Results for 'rules of a practice'

969 found
Order:
  1.  32
    Does "obeying a rule is a practice" imply a community view of language?Patricia H. Werhane - 1989 - Metaphilosophy 20 (2):134–151.
  2. A Practical Explication of the Knowledge Rule of Informative Speech Acts.Christoph Kelp - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 21 (3):367-383.
    This paper defends the knowledge rule of informative speech acts. It is argued that Edward Craig's insightful practical explication of the concept of knowledge can be extended to motivate the knowledge rule. A number of problem cases for the knowledge rule are addressed and accommodated.
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  3. Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning.Simon Blackburn - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press UK.
    Simon Blackburn puts forward a compelling original philosophy of human motivation and morality. He maintains that we cannot get clear about ethics until we get clear about human nature. So these are the sorts of questions he addresses: Why do we behave as we do? Can we improve? Is our ethics at war with our passions, or is it an upshot of those passions? Blackburn seeks the answers in an exploration of guilt, shame, disgust, and other moral emotions; he draws (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   345 citations  
  4. Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reason.Simon Blackburn - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 51 (202):110-114.
  5. Ruling passions: A theory of practical reasoning.Michael E. Bratman - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):586-589.
    The title of this rich, wide-ranging, and rewarding book alludes both to the idea that passions rule, and to the thought that we rule our passions. Blackburn offers a conception of both, one broadly in the spirit of Hume and Adam Smith.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  6. Clinical Bioethics: Analysis of a Practice.Lisa Marie Rasmussen - 2003 - Dissertation, Rice University
    This project is a philosophical analysis of the practice of bioethics consultation---what might be called the philosophy of bioethics. It assesses claims made about the purposes and appropriate aims of the field, in order to establish whether an identifiable conceptual unity underlies the practice. The conclusion is that no such unity exists. ;The project begins by assessing the history of the field, in the hope that a historical analysis will explain why the field arose at all, which reason (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  5
    Golden Rules of Social Philosophy; Or, a New System of Practical Ethics.R. Phillips & James Adlard - 2023 - Legare Street Press.
    First published in 1865, this book puts forth a new ethical system that aims to provide practical guidance on how to live a good life based on reason, empathy, and social responsibility. The author argues that traditional religious and philosophical systems have failed to keep up with the changing social and economic conditions of modern life and proposes a set of principles that are grounded in the needs and aspirations of ordinary people. The book covers a wide range of topics, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  7
    Rules of Islamic creed ''Aqidah'' Between Theory and Practical (A Study of creed Issues According to Ash'arites).Mohammed Adel Masoud Mohammed - forthcoming - Evolutionary Studies in Imaginative Culture:786-802.
    The attention to the deductive method began with Imam Al-Ash’ari and the establishment of the rules of theorizing from the first moment of the emergence of the Ash’ari school of thought at the hands of the founder of the school of thought, Abu Al-Hasan Al-Ash’ari, and the scholars who followed after him who wrote theological works. This reflects the great care of the Ash’arism in rooting and theorizing the methods of theory, and setting the methodological rules of reasoning, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  19
    The rules of the rationality of practical discourse in the light of ethics of discourse: An analysis of Robert Alexy’s proposal.Guillermo Lariguet - 2019 - Ethics and Bioethics (in Central Europe) 9 (1-2):17-25.
    The author discusses the rational argumentation of the values from a proposal defended by the legal philosopher Robert Alexy. The paper shows that discourse for Alexy is essentially a regulated activity. A model of certain rules ensure the rationality and correctness of practical discourse oriented towards resolving conflicts of value. Firstly, the types of rules responsible for the rationality of practical argumentation are described. Secondly, some open problems relating to the claim to correctness of reasoned practical discourse are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. The rule of rescue in clinical practice.Jonathan Hughes & Tom Walker - 2009 - Clinical Ethics 4 (1):50-54.
    People often have a strong intuitive sense that we ought to rescue those in serious need, even in cases where we could produce better outcomes by acting in other ways. It has become common in such cases to refer to this as the Rule of Rescue. Within the medical field this rule has predominantly been discussed in relation to decisions about whether to fund particular treatments. Whilst in this setting the arguments in favour of the Rule of Rescue have generally (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11. Wittgenstein, Literature, and the Idea of a Practice.Peter Lamarque - 2010 - British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (4):375-388.
