Results for 'Keith Lindblom'

968 found
Order:
  1.  36
    Lindblom (continued from page 28).Keith Lindblom - 1991 - Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 7 (4):44-44.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  41
    Critical Thinking in a Secondary School.Keith Lindblom - 1991 - Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 7 (4):28-28.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Proper names and identifying descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1970 - Synthese 21 (3-4):335 - 358.
  4. The Case for Contextualism: Knowledge, Skepticism, and Context, Vol. 1.Keith DeRose - 2009 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Contextualism has been hotly debated in recent epistemology and philosophy of language. The Case for Contextualism is a state-of-the-art exposition and defense of the contextualist position, presenting and advancing the most powerful arguments in favor of the view and responding to the most pressing objections facing it.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  5.  72
    Logic and Information.Keith Devlin - 1991 - Cambridge University Press.
    Classical logic, beginning with the work of Aristotle, has developed into a powerful and rigorous mathematical theory with many applications in mathematics and ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  6. Putting humpty dumpty together again.Keith S. Donnellan - 1968 - Philosophical Review 77 (2):203-215.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  7.  86
    Universality and the Liar: An Essay on Truth and the Diagonal Argument.Keith Simmons - 1993 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    This book is about one of the most baffling of all paradoxes – the famous Liar paradox. Suppose we say: 'We are lying now'. Then if we are lying, we are telling the truth; and if we are telling the truth we are lying. This paradox is more than an intriguing puzzle, since it involves the concept of truth. Thus any coherent theory of truth must deal with the Liar. Keith Simmons discusses the solutions proposed by medieval philosophers and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  8. Inter-species variation in colour perception.Keith Allen - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 142 (2):197 - 220.
    Inter-species variation in colour perception poses a serious problem for the view that colours are mind-independent properties. Given that colour perception varies so drastically across species, which species perceives colours as they really are? In this paper, I argue that all do. Specifically, I argue that members of different species perceive properties that are determinates of different, mutually compatible, determinables. This is an instance of a general selectionist strategy for dealing with cases of perceptual variation. According to selectionist views, objects (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  9. Ought we to follow our evidence?Keith Derose - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (3):697-706.
    fits our evidence.[1] I will propose some potential counter-examples to test this evidentialist thesis. My main intention in presenting the “counter-examples” is to better understand Feldman’s evidentialism, and evidentialism in general. How are we to understand what our evidence is, how it works, and how are we to understand the phrase “epistemically ought to believe” such that evidentialism might make sense as a plausible thesis in light of the examples? Of course, we may decide that there’s no such way to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  10. Deciding to Believe Again.Keith Frankish - 2007 - Mind 116 (463):523 - 547.
    This paper defends direct activism-the view that it is possible to form beliefs in a causally direct way. In particular, it addresses the charge that direct activism entails voluntarism-the thesis that we can form beliefs at will. It distinguishes weak and strong varieties of voluntarism and argues that, although direct activism may entail the weak variety, it does not entail the strong one. The paper goes on to argue that strong voluntarism is non-contingently false, sketching a new argument for that (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  11. Freedom, republicanism, and workplace democracy.Keith Breen - 2015 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 18 (4):470-485.
  12. The mind-independence of colour.Keith Allen - 2007 - European Journal of Philosophy 15 (2):137–158.
    The view that the mind-dependence of colour is implicit in our ordinary thinking has a distinguished history. With its origins in Berkeley, the view has proved especially popular amongst so-called ‘Oxford’ philosophers, proponents including Cook Wilson (1904: 773-4), Pritchard (1909: 86-7), Ryle (1949: 209), Kneale (1950: 123) and McDowell (1985: 112). Gareth Evans’s discussion of secondary qualities in “Things Without the Mind” is representative of this tradition. It is his version of the view that I consider in this paper.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  13.  94
    Counterfactual success and negative freedom.Keith Dowding & Martin van Hees - 2007 - Economics and Philosophy 23 (2):141-162.
