Results for 'Act requirement'

968 found
Order:
  1.  73
    Action, the Act Requirement and Criminal Liability.Antony Duff - 2004 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 55:69-103.
    The slogan that criminal liability requires an ‘act’, or a ‘voluntary act’, is still something of a commonplace in textbooks of criminal law. There are, it is usually added, certain exceptions to this requirement— cases in which liability is in fact, and perhaps even properly, imposed in the absence of such an act: but the ‘act requirement’ is taken to represent a normally minimal necessary condition of criminal liability. Even offences of strict liability, for which no mens rea (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2. An alleged act requirement in the criminal law.Douglas Husak - 2011 - In John Deigh & David Dolinko (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of the Criminal Law. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  91
    The Voluntary Act Requirement.Gideon Yaffe - 2012 - In Andrei Marmor (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Law. New York , NY: Routledge. pp. 174.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  4. Intoxication and the Act/Control/Agency Requirement.Susan Dimock - 2012 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3):341-362.
    Doug Husak has argued, persuasively I think, that there is no literal ‘act requirement’ in Anglo-American law. I begin by reviewing Husak’s reasons for rejecting the act requirement, and provide additional reasons to think he is right to do so. But Husak’s alternative, the ‘control condition’, I argue, is inadequate. The control requirement is falsified by the widespread practice of holding extremely intoxicated offenders liable for criminal conduct they engage in even if they lack control over their (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  55
    The requirements of the Data Protection Act 1998 for the processing of medical data.P. Boyd - 2003 - Journal of Medical Ethics 29 (1):34-35.
    The Data Protection Act 1998 presents a number of significant challenges to data controllers in the health sector. To assist data controllers in understanding their obligations under the act, the Information Commissioner has published guidance, The Use and Disclosure of Health Data, which is reproduced here. The guidance deals, among other things, with the steps that must be taken to obtain patient data fairly, the implied requirements of the act to use anonymised or psuedonymised data where possible, an exemption applicable (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  25
    Requirement and rationality: two problems concerning supererogatory acts.Elizabeth Drummond Young - 2005 - Dissertation, University of Edinburgh
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  29
    Acting More Generously than the Law Requires: The Issue of Employee Layoffs in halakhah.Harry J. van Buren Iii - 1999 - Journal of Business Ethics 19 (4):335-343.
    In this paper, the issue of plant closings is analyzed from the perspective of halakhah (the Written Law of Judaism). Two levels of analysis in halakhah must be differentiated: the legal (enforced by courts) and the moral (not enforced by law, but rather framed in terms of duty to God). There is no legal mandate to keep an unprofitable plant open, but there are a number of moral imprecations (particularly "acting more generously than the law requires") that might influence an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  26
    Acting irrationally versus acting contrary to what is required by reason.Bernard Gert - 1999 - Journal of Social Philosophy 30 (3):379–386.
  9.  63
    Acting more generously than the law requires: The issue of employee layoffs in halakhah.Harry J. Van Buren - 1999 - Journal of Business Ethics 19 (4):335-343.
    In this paper, the issue of plant closings is analyzed from the perspective of halakhah (the Written Law of Judaism). Two levels of analysis in halakhah must be differentiated: the legal (enforced by courts) and the moral (not enforced by law, but rather framed in terms of duty to God). There is no legal mandate to keep an unprofitable plant open, but there are a number of moral imprecations (particularly "acting more generously than the law requires") that might influence an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  15
    Require an Act?Douglas Husak - 1998 - In Antony Duff (ed.), Philosophy and the criminal law: principle and critique. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 60.
  11. Reasons to act, reasons to require, and the two-level theory of moral explanation.Jörg Https://Orcidorg Löschke - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (1):169-185.
    Deontic buck-passing aims to analyse deontic properties of acts in terms of reasons. Many authors accept deontic buck-passing, but only few have discussed how to understand the relation between reasons and deontic properties exactly. Justin Snedegar has suggested understanding deontic properties of acts in terms of both reasons and reasons to require: A is required to φ iff A has most reason to φ, and there is most reason to require A to φ. This promising proposal faces two open questions: (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  75
    “No Father Required”? The Welfare Assessment in the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act 2008.Julie McCandless & Sally Sheldon - 2010 - Feminist Legal Studies 18 (3):201-225.