    The familiar idea that literature is embedded in social practices that help explain both its existence and its value took a distinctive form in analytic philosophy, drawing on speech act theory and a conception of ‘rules’. A major influence was John Rawls's seminal paper ‘Two Concepts of Rules’ (1955) in which he introduced the ‘practice conception of rules’ according to which certain practices are defined by rules that in turn make possible certain kinds of action. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  12. Rules of Meaning and Practical Reasoning.Peter Pagin - 1998 - Synthese 117 (2):207 - 227.
    Can there be rules of language which serve both to determine meaning and to guide speakers in ordinary linguistic usage, i.e., in the production of speech acts? We argue that the answer is no. We take the guiding function of rules to be the function of serving as reasons for actions, and the question of guidance is then considered within the framework of practical reasoning. It turns out that those rules that can serve as reasons for linguistic (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  13. Ruling passions: A theory of practical reason, Simon Blackburn. Clarendon press, 1998, 344 pages. [REVIEW]Eric Barnes - 2000 - Economics and Philosophy 16 (2):372-378.
  14.  7
    Faithful innovation: the rule of God and a Christian practical wisdom.Paul A. Lewis - 2020 - Macon, GA: Smyth & Helwys.
    This book offers an approach to Christian ethics. It does so first by organizing Christian ethics around the virtue of practical wisdom and suggesting what the guiding vision of a Christian practical wisdom should be. Second, it provides an account of practical wisdom that integrates literature drawn from the fields of philosophy, psychology, evolutionary theory, and the neurosciences. Reconceptualizing Christian ethics in this way can help us address-but not resolve once and for all-in a faithful way the challenges of our (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Rule Following, Social Practices, and Public Language in a Taxonomy of Representation Types.Greg M. Sax - 2002 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
    We are the funny organisms that make and follow rules. To understand us, one must understand what is it to institute and follow a rule, to perform correctly or in error. This question is more important than it might at first seem for linguistic meaning is constituted by rules that govern uses of expressions. For example, the fact that 'squid' is correctly applied to squid and incorrectly applied to cuttlefish is part of what makes 'squid' mean what it (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  63
    The rule of recognition and the emergence of a legal system.Luka Burazin - 2015 - Revus 27.
    The paper claims that the rule of recognition, given the way it is presented by Hart, cannot be a constitutive rule of any legal system as a whole, but rather a constitutive rule of legal rules as elements of a legal system. Since I take the legal system to be an institutional artifact kind, I claim that, in order to account for a legal system as a whole, at least two further constitutive rules, in addition to the rule (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  27
    Discussione su "Ruling Passions. A Theory of Practical Reasoning" di Simon Blackburn.Carla Bagnoli - 2000 - Iride: Filosofia e Discussione Pubblica 13 (2):411-432.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  24
    The Rules of Ferrous Metallurgy: Genesis and Structure of a Field of Engineering Science, 1870–1914.Stefan Krebs - 2010 - NTM Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Wissenschaften, Technik und Medizin 18 (1):29-60.
    The ways in which the sciences have been delineated and categorized throughout history provide insights into the formation, stabilization, and establishment of scientific systems of knowledge. The Dresdener school’s approach for explaining and categorizing the genesis of the engineering disciplines is still valid, but needs to be complemented by further-reaching methodological and theoretical reflections. Pierre Bourdieu’s theory of social practice is applied to the question of how individual agents succeed in influencing decisively a discipline’s changing object orientation, institutionalisation and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  25
    The rule of right vs might: a reply to Wischik's ‘Nazis, teleology, and the freedom of conscience'.Nathan K. Gamble & Michal Pruski - 2021 - The New Bioethics 27 (1):81-95.
    Wischik presents an extensive reply to our paper on conscientious objection, which explores the implications of distinguishing ‘medical acts’ from ‘socioclinical acts’. He provides an extensive legal analysis of the issues surrounding conscientious objection, drawing on the concepts of professional practice and consequentialism. Invoking some of these concepts, we respond and demonstrate that Wischik does not seriously engage with our argument. Instead, he merely proffers his preference for legal positivism, which – when viewed as the fount of justice (as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  10
    Faithful Innovation: The Rule of God and a Christian Practical Wisdom.Elisabeth Rain Kincaid - 2022 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 42 (1):223-224.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Ruling Passions. A Theory of Practical Reasoning. [REVIEW]Michael Quante - 2000 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 54 (1).