    Recent theories of negative freedom see it as a value-neutral concept; the definition of freedom should not be in terms of specific moral values. Specifically, preferences or desires do not enter into the definition of freedom. If preferences should so enter then Berlin's problem that a person may enhance their freedom by changing their preferences emerges. This paper demonstrates that such a preference-free conception brings its own counter-intuitive problems. It concludes that these problems might be avoided if the description of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  14. (1 other version)Condorcet: From Natural Philosophy to Social Mathematics.Keith Michael Baker - 1975 - Political Theory 3 (4):469-474.
  15. Now you know it, now you don’t.Keith DeRose - 2000 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 5:91-106.
    Resistance to contextualism comes in the form of many very different types of objections. My topic here is a certain group or family of related objections to contextualism that I call “Now you know it, now you don’t” objections. I responded to some such objections in my “Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions” a few years back. In what follows here, I will expand on that earlier response in various ways, and, in doing so, I will discuss some aspects of David Lewis’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  16. How Can We Know that We're Not Brains in Vats?Keith DeRose - 2000 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (S1):121-148.
    This should be fairly close to the text of this paper as it appears in The Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (2000), Spindel Conference Supplement: 121-148.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  17.  33
    Multiculturalism and the Welfare State: Recognition and Redistribution in Contemporary Democracies.Keith Banting & Will Kymlicka (eds.) - 2006 - Oxford University Press.
    Does the increasing politicization of ethnic and racial diversity of Western societies threaten to undermine the welfare state? This volume is the first systematic attempt to explore this linkage between "the politics of recognition" and "the politics of redistribution".
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  18. Gradable adjectives: A defence of pluralism.Keith DeRose - 2008 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (1):141-160.
    This paper attacks the Implicit Reference Class Theory of gradable adjectives and proposes instead a ?pluralist? approach to the semantics of those terms, according to which they can be governed by a variety of different types of standards, one, but only one, of which is the group-indexed standards utilized by the Implicit Reference Class Theory.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  19. (1 other version)Educational philosophy and the challenge of complexity theory.Keith Morrison - 2008 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 40 (1):19–34.
    Complexity theory challenges educational philosophy to reconsider accepted paradigms of teaching, learning and educational research. However, though attractive, not least because of its critique of positivism, its affinity to Dewey and Habermas, and its arguments for openness, diversity, relationships, agency and creativity, the theory is not without its difficulties. These are seen to lie in terms of complexity theory's nature, status, methodology, utility and contribution to the philosophy of education, being a descriptive theory that is easily misunderstood as a prescriptive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  20. Natural language and virtual belief.Keith Frankish - 1998 - In Peter Carruthers & Jill Boucher (eds.), Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 248.
    This chapter outlines a new argument for the view that language has a cognitive role. I suggest that humans exhibit two distinct kinds of belief state, one passively formed, the other actively formed. I argue that actively formed beliefs (_virtual beliefs_, as I call them) can be identified with _premising policies_, and that forming them typically involves certain linguistic operations. I conclude that natural language has at least a limited cognitive role in the formation and manipulation of virtual beliefs.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  21. Relevant Alternatives and the Content of Knowledge Attributions.Keith Derose - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (1):193-197.
    In “Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions,” I argue that advocates of the “Relevant Alternatives” theory of knowledge fall into certain mistakes result if they tie the content of a knowledge attribution, on a given occasion of use, too tightly to what the range of relevant alternatives is on that occasion, and I sketch an alternative approach to the issues involved that avoids such mistakes. In “The Shifting Content of Knowledge Attributions,” Anthony Brueckner charges that my own account of these matters falls (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  22.  66
    Can capabilities reconcile freedom and equality?Keith Dowding - 2006 - Journal of Political Philosophy 14 (3):323–336.
  23.  55
    Learning During Processing: Word Learning Doesn't Wait for Word Recognition to Finish.S. Apfelbaum Keith & McMurray Bob - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (S4):706-747.
