Results for 'Morally Good'

966 found
Order:
  1. Christopher Winch.Good Lives