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  13
    Law without frontiers: a comparative survey of the rules of professional ethics applicable to the cross-border practice of law.Edwin Godfrey (ed.) - 1995 - London, UK: International Bar Association.
    This book is a comparative study which covers a number of major jurisdictions, viz., Australia, Belgium, Canada, England and Wales, France, Germany, Italy, Japan, Spain, Sweden, The Netherlands and the USA. A separate chapter deals with developments in the context of the European Union. The study is based on a questionnaire of the IBA Section on Business Law Subcommittee on the Structure and Ethics of Business Law. Part one of each country report covers the basic rules applying to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  48
    Book ReviewSimon Blackburn,. Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning. Oxford: Clarendon, 1999. Pp. vii + 334. $29.95. [REVIEW]Russell Shafer‐Landau - 2001 - Ethics 111 (4):799-804.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  38
    The Rule of Virtue: A Confucian Response to the Ethical Challenges of Technocracy.Yongmou Liu, Qin Zhu & Lishan Lan - 2021 - Science and Engineering Ethics 27 (5):1-24.
    The idea of technocracy has been widely criticized in Western literature in the philosophy and sociology of technology. A common critique of technocracy is that it represents an “antidemocratic” and “dehumanizing” ideology. This paper invites Western scholars to reconsider their oppositions to technocracy by drawing on resources from Confucian ethics. In doing so, this paper synthesizes the major ethical challenges of technocracy mainly concerned by Western scholars in philosophy, political theories, sociology, and policy studies. This paper argues that incorporating Confucian (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. How Can I Become a Responsible Subject? Towards a Practice-Based Ethics of Responsiveness.Bernadette Loacker & Sara Louise Muhr - 2009 - Journal of Business Ethics 90 (2):265-277.
    Approaches to business ethics can be roughly divided into two streams: ‹codes of behavior’ and ‹forms of subjectification’, with code-oriented approaches clearly dominating the field. Through an elaboration of poststructuralist approaches to moral philosophy, this paper questions the emphasis on codes of behaviour and, thus, the conceptions of the moral and responsible subject that are inherent in rule-based approaches. As a consequence of this critique, the concept of a practice-based ‹ethics of responsiveness’ in which ethics is never final but (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  26.  12
    Judgements without rules: towards a postmodern ironist concept of research validity.Gary Rolfe - 2006 - Nursing Inquiry 13 (1):7-15.
    The past decade has seen the gradual emergence of what might be called a postmodern perspective on nursing research. However, the development of a coherent postmodern critique of the modernist position has been hampered by some misunderstandings and misrepresentations of postmodern epistemology by a number of writers, leading to a fractured and distorted view of postmodern nursing research. This paper seeks to distinguish between judgemental relativist and epistemic relativist or ironist positions, and regards the latter as offering the most coherent (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  27.  7
    Between the rule of power and the power of rule in search of an effective world order.A. Van Staden - 2007 - Boston: M. Nijhoff.
    The book discusses different models of world order, traditional and modern. Any practical application of the concept at issue will be affected by the prevailing power structure, and to some degree, reflect it. The reality of American preeminence in the world today needs to be reconciled with the demand for international legitimacy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  79
    A Practical Look at the Concept of Freedom with a Philosophy Approach for Children in Early Childhood.Deniz Yüceer & Sevgi Coşkun Keskin - 2023 - Childhood and Philosophy 19:01-31.
    Both social studies and preschool programs mention freedom as a value. However, in typical social studies curricula, the philosophical perspective is not included and no discussion takes place. In the preschool curriculum, freedom is an abstract concept, and the belief that children cannot understand abstract concepts prevails, while value studies are still limited to determining the frequency of values rather than interrogating them. As such, this study aims to explore young children's views on the concept of freedom, how these views (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  39
    Is the Rule of Recognition Really a Conventional Rule?Julie Dickson - 2007 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27 (3):373-402.