    Previous research on associative learning has uncovered detailed aspects of the process, including what types of things are learned, how they are learned, and where in the brain such learning occurs. However, perceptual processes, such as stimulus recognition and identification, take time to unfold. Previous studies of learning have not addressed when, during the course of these dynamic recognition processes, learned representations are formed and updated. If learned representations are formed and updated while recognition is ongoing, the result of learning (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  76
    Personal and social knowledge.Keith Lehrer - 1987 - Synthese 73 (1):87 - 107.
    This paper is an investigation of the relation between personal and social conditions of knowledge. A coherence theory of knowledge and justification is assumed, according to which incoming information is evaluated in terms of background information. The evaluation of incoming information in terms of background information is a higher order or metamental activity. Personal knowledge and justification is based on the coherent integration of individual information. Social knowledge and justification is based on the coherent aggregation of social information, that is, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  25.  54
    Emotional appeals in politics and deliberation.Keith Dowding - 2018 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 21 (2):242-260.
    This is, no doubt, an emotional response, but there are, I believe, occasions when an emotional response is the only intellectually honest one. Brian Barry (1975, p. 332)Deliberative democracy is o...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  26. On an argument against omniscience.Keith Simmons - 1993 - Noûs 27 (1):22-33.
  27. Integrating text and pictorial information: eye movements when looking at print advertisements.Keith Rayner, Caren M. Rotello, Andrew J. Stewart, Jessica Keir & Susan A. Duffy - 2001 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 7 (3):219.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  28.  32
    After the Science Wars: Science and the Study of Science.Keith Ashman & Phillip Barringer (eds.) - 2000 - Routledge.
    The "War" in science is largely the discussion between those who believe that science is above criticism and those who do not. After the Science Wars is a collection of essays by leading philosophers and scientists, all attempting to bridge interdisciplinary gulfs in this discussion.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29. Ethical issues in tissue banking for research: A brief review of existing organizational policies.Keith Bauer, Sara Taub & Kayhan Parsi - 2004 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 25 (2):113-142.
    Based on a general review of international, representative tissue banking policies that were described in the medical, ethics, and legal literature, this paper reviews the range of standards, both conceptually and in existing regulations, relevant to four main factors:(1) commercialization, (2) confidentiality, (3) informed consent, and (4) quality of research. These four factors were selected as reflective of some of the major ethical considerations that arise in the conduct of tissue banking research. The authors emphasize that any policy or ethical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30. Divine Necessity and Divine Goodness.Keith Yandell - 1988 - In Thomas V. Morris (ed.), Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. pp. 313–344.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  50
    Manifestos for history.Keith Jenkins, Sue Morgan & Alun Munslow (eds.) - 2007 - New York: Routledge.
    P EM Manifestos for History /EM is a thought-provoking and controversial text that, through a star studded collection of essays, presents a wide ranging ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  59
    Imaginary naturalism: the natural and primitive in Wittgenstein’s later thought.Keith Dromm - 2003 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (4):673 – 690.
  33. Temporal asymmetry in classical mechanics.Keith Hutchison - 1995 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (2):219-234.
    This paper argues against a standard view that all deterministic and conservative classical mechanical systems are time-reversible, by asking how the temporal evolution of a system modulates parametric imprecision (either ontological or epistemic). It notes that well-behaved systems (e.g. inertial motion) can possess a dynamics which is unstable enough to fail at reversing uncertainties—even though exact values are reliably reversed. A limited (but significant) source of irreversibility is thus displayed in classical mechanics, closely analogous the lack of predictability revealed by (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34. Content, computation, and individuation.Keith Butler - 1998 - Synthese 114 (2):277-92.
    The role of content in computational accounts of cognition is a matter of some controversy. An early prominent view held that the explanatory relevance of content consists in its supervenience on the the formal properties of computational states (see, e.g., Fodor 1980). For reasons that derive from the familiar Twin Earth thought experiments, it is usually thought that if content is to supervene on formal properties, it must be narrow; that is, it must not be the sort of content that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  19
    Personalized Medicine in the NICU.Keith J. Barrington - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (12):33-35.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  47
    Commentary: Does Cognitive Behavior Therapy for psychosis show a sustainable effect on delusions? A meta-analysis.Keith R. Laws - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  54
    (1 other version)What motivates eliminativism?Keith Campbell - 1993 - Mind and Language 8 (2):206-210.