    Of all the changes to the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act 1990 that were introduced in 2008 by legislation of the same name, foremost to excite media attention and popular controversy was the amendment of the so-called welfare clause. This clause forms part of the licensing conditions which must be met by any clinic before offering those treatment services covered by the legislation. The 2008 Act deleted the statutory requirement that clinicians consider the need for a father of any (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  41
    Placement of long-acting reversible contraception for minors who are mothers should not require parental consent.Savannah Kaszubinski - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 48 (11):857-860.
    Decreasing unintended teenage pregnancy, especially repeat teenage pregnancy, is an important public health goal. Unfortunately, legal barriers in the USA impede this goal as all minors are unable to consent for birth control in 24 states, and only 10 of those states allow consent after the minor has given birth according to state statutory law. Placement of long-acting reversible contraception is one of the most effective methods of preventing rapid repeat pregnancies. However, restrictions are placed on adolescents who may not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. (1 other version)Act and Crime: The Philosophy of Action and its Implications for Criminal Law.Michael S. Moore - 1993 - Oxford University Press.
    This work provides, for the first time, a unified account of the theory of action presupposed by both British and American criminal law and its underlying morality. It defends the view that human actions are volitionally caused body movements. This theory illuminates three major problems in drafting and implementing criminal law--what the voluntary act requirement does and should require, what complex descriptions of actions prohibited by criminal codes both do and should require, and when the two actions are the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  15.  65
    Acting and Understanding.Alexander Stathopoulos - 2016 - Dissertation, University of St. Andrews
    This thesis concerns the question of what it is for a subject to act. It answers this question in three steps. The first step is taken by arguing that any satisfactory answer must build on the idea that an action is something predicable of the acting subject. The second step is taken by arguing in support of an answer which does build on this idea, and does so by introducing the idea that acting is doing something which is an exercise (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Normative requirements.John Broome - 1999 - Ratio 12 (4):398–419.
    Normative requirements are often overlooked, but they are central features of the normative world. Rationality is often thought to consist in acting for reasons, but following normative requirements is also a major part of rationality. In particular, correct reasoning – both theoretical and practical – is governed by normative requirements rather than by reasons. This article explains the nature of normative requirements, and gives examples of their importance. It also describes mistakes that philosophers have made as a result of confusing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   421 citations  
  17.  13
    Administrative Developments: Civil Cause of Action under RICO Requires Tortious Act—Beck v. Prupis.Sharon Hussong - 2000 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 28 (2):189-190.
    The U.S. Supreme Court held 7-2 that an individual harmed by an overt act that is not tortious under the Racketeer Influenced and Corrupt Organizations Act does not have a civil cause of action under RICO. Therefore, an individual terminated from his job in furtherance of a racketeering conspiracy does not have a civil cause of action, since such termination is not an “independently wrongful” act under RICO.The plaintiff, Robert Beck, was the president, CEO, director, and shareholder of Southeastern Insurance (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  64
    The Alien Tort Claims Act of 1789: Globalization of Business Requires Globalization of Law and Ethics.Edward J. Schoen, Joseph S. Falchek & Margaret M. Hogan - 2005 - Journal of Business Ethics 62 (1):41-56.
  19. Acts of the State and Representation in Edith Stein.Hamid Taieb - 2020 - Journal of Social Ontology 6 (1):21-45.
    This paper discusses the thesis defended by Edith Stein that certain acts can be attributed to the State. According to Stein, the State is a social structure characterized by sovereignty. As such, it is responsible for the production, interpretation, and application of law. These tasks require the performance of acts, most of which are what Stein calls “social acts” like enactments and orders. For Stein, the acts in question are made by the organs of the State, but in the name (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  50
    Medical Acts and Conscientious Objection: What Can a Physician be Compelled to Do.Nathan K. Gamble & Michal Pruski - 2019 - The New Bioethics 25 (3):262-282.