    In this article I examine the view, common amongst several contemporary legal positivists, that rules of recognition are to be understood as conventional rules of some kind. The article opens with a discussion of H.L.A. Hart's original account of the rule of recognition in the 1st edn of The Concept of Law and argues that Hart did not view the rule of recognition as a conventional rule in that account. I then discuss Hart's apparent turn towards a conventionalist (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  30.  15
    The Role of The Practice of The Companions in Establishing The Ḥanafī Uṣūl Thought: Al-Sarakhsī as a Case Study.Ahmet Numan Ünver - 2021 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 25 (3):1359-1379.
    Along with the legal opinions, the juristic proofs presented to underpin these legal opinions also occupy an important place in uṣūl al-fiqh. Thus, scholars of uṣūl al-fiqh strived to propound the proofs indicating the relevant theoretical principles in an apparent and definite way. As a result, the disputed and undisputed proofs ranked among al-adilla al-shar‘iyya have been abundantly addressed in the classical uṣūl al-fiqh works. However, although it is not mentioned as a part of legal sources in the uṣul literature, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  14
    Invoking Rules in Everyday Family Interactions: A Method for Appealing to Practical Reason.Uwe-A. Küttner, Anna Vatanen & Jörg Zinken - 2022 - Human Studies 45 (4):793-823.
    In this article we examine moments in which parents or other caregivers overtly invoke rules during episodes in which they take issue with, intervene against, and try to change a child’s ongoing behavior or action(s). Drawing on interactional data from four different languages (English, Finnish, German, Polish) and using Conversation Analytic methods, we first illustrate the variety of ways in which parents may use such overt rule invocations as part of their behavior modification attempts, showing them to be functionally (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  19
    Buddhist Litigants in Public Court: A Case Study of Legal Practices in Tibetan-ruled Dunhuang.Cuilan Liu - 2021 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 139 (1):91.
    This article examines a legal dispute over the ownership of nine bondservants between a Buddhist monastery and two monks and a nun, focusing on the legal apparatus and practices in Dunhuang when it was under Tibetan control. During the Tang, eminent monks of the Buddhist clergy petitioned for exemptions from public courts in order to restrict trials of ordained Buddhists at alternative venues. Such petitions were declined, granted, or revoked by different Tang emperors. This case study demonstrates that ordained Buddhists (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  16
    Moral Consensus, the Rule of Law, and the Practice of Torture.Jonathan Rothchild - 2006 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 26 (2):125-156.
    THIS ESSAY ARGUES AGAINST LEGAL, POLITICAL, AND ETHICAL JUSTIFICAtions for torture. In the expository sections of the essay, I juxtapose international prohibitions against torture with the current U.S. administration's justifications for harsh interrogation methods on the basis of military necessity and presidential prerogative. I examine the systematic and individual causes of the specific abuses at Abu Ghraib that were tantamount to torture. In the constructive sections of the essay, I retrieve the evolving standards of decency from Supreme Court cases and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. The impossibility of the rule of law.Timothy A. O. Endicott - 1999 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 19 (1):1-18.
    No community fully achieves the ideal of the rule of law. Puzzles about the content of the ideal seem to make it necessarily unattainable (and, therefore, an incoherent ideal). Legal systems necessarily contain vague laws. They typically allow for change in the law, they typically provide for unreviewable official decisions, and they never regulate every aspect of the life of a community. It may seem that the ideal can never be achieved because of these features of legal practice. But (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35. Modeling the invention of a new inference rule: The case of ‘Randomized Clinical Trial’ as an argument scheme for medical science.Jodi Schneider & Sally Jackson - 2018 - Argument and Computation 9 (2):77-89.
    A background assumption of this paper is that the repertoire of inference schemes available to humanity is not fixed, but subject to change as new schemes are invented or refined and as old ones are obsolesced or abandoned. This is particularly visible in areas like health and environmental sciences, where enormous societal investment has been made in finding ways to reach more dependable conclusions. Computational modeling of argumentation, at least for the discourse in expert fields, will require the possibility of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  78
    We Make Up the Rules as We Go Along: Improvisation as an Essential Aspect of Human Practices?Georg W. Bertram & Alessandro Bertinetto - 2020 - Open Philosophy 3 (1):202-221.