  38.  30
    Leaping to Conclusions: Why Premise Relevance Affects Argument Strength.Keith J. Ransom, Amy Perfors & Daniel J. Navarro - 2016 - Cognitive Science 40 (7):1775-1796.
    Everyday reasoning requires more evidence than raw data alone can provide. We explore the idea that people can go beyond this data by reasoning about how the data was sampled. This idea is investigated through an examination of premise non-monotonicity, in which adding premises to a category-based argument weakens rather than strengthens it. Relevance theories explain this phenomenon in terms of people's sensitivity to the relationships among premise items. We show that a Bayesian model of category-based induction taking premise sampling (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39. What is it like to be colour‐blind? A case study in experimental philosophy of experience.Keith Allen, Philip Quinlan, James Andow & Eugen Fischer - 2021 - Mind and Language 37 (5):814-839.
    What is the experience of someone who is “colour‐blind” like? This paper presents the results of a study that uses qualitative research methods to better understand the lived experience of colour blindness. Participants were asked to describe their experiences of a variety of coloured stimuli, both with and without EnChroma glasses—glasses which, the manufacturers claim, enhance the experience of people with common forms of colour blindness. More generally, the paper provides a case study in the nascent field of experimental philosophy (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Divine Action in the World of Physics: Response to Nicholas Saunders.Keith Ward - 2000 - Zygon 35 (4):901-906.
    Nicholas Saunders claims that, in my view, divine action requires and is confined to indeterminacies at the quantum level. I try to make clear that, in speaking of “gaps” in physical causality, I mean that the existence of intentions entails that determining law explanations alone cannot give a complete account of the natural world. By “indeterminacy” I mean a general (not quantum) lack of determining causality in the physical order. Construing physical causality in terms of dispositional properties variously realized in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41. How should we revise the paratactic theory?Keith Frankish - 1996 - Analysis 56 (4):251–262.
    This paper takes another look at Davidson's paratactic theory of indirect discourse and evaluates some revisions to it, proposed recently by Ian Rumfitt (Mind, 1993). Davidson's original version of the theory – according to which indirect speech reports refer to token utterances – has a problem dealing with ambiguity. Rumfitt suggests that we can solve this problem by supposing that the immediate objects of verbs in indirect speech are token representations of disambiguated LF tree-structures. I argue that this proposal is (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  55
    Contemporary Ethical Issues Within the Australian Defence Force.Keith Joseph - 1998 - Professional Ethics, a Multidisciplinary Journal 6 (3):123-136.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. A third analysis of prediction.Keith Lehrer - 1966 - Theoria 32 (1):71.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  43
    Cognition, consensus and consciousness: my replies.Keith Lehrer - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 161 (1):163-184.
  45.  34
    Coherence, justification, and Chisholm.Keith Lehrer - 1988 - Philosophical Perspectives 2:125-138.
  46.  31
    Denying deception: A reply to Terry price.Keith Lehrer - 1994 - Philosophical Studies 74 (3):283 - 290.
  47.  32
    Neglecting to do what one can: A reply.Keith Lehrer - 1969 - Mind 78 (309):121-123.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  25
    Our Knowledge of Other Selves.Keith Lehrer & Margaret Chatterjee - 1967 - Philosophical Review 76 (1):127.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  14
    Rationality and Trustworthiness.Keith Lehrer - 1996 - ProtoSociology 8:183-196.
    Our rationality depends on the reasons we have for accepting and preferring what we do. But where do reasons come from? What makes what I accept a reason for a conclusion or what I prefer a reason for action? We can explain where reasons come from without postulation or regress. The explanation rests on our trustworthiness combined with our acceptance of it and our preference for it. The explanation reveals that theoretical and practical reason are intertwined in a loop of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  20
    Reply to Marian David.Keith Lehrer - 1991 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 40:108-111.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 968