This category needs an editor. We encourage you to help if you are qualified.
Volunteer, or read more about what this involves.
Related

Contents
420 found
Order:
1 — 50 / 420
Material to categorize
  1. Partiality, Asymmetries, and Morality's Harmonious Propensity.Benjamin Lange & Joshua Brandt - 2024 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 109 (1):30-54.
    We argue for asymmetries between positive and negative partiality. Specifically, we defend four claims: i) there are forms of negative partiality that do not have positive counterparts; ii) the directionality of personal relationships has distinct effects on positive and negative partiality; iii) the extent of the interactions within a relationship affects positive and negative partiality differently; and iv) positive and negative partiality have different scope restrictions. We argue that these asymmetries point to a more fundamental moral principle, which we call (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Indirect, Multidimensional Consequentialism.Alan Carter - 2013 - In Avram Hiller, Ramona Ilea & Leonard Kahn, Consequentialism and environmental ethics. New York: Routledge. pp. 70-91.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. (1 other version)AFTERWORDS Criticism and Countertheses.Lawrence W. Hyman - 1980 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 38 (4):451-452.
  4. Being and the Good.Noreen O’Connor - 1980 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 27:212-220.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism.Douglas W. Portmore (ed.) - 2020 - New York, USA: Oup Usa.
    Consequentialism is a major moral theory and a rival to such non-consequentialist theories as deontology, contractualism, and virtue ethics. It is the view that the only thing that matters morally is the consequences of an action. Thus, consequentialists hold that, to assess an act, we must first evaluate and rank the various ways things could turn out depending on whether it or some alternative act is performed. Its moral permissibility, then, depends on how its consequences compare to those of its (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6. Allan Gibbard, Reconciling Our Aims: In Search of Bases for Ethics , pp. viii + 216.Brian Mcelwee - 2012 - Utilitas 24 (4):563-566.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. What's the Point of Self-consciousness? A Critique of Singer's Arguments against Killing (Human or Non-human) Self-conscious Animals.Federico Zuolo - 2016 - Utilitas 28 (4):465-487.
    Singer has argued against the permissibility of killing people on the grounds of the distinction between conscious and self-conscious animals. Unlike conscious animals, which can be replaced without a loss of overall welfare, there can be no substitution for self-conscious animals. In this article, I show that Singer's argument is untenable, in the cases both of the preference-based account of utilitarianism and of objective hedonism, to which he has recently turned. In the first case, Singer cannot theoretically exclude that a (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Book Reviews Portmore , Douglas . Commonsense Consequentialism: Wherein Morality Meets Rationality Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011. Pp. 266. $74.00 (paper). [REVIEW]Frances Howard-Snyder - 2012 - Ethics 123 (1):179-183.
  9. Good, Good For, and Good Relative To: Relative and Relational in Value Theory.Fritz-Anton Fritzson - 2016 - Philosophy 91 (2):255-267.
    This paper discusses how we are to understand claims to the effect that something is good relative to a person. It is argued that goodness relative to should not be equated with good for as the latter is a relational value notion and the former is a value theoretical notion. It is argued further that good relative to a person should be understood as good from the perspective or the point of view of the person. But this analysis of the (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. Impartiality and Associative Duties: David O. Brink.David O. Brink - 2001 - Utilitas 13 (2):152-172.
    Consequentialism is often criticized for failing to accommodate impersonal constraints and personal options. A common consequentialist response is to acknowledge the anticonsequentialist intuitions but to argue either that the consequentialist can, after all, accommodate the allegedly recalcitrant intuitions or that, where accommodation is impossible, the recalcitrant intuition can be dismissed for want of an adequate philosophical rationale. Whereas these consequentialist responses have some plausibility, associational duties represent a somewhat different challenge to consequentialism, inasmuch as they embody neither impersonal constraints nor (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  11. On Life, Death, and Abortion.D. W. Haslett - 1996 - Utilitas 8 (2):159-189.