    The article presents the conceptual groundwork for an understanding of the essentially improvisational dimension of human rationality. It aims to clarify how we should think about important concepts pertinent to central aspects of human practices, namely, the concepts of improvisation, normativity, habit, and freedom. In order to understand the sense in which human practices are essentially improvisational, it is first necessary to criticize misconceptions about improvisation as lack of preparation and creatio ex nihilo. Second, it is necessary to solve the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  37.  83
    Double effect: a useful rule that alone cannot justify hastening death.J. A. Billings - 2011 - Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (7):437-440.
    The rule of double effect is regularly invoked in ethical discussions about palliative sedation, terminal extubation and other clinical acts that may be viewed as hastening death for imminently dying patients. Unfortunately, the literature tends to employ this useful principle in a fashion suggesting that it offers the final word on the moral acceptability of such medical procedures. In fact, the rule cannot be applied appropriately without invoking moral theories that are not explicit in the rule itself. Four tenets of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38.  37
    The Rule of Non‐Opposition: Opening Up Decision‐Making by Consensus.Philippe Urfalino - 2014 - Journal of Political Philosophy 22 (3):320-341.
    The objective of this article is to propose a precise characterization of the collective practice behind at least an important part of the phenomena named “decision by consensus”. First, I provide descriptions of the use of this rule, and give a definition of the non-opposition rule, both as a specific sequence of acts and as a stopping rule. Second, I challenge the usual way of understanding the non-opposition rule by contrast with voting, stating that the contrast between logic of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  39.  3
    Rule of Law, Religious Freedom, and Harmony: Regulating Religion Within kazakhstan's Secular Model.Yermek Buribayev, Natalya Seitakhmetova, Ph D. Sholpan Zhandossova, Kuralay Turlykhankyzy, Nessibeli Kalkayeva & Zhanna Khamzina - 2024 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16 (4):417-442.
    This article examines the regulation of religious policy and state-confessional relations in Kazakhstan. Religion is an integral part of the spiritual life in secular Kazakhstan, and religious values are embedded within the value paradigm of Kazakhstani identity. In this context, there is a need to model secularism based on the rule of law, human rights, and personal freedoms. The purpose of this article is to conceptualize "Kazakhstani secularism" and "Kazakhstani religiosity," identifying their differences and the universality of their value meanings. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  76
    An Evaluation of the Rules of Conduct Governing Legal Representatives in Mediation: Challenges for Rule Drafters and a Response to Jim Mason.Bobette Wolski - 2013 - Legal Ethics 16 (1):182-215.
    This paper provides a comparative analysis of the rules of conduct governing legal representatives in Australia, the United States of America and the United Kingdom as they apply to a range of ethical issues in mediation. The analysis has four main aims. First, it clarifies the position in Australia and the USA - the Australian and American mediation communities have not introduced separate codes for ?mediation advocates? as Mason recently suggested. But some provisions have been made for mediation (...). The second aim is to tease out from these provisions learning points for policy makers and rule drafters. Amongst the points to consider is whether or not, and under what circumstances, mediators should be regarded as courts, or as third parties for the purpose of the rules. Third, the analysis provides some grounds for arguing that the current rules of conduct are appropriate for legal representatives in mediation. Fourth, it identifies challenges associated with proposals to introduce rules which require legal representatives to participate in mediation in good faith in a non-adversarial manner according to higher standards of honesty and candour. The article concludes by identifying a number of assumptions which permeate the literature on this topic. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. The Rule of Law and Jury Nullification.Travis Hreno - 2008 - Commonwealth Law Bulletin 34 (2).
    Jury nullification occurs when a jury votes to acquit a defendant in a criminal trial despite its belief that the defendant is, in fact, guilty. One of the main objections to this practice is that it subverts the rule of law. In this paper, I examine this objection by expanding on what is entailed by the rule of law objection and demonstrating that the very principles that the rule of law are built upon – liberty and autonomy – are, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  60
    Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning (review). [REVIEW]Michelle Mason - 1998 - Hume Studies 24 (2):367-371.
