claim is this: S should have known that p when another person has, or would have, legitimate expectations regarding S’s epistemic condition, the satisfaction of these expectations (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
1 — 50 / 965