    Morally speaking, is abortion murder? This is what I am calling the ‘abortion problem’. I claim that neither pro-life nor pro-choice advocates have the correct solution; that the correct solution is instead one considered correct by relatively few people. But if this solution really is correct, then why, after years of intense debate, is this solution not more widely accepted? Many, no doubt, are precluded from accepting it by religious dogma. But others, I think, fail to arrive at a correct (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. (1 other version)Could Kant Have been A Utilitarian?Richard Hare - 1993 - Utilitas 5 (1):1-16.
    … the supreme end, the happiness of all mankind (Kr VA851/NKS 665).The law concerning punishment is a Categorical Imperative; and woe to him who rummages around in the winding paths of a theory of happiness, looking for some advantage to be gained by releasing the criminal from punishment or by reducing the amount of it (Rl.A196/B226, 6:331; Ladd, 100).
    Remove from this list   Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  13. Astronomical Waste: The Opportunity Cost of Delayed Technological Development: Nick Bostrom.Nick Bostrom - 2003 - Utilitas 15 (3):308-314.
    With very advanced technology, a very large population of people living happy lives could be sustained in the accessible region of the universe. For every year that development of such technologies and colonization of the universe is delayed, there is therefore a corresponding opportunity cost: a potential good, lives worth living, is not being realized. Given some plausible assumptions, this cost is extremely large. However, the lesson for standard utilitarians is not that we ought to maximize the pace of technological (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  14. Jevons's Applications of Utilitarian Theory to Economic Policy*: Sandra J. Peart.Sandra J. Peart - 1990 - Utilitas 2 (2):281-306.
    The precise nature of W. S. Jevons's utilitarianism as a guiding rule for economic policy has yet to be investigated, and that will be the first issue treated in this paper. While J. A. Schumpeter, for instance, asserted that ‘some of the most prominent exponents of marginal utility’, were ‘convinced utilitarians’, he did not investigate the further implications for Jevons's policy analysis.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Benefit versus Numbers versus Helping the Worst-off: An Alternative to the Prevalent Approach to the Just Distribution of Resources.Andrew Stark - 2008 - Utilitas 20 (3):356-382.
    A central strand in philosophical debate over the just distribution of resources attempts to juggle three competing imperatives: helping those who are worst off, helping those who will benefit the most, and then – beyond this – determining when to aggregate such ‘worst off’ and ‘benefit’ claims, and when instead to treat no such claim as greater than that which any individual by herself can exert. Yet as various philosophers have observed, ‘we have no satisfactory theoretical characterization’ as to how (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16. More on Bentham on Utility and Rights.P. J. Kelly - 1998 - Utilitas 10 (2):165-167.
    This paper examines Rosen's claim that Bentham's principle of utility was a distributive rather than an aggregative principle.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Is it Rational to Maximize?James Wood Bailey - 1998 - Utilitas 10 (2):195-221.
    Most versions of utilitarianism depend on the plausibility and coherence of some conceptionof maximizing well-being, but these conceptions have been attacked on various grounds. This paper considers two such contentions. First, it addresses the argument that because goods are plural and incommensurable, maximization is incoherent. It is shown that any conception of incommensurability strong enough to show the incoherence of maximization leads to an intolerable paradox. Several misunderstandings of what maximization requires are also addressed. Second, this paper responds to the (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  18. The Distinction Between Criterion and Decision Procedure: A Reply to Madison Powers: James Griffin.James Griffin - 1994 - Utilitas 6 (2):177-182.
    Madison Powers raises the difficult problem of repugnant desires. The problem is not only difficult but pervasive, more pervasive even than Powers says. He notes that it affects hedonist, eudaimonist, and desire-fulfilment forms of utilitarianism; but it also affects the form of utilitarianism that uses a list of irreducibly plural values, so long as one of the values on the list is pleasure or happiness, and it can affect non-utilitarian positions as well for the same reason.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19. Choice and Consequentialism.Germain Grisez - 1977 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 51:144-152.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. The Irrationality of the Good.C. E. M. Joad - 1926 - Philosophy 1 (4):497-506.
    The theories of most writers on Ethics, with whose works I am acquainted, appear to be based upon the assumption of the unique character of goodness or The Good. By the word unique these writers mean, I think, among other things that goodness cannot be analysed into or described in terms of anything other than itself, that it can be and is desired for its own sake and not for the sake of some other thing which is not goodness, and (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Deep Down: Consequentialist Assumptions Underlying Policy Differences.Zeljka Buturovic - 2012 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 24 (2):269-289.