  43.  40
    Popular Constitutionalism and the Rule of Recognition: Whose Practices Ground U.Matthew D. Adler - unknown
    The law within each legal system is a function of the practices of some social group. In short, law is a kind of socially grounded norm. H.L.A Hart famously developed this view in his book, The Concept of Law, by arguing that law derives from a social rule, the so-called “rule of recognition.” But the proposition that social facts play a foundational role in producing law is a point of consensus for all modern jurisprudents in the Anglo-American tradition: not just (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  15
    The Rule of the Present, Not the Past.Franco Peirone - 2021 - Jus Cogens 3 (3):229-256.
    There is a perennial ambiguity in the rule-of-law preposition: it predicates that the law shall rule, but which law? This legal loophole has led to a diverse array of interpretations of the concept. Of these, two appear particularly adverse to what the rule of law should primarily be—the rulership of the law—yet still remain dominant. On the one hand, the rule of law is intended to be the vehicle to deliver above-the-law goods such as human rights or other individual entitlements (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Is the rule of recognition really a duty-imposing rule?Laurenz Ramsauer - 2023 - Journal of Legal Philosophy 48 (2):83-102.
    According to a persistent assumption in legal philosophy, the social rule at the foundation of a legal system (the Rule of Recognition) serves both an epistemic and a duty-imposing function. Thus, some authors have claimed that it would be a formidable problem for legal philosophy to explain how such social rules can impose duties, and some have taken it upon themselves to show how social practices might just do that. However, I argue that this orthodox assumption about the dual (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  47
    The rule of law: beyond contestedness.Paul Burgess - 2017 - Jurisprudence 8 (3):480-500.
    In assessing compliance with the Rule of Law, the contested nature of the concept renders the use of a single theorist’s conception or, alternatively, the adoption of a hybrid conception open to criticism. There is no settled and practical way to determine Rule of Law non-compliance. It is argued that by looking behind the concept’s contestedness, Rule of Law non-compliance can be identified. The fundamental needs undergirding canonical conceptions are used to identify common elements of the Rule of Law. By (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  35
    King, magnates, and society: the personal rule of King Henry III, 1234–1258.D. A. Carpenter - 1985 - Speculum 60 (1):39-70.
    Between 1234 and 1258 King Henry III, having emerged from the tutelage of ministers inherited from his father, controlled the government of England himself. Looking at this period of personal rule, it would be easy to gain the impression that Henry's kingship, in its theory, and also to some extent its practice, challenged the position of the magnates. M. T. Clanchy, for example, in a justly famous article has suggested that in the 1240s and 1250s Henry III evolved a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  62
    (1 other version)Han Fei's Theory of the "Rule of Law" Played a Progressive Role.Yang K'uan - 1978 - Contemporary Chinese Thought 10 (1):4-18.
    Han Fei was a famous Legalist in the late Warring States period. During the struggle to criticize the Confucian school, he developed the theory of the "rule of law," which laid a theoretical groundwork on which the newly emerging landlord class could build a centralized feudal state. His works had been appreciated by Ch'in Shih-huang. When Ch'in Shih-huang read the book Han Fei Tzu, he sighed and said, "I would feel no regret about dying if I could meet this person (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  13
    A community of practice approach to enhancing academic integrity policy translation: a case study.Alison Lockley, Amanda Janssen, Penelope A. S. Wurm & Alison Kay Reedy - 2021 - International Journal for Educational Integrity 17 (1).
    IntroductionAcademic integrity policy that is inaccessible, ambiguous or confusing is likely to result in inconsistent policy enactment. Additionally, policy analysis and development are often undertaken as top down processes requiring passive acceptance by users of policy that has been developed outside the context in which it is enacted. Both these factors can result in poor policy uptake, particularly where policy users are overworked, intellectually critical and capable, not prone to passive acceptance and hold valuable grass roots intelligence about policy enactment.Case (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  64
    How to regulate a practice: The case of cosmetic surgery. [REVIEW]Henri Wijsbek - 2001 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 4 (1):59-74.
    How should a practice, subservient to a public good, be regulated in order to guarantee fair access without encouraging improper claims? In the first place, a clear understanding of the goal of the practice is indispensable for knowing what criteria the regulation must contain. As to the purely formal aspect, the regulation of any practice must include both general rules and particular instances. Finally, to resolve conflicts, committees in which different kinds of expertise are represented should (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 969