    A key question has been underexplored in the literature on conscientious objection: if a physician is required to perform ‘medical activities,’ what is a medical activity? This paper explores the question by employing a teleological evaluation of medicine and examining the analogy of military conscripts, commonly cited in the conscientious objection debate. It argues that physicians (and other healthcare professionals) can only be expected to perform and support medical acts – acts directed towards their patients’ health. That is, physicians cannot (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  21.  12
    Acts, intentions, and moral evaluation: a dialogue.Craig M. White - 2023 - New York, NY: Routledge.
    This book argues that the moral quality of an act comes from the agent's inner states. By arguing for the indispensable relevance of intention in the moral evaluation of acts, the book moves against a mainstream, 'objective' approach in normative ethics. It is commonly held that the intentions, knowledge, and volition of agents are irrelevant to the moral permissibility of their acts. This book stresses that the capacities of agency, rather than simply the label 'agent', must be engaged during an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Mental acts as natural kinds.Joëlle Proust - 2013 - In Andy Clark, Julian Kiverstein & Tillmann Vierkant (eds.), Decomposing the Will. , US: Oxford University Press USA. pp. 262-282.
    This chapter examines whether, and in what sense, one can speak of agentive mental events. An adequate characterization of mental acts should respond to three main worries. First, mental acts cannot have pre-specified goal contents. For example, one cannot prespecify the content of a judgment or of a deliberation. Second, mental acts seem to depend crucially on receptive attitudes. Third, it does not seem that intentions play any role in mental actions. Given these three constraints, mental and bodily actions appear (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  48
    The Impact of the Patient Self-Determination Act's Requirement That States Describe Law concerning Patients' Rights.Joan M. Teno, Charles Sabatino, Fenella Rouse & Joanne Lynn - 1993 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 21 (1):102-108.
    As of December 1991, the Patient Self-Determination Act mandated that health care institutions which receive funding from Medicare or Medicaid provide written information about persons rights to participate in medical decision-making and formulate advance directives. The PSDA required each state…acting through a State agency, association, or other private nonprofit entity develop a written description of the law of the State concerning advance directives that would be distributed by providers or organizations under the requirements of [the Act].
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  80
    Speech Acts, Attitudes, and Scientific Practice: Can Searle Handle "Assuming for the Sake of Hypothesis?".Daniel J. McKaughan - 2012 - Pragmatics and Cognition 20 (1):88-106.
    There are certain illocutionary acts that, contrary to John Searle's speech act theory, cannot be correctly classified as assertives. Searle's sincerity and essential conditions on assertives require, plausibly, that we believe our assertions and that we are committed to their truth. Yet it is a commonly accepted scientific practice to propose and investigate an hypothesis without believing it or being at all committed to its truth. Searle's attempt to accommodate such conjectural acts by claiming that the degree of belief and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  26
    Can the consent provisions in the Choice on Termination of Pregnancy Act, which do not require children to be assisted by a parent or guardian, be used for live births by caesarian section in emergency situations?David Jan McQuoid-Mason - 2018 - South African Journal of Bioethics and Law 11 (1):43.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  22
    Act or Revolution? Yes, Please!Santiago M. Roggerone - 2013 - International Journal of Žižek Studies 7 (3).
    As a part of an attempt to account for the status of Marxism today, this paper explores Slavoj Žižek’s Theory of the Act. Given that, to a point, this theory constitutes a neutralization of certain postmodernist challenges, the paper presents its materialistic-ontological assumptions and genealogically restores its most important conceptual components. It also questions the link between Žižek’s Theory of the Act and the communist Idea and partially elucidates the differences between Žižek’s stance and the post-Marxism of authors such as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Speech acts without propositions?Marina Sbisà - 2006 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 72 (1):155-178.
    This paper argues that understanding speech in terms of action requires dispensing with propositions. Austin's outline of speech act theory did not give any role to propositions, which were introduced into speech act theory later on, in order to cope with criticism leveled by Strawson and Searle at Austin's characterization of the locutionary act and his view of the truth/falsity assessment. The introduction of propositions had weakening effects on the claim that speech is action, foregrounding again the received picture of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Is Objective Act Consequentialism satisfiable?Johan E. Gustafsson - 2019 - Analysis 79 (2):193-202.