    A conditional survey establishes a preliminary case for believing that policy differences are to some extent driven by fundamental beliefs about empirical aspects of society and economics. The survey shows willingness in about a third of all respondents to shift their expressed policy preferences when asked a hypothetical question positing negative consequences of their initial preferences. This suggests that assumptions about the consequences of public policies may play as important a role in policy preferences, or a more important role, than (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Two Theories of the Good: L. W. SUMNER.L. W. Sumner - 1992 - Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (2):1-14.
    Suppose that the ultimate point of ethics is to make the world a better place. If it is, we must face the question: better in what respect? If the good is prior to the right — that is, if the rationale for all requirements of the right is that they serve to further the good in one way or another — then what is this good? Is there a single fundamental value capable of underlying and unifying all of our moral (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  23. It Is Not Good for God to Be Alone.Joyce Little - 2000 - The Chesterton Review 26 (1-2):95-115.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. The “Good War”.Allan Carlson - 2008 - The Chesterton Review 34 (1-2):147-161.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Christianity and Consequentialism.James A. Keller - 1989 - Faith and Philosophy 6 (2):198-206.
    In a recent paper, Gilbert Meilaender argues that Christian ethics must not be consequentialist. Though Meilaender does indicate some problems which may exist with certain consequentialist theories, those problems do not exclude all types of consequentialist theories from consideration as Christian ethical theories. A consequentialism like R. M. Hare’s offers virtually all the advantages Meilaender claims for his Christian deontological view. Moreover. Meilaender has overlooked certain advantages of consequentialism and certain disadvantages of the sort of deontological theory he espouses.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Can We Be Good Without God?: Biology, Behavior, and the Need to Believe. [REVIEW]Mark Wynn - 2005 - International Philosophical Quarterly 45 (1):119-120.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. A Consequentialist Case for Rejecting the Right.Frances Howard-Snyder & Alastair Norcross - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Research 18:109-125.
    Satisficing and maximizing versions of consequentialism have both assumed that rightness is an alI-or-nothing property. We argue thal this is inimical to the spirit of consequentialism, and that, from the point of view of the consequentialist, actions should be evaluated purely in terms that admit of degree. We first consider the suggestion that rightness and wrongness are a matter of degree. If so, this raises the question of whether the claim that something is wrong says any more than that it (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28. Readjusting Utility for Justice.Dennis R. Cooley - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Research 25:363-380.
    Despite the best efforts of utilitarians, justice remains a serious problem for consequentialism. Many counterexamples have been described which show that an agent may be obligated to do a gross injustice, according to hedonic utilitarianism, just because it maximizes utility. Fred Feldman attempts to avoid this result by adjusting utility for justice.In this paper, I examine Feldman’s axiology and his normative theory of world utilitarianism, and show that, ultimately, he is not successful in his endeavor. Though Feldman’s theories may not (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. If You Can’t Be Good, Be Careful.Kelly Oliver - 2011 - Philosophy Today 55 (Supplement):47-55.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Incoherence and Consequentialism (or Proportionalism).Joseph Boyle, Germain Grisez & John Finnis - 1990 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 64 (2):271-277.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Without Good Reason. [REVIEW]Michael Bradie - 2004 - International Studies in Philosophy 36 (4):131-132.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Ethics.Frank Chapman Sharp - 1928 - Century Co..
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. The good as good will.C. Fox - 1925 - Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy 3 (1):12-23.
  34. Might anything be plain good?Thomas Byrne - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (12):3335-3346.
    G.E. Moore said that rightness was obviously a matter of maximising plain goodness. Peter Geach and Judith Thomson disagree. They have both argued that ‘good’ is not a predicative adjective, but only ever an attributive adjective: just like ‘big.’ And just as there is no such thing as plain bigness but only ever big for or as a so-and-so, there is also no such thing as plain goodness. They conclude that Moore’s goodness is thus a nonsense. However attention has been (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35. Good Athlete, Good Person?Dustin Nelson - 2016 - Southwest Philosophy Review 32 (2):69-71.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. The Good Will: a Study in the Coherence Theory of Goodness.Alex J. D. Porteous - 1929 - Philosophical Review 38 (1):78.