    A compelling requirement on normative theories is that they should be satisfiable, that is, in every possible choice situation with a finite number of alternatives, there should be at least one performable act such that, if one were to perform that act, one would comply with the theory. In this paper, I argue that, given some standard assumptions about free will and counterfactuals, Objective Act Consequentialism violates this requirement.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  39
    Bringing Transparency to Medicine: Exploring Physicians' Views and Experiences of the Sunshine Act.Susan Chimonas, Nicholas J. DeVito & David J. Rothman - 2017 - American Journal of Bioethics 17 (6):4-18.
    The Physician Payments Sunshine Act requires health care product manufacturers to report to the federal government payments more than $10 to physicians. Bringing unprecedented transparency to medicine, PPSA holds great potential for enabling medical stakeholders to manage conflicts of interest and build patient trust—crucial responsibilities of medical professionalism. The authors conducted six focus groups with 42 physicians in Chicago, IL, San Francisco, CA, and Washington, DC, to explore attitudes and experiences around PPSA. Participants valued the concept of transparency but were (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  30. Acts of tolerance: A political and descriptive account.Peter Balint - 2014 - European Journal of Political Theory 13 (3):264-281.
    Almost all philosophical understandings of tolerance as forbearance require that the reasons for objection and/or the reasons for withholding the power to negatively interfere must be of the morally right kind. In this paper, I instead put forward a descriptive account of an act of tolerance and argue that in the political context, at least, it has several important advantages over the standard more moralised accounts. These advantages include that it better addresses instances of intolerance and that it is able (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  31.  25
    Listening, Acting, and the Quest for Alternatives: A Response to Charland and Bracken.Erica Lilleleht - 2002 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 9 (2):189-191.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 9.2 (2002) 189-191 [Access article in PDF] Listening, Acting, and the Quest for AlternativesA Response to Charland and Bracken Erica Lilleleht The challenge is not to replace one certitude... with another but to cultivate an attention to the conditions under which things become 'evident,'... ceasing to be objects of our attention and therefore seeming fixed, necessary, and unchangeable. (Rabinow on Foucault 1997, p. XIX) I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  26
    Speech Acts and Non-Extensionality.A. C. Genova - 1976 - Review of Metaphysics 29 (3):401 - 430.
    My central concern is to show that attempts to resolve problems of non-extensionality in abstraction from speech act theory are unsatisfactory. Generally, I shall argue that speech act theory identifies the various units, levels, and dimensions of analysis which are relevant to the problem of non-extensionality. To ignore or underplay this results in interpretations of non-extensionality which are counter-intuitive and plagued with counter-examples. In what follows, I shall first distinguish what I take to be the essential ingredients of the problem (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  61
    Speech act conditions as tools for reconstructing argumentative discourse.FransH Eemeren & Rob Grootendorst - 1989 - Argumentation 3 (4):367-383.
    According to the pragma-dialectical approach to argumentation, for analysing argumentative discourse, a normative reconstruction is required which encompasses four kinds of transformations. It is explained in this paper how speech act conditions can play a part in carrying out such a reconstruction. It is argued that integrating Searlean insights concerning speech acts with Gricean insights concerning conversational maxims can provide us with the necessary tools. For this, the standard theory of speech acts has to be amended in several respects and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34.  34
    Social Acts and Communities: Walther Between Husserl and Reinach.Alessandro Salice & Genki Uemura - 2018 - In Antonio Calcagno (ed.), Gerda Walther's Phenomenology of Sociality, Psychology, and Religion. Cham: Imprint: Springer. pp. 27-46.
    The chapter contextualizes and reconstructs Walther’s theory of social acts. In her view a given act qualifies as social if it is performed in the name of or on behalf of a community. Interestingly, Walther’s understanding of that notion is patently at odds with the idea of a social act originally propounded by Reinach. According to Reinach, an act is social if it “addresses” other persons and if it, for its success, requires them to grasp it. We claim that to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  35.  93
    Intentions to Report Questionable Acts: An Examination of the Influence of Anonymous Reporting Channel, Internal Audit Quality, and Setting.Steven E. Kaplan & Joseph J. Schultz - 2007 - Journal of Business Ethics 71 (2):109-124.