  37. Are there organic unities?Jonathan Dancy - unknown
    Argues against G. E. Moore’s conception of organic unities, attempting to replace it with a conception more amenable to particularism. Considers the possibility of a form of default value acceptable to particularism. Ends by contrasting the views expressed here with those of Kagan.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  38. G. E. Moore and Intrinsic Goodness.Edward F. Mettrick - 1928 - International Journal of Ethics 38 (4):389-400.
  39. The Good and the Bad.Arthur Ernest Davies - 1907 - International Journal of Ethics 17 (2):147-163.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Susan Wolf: Meaning in Life and Why It Matters.Markus Rüther - 2011 - Philosophischer Literaturanzeiger 64 (3):308-313.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. (1 other version)The Good and the Right.L. W. Sumner - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (sup1):99-114.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42. Consequentialism and Preference Formation in Economics and Game Theory.Daniel M. Hausman - 2006 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 59:111-130.
    When students first study expected utility, they are inclined to interpret it as a theory that explains preferences for lotteries in terms of preferences for outcomes. Knowing U($100) and U($0), the agent can calculate that the utility of a gamble of $100 on a fair coin coming up heads is U($100)/2 + U($0)/2. Utilities are indices representing preferences, so in calculating the utility of the gamble, one is apparently giving a causal explanation for the agent’s preference for the gamble.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. The Right and the Good.Judith Thomson - 1997 - Journal of Philosophy 94 (6):273.
  44. VI*—The Self and the Good.A. D. Smith - 1985 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 85 (1):101-118.
    A. D. Smith; VI*—The Self and the Good, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 85, Issue 1, 1 June 1985, Pages 101–118, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristot.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. IX.—The Good and the Right.M. C. D'Arcy - 1932 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 32 (1):171-206.
  46. III—Does it Pay to be Good?D. Z. Phillips - 1965 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 65 (1):45-60.
    D. Z. Phillips; III—Does it Pay to be Good?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 65, Issue 1, 1 June 1965, Pages 45–60, https://doi.org/10.1093/aris.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47. The Supererogatory and How Not To Accommodate It: A Reply to Dorsey.Alfred Archer - 2016 - Utilitas 28 (2):179-188.
    It is plausible to think that there exist acts of supererogation. It also seems plausible that there is a close connection between what we are morally required to do and what it would be morally good to do. Despite being independently plausible these two claims are hard to reconcile. My aim in this article will be to respond to a recent solution to this puzzle proposed by Dale Dorsey. Dorsey's solution to this problem is to posit a new account of (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  48. Toward an Axiological Virtue Ethics.Rem B. Edwards - 2013 - Ethical Research 3 (3):21-48.
    This article introduces Formal Axiology, first developed by Robert S. Hartman, and explains its essential features—a formal definition of “good” (the “Form of the Good”), three basic kinds of value and evaluation—systemic, extrinsic, and intrinsic, and the hierarchy of value according to which good things having the richest quantity and quality of good-making properties are better than those having less. Formal Axiology is extended into moral philosophy by applying the Form of the Good to persons and showing how this culminates (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Consequentialism and Feminist Ethics.Julia Driver - 2000 - Hypatia 20 (4):183-199.
    This essay attempts to show that sophisticated consequentialism is able to accommodate the concerns that have traditionally been raised by feminist writers in ethics. Those concerns have primarily to do with the fact that consequentialism is seen as both too demanding of the individual and neglectful of the agent's special obligations to family and friends. Here, I argue that instrumental justification for partiality can be provided, for example, even though an attitude of partiality is not characterized itself in instrumental terms.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  50. Two preference metrics provide settings for the study of properties of binary relations.Vicki Knoblauch - 2015 - Theory and Decision 79 (4):615-625.
    The topological structures imposed on the collection of binary relations on a given set by the symmetric difference metric and the Hausdorff metric provide opportunities for learning about how collections of binary relations with various properties fit into the collection of all binary relations. For example, there is some agreement and some disagreement between conclusions drawn about the rarity of certain properties of binary relations using first the symmetric difference metric and then the Hausdorff metric.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 420