    The Sarbanes–Oxley Act of 2002 requires audit committees of public companies’ boards of directors to install an anonymous reporting channel to assist in deterring and detecting accounting fraud and control weaknesses. While it is generally accepted that the availability of such a reporting channel may reduce the reporting cost of the observer of a questionable act, there is concern that the addition of such a channel may decrease the overall effectiveness compared to a system employing only non-anonymous reporting options. The (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  36.  48
    Conditions required for a law on active voluntary euthanasia: a survey of nurses' opinions in the Australian Capital Territory.B. Kitchener & A. F. Jorm - 1999 - Journal of Medical Ethics 25 (1):25-30.
    OBJECTIVES: To ascertain which conditions nurses believe should be in a law allowing active voluntary euthanasia (AVE). DESIGN: Survey questionnaire posted to registered nurses (RNs). SETTING: Australian Capital Territory (ACT) at the end of 1996, when active voluntary euthanasia was legal in the Northern Territory. SURVEY SAMPLE: A random sample of 2,000 RNs, representing 54 per cent of the RN population in the ACT. MAIN MEASURES: Two methods were used to look at nurses' opinions. The first involved four vignettes which (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Acting Without Reasons.Josep L. Prades - 2007 - Disputatio 2 (23):229-246.
    In this paper, I want to challenge some common assumptions in contemporary theories of practical rationality and intentional action. If I am right, the fact that our intentions can be rationalised is widely misunderstood. Normally, it is taken for granted that the role of rationalisations is to show the reasons that the agent had to make up her mind. I will argue against this. I do not object to the idea that acting intentionally is, at least normally, acting for reasons, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  20
    Guilty acts, guilty minds / c Stephen P. Garvey.Stephen P. Garvey - 2020 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    You can't be convicted of a crime without a guilty act and a guilty mind." A lawyer might dress the same idea up in Latin: "You can't be convicted of a crime without actus reus and mens rea." Things like that are often said, but what do people mean when they say them? Guilty Acts, Guilty Minds proposes an understanding of mens rea and actus reus as limits on the authority of a state, and in particular the authority of a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Acting without reasons.José Luis Prades Celma - 2007 - Disputatio 2 (23):1-18.
    In this paper, I want to challenge some common assumptions in contemporary theories of practical rationality and intentional action. If I am right, the fact that our intentions can be rationalised is widely misunderstood. Normally, it is taken for granted that the role of rationalisations is to show the reasons that the agent had to make up her mind. I will argue against this. I do not object to the idea that acting intentionally is, at least normally, acting for reasons, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Act and Principle Contractualism.Hanoch Sheinman - 2011 - Utilitas 23 (3):288-315.
    Unrejectability is the property shared by things no one could reasonably reject. Following the lead of T. M. Scanlon, modern contractualists hold Principle Contractualism: An act is obligatory when conformity to unrejectable principles requires its performance. This article entertains Act Contractualism: An act is obligatory when its performance is unrejectable. The article hypothesizes that Principle Contractualism owes its initial plausibility to the assumption that following it somehow realizes unrejectability, if only indirectly. The article then argues that, whereas following Act Contractualism (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  41. Acts, Omissions, Emissions.Garrett Cullity - 2015 - In Jeremy Moss (ed.), Climate Change and Justice. Cambridge University Press. pp. 148-64.
    What requirements does morality impose on us in relation to climate change? This question can be asked of individuals, of the entire global population, and of groups of various sizes in between. Given the case for accepting that we all collectively ought to be causing less climate-affecting pollution than we do, what follows from that about the moral status of the actions of members of the larger group? I examine two main ways in which moral requirements on group members can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  42. Moral requirements are still not rational requirements.Paul Noordhof - 1999 - Analysis 59 (3):127-136.
    Moral requirements apply to rational agents as such. But it is a conceptual truth that if agents are morally required to act in a certain way then we expect them to act in that way. Being rational, as such, must therefore suffice to ground our expectation that rational agents will do what they are morally required to do. But how could this be so? It could only be so if we think of the moral requirements that apply to agents as (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  84
    The Endangered Species Act, Regulatory Takings, and Public Goods.N. Scott Arnold - 2009 - Social Philosophy and Policy 26 (2):353-377.
    The Endangered Species Act (ESA) can impose significant limitations on what landowners may do with their property, especially as it pertains to development. These restrictions imposed by the ESA are part of a larger controversy about the reach of the “Takings Clause” of the Fifth Amendment, which says that private property shall not be taken for public use without just compensation. The question this paper addresses is whether these restrictions require compensation. The paper develops a position on the general question (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  22
    Acting from the Virtue of Caring in Nursing.Stan van Hooft - 1999 - Nursing Ethics 6 (3):189-201.
    The author challenges the recently argued position of Helga Kuhse that caring is merely a preparatory stage to moral action and that impartial, principled thinking is required to make action moral, by suggesting a notion of caring as virtue. If caring is a virtue then acting from that virtue will be acting well. Acting from the virtue of caring involves eight features, which include not only that of being sensitive to, and concerned about, the patient, but also that of being (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  45.  81
    Moral Heroism and the Requirement Claim.Kyle Fruh - 2014 - Southwest Philosophy Review 30 (1):93-104.
    Acts of moral heroism are often described by heroes as having been in some sense or another required. Here I elaborate two rival strategies for accounting for what I call the requirement claim. The first, originating with J.O. Urmson, attempts to explain away the phenomenon. The second and more popular among moralists is to treat the requirement claim as a moment of moral insight and to make sense of it in terms of moral duty. I argue that both (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  25
    The Equality Act, 2010.Stephen Humphreys - 2010 - Research Ethics 6 (3):95-95.
    The Equality Act 2010 brings the concept of indirect discrimination to discrimination on the grounds of religion or belief. This has real potential to require a change in practice in certain types of clinical trials of which relevant ethics committees should be aware.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. II—Acting ‘of One's Own Free Will’: Modern Reflections on an Ancient Philosophical Problem.Robert Kane - 2014 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114 (1pt1):35-55.
    Over the past five decades, I have been developing a distinctive view of free will according to which it requires that agents be to some degree ultimately responsible for the formation of their own wills. To act ‘of one's own free will’ in this sense is to act ‘from a will’ that is to some extent ‘of one's own free making’. A free will of this ultimate kind has been under attack in the modern era as obscure and unintelligible. In (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48.  44
    Speech act conditions as tools for reconstructing argumentative discourse.Frans H. van Eemeren & Rob Grootendorst - 1989 - Argumentation 3 (4):367-383.
    According to the pragma-dialectical approach to argumentation, for analysing argumentative discourse, a normative reconstruction is required which encompasses four kinds of transformations. It is explained in this paper how speech act conditions can play a part in carrying out such a reconstruction. It is argued that integrating Searlean insights concerning speech acts with Gricean insights concerning conversational maxims can provide us with the necessary tools. For this, the standard theory of speech acts has to be amended in several respects and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  13
    Against the Religious Neutrality Requirement.Henrik Friberg-Fernros - 2022 - Ratio Juris 35 (4):383-400.
    One element of the liberal ideal of secularity is the principle that the state should treat religions neutrally: This is the religious neutrality requirement. Applied to religious belief systems, the principle stipulates that the state should not take a position on whether or not a certain religion is true. I challenge this ideal and argue that teachers in public schools sometimes need to take a position on religious truth claims in order to avoid the risk of promoting false beliefs. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  23
    Understanding Miscommunication: Speech Act Recognition in Digital Contexts.Thomas Holtgraves - 2021 - Cognitive Science 45 (10):e13023.
    Successful language use requires accurate intention recognition. However, sometimes this can be undermined because communication occurs within an interpersonal context. In this research, I used a relatively large set of speech acts (n = 32) and explored how variability in their inherent face‐threat influences the extent to which they are successfully recognized by a recipient, as well as the confidence of senders and receivers in their communicative success. Participants in two experiments either created text messages (senders) designed to perform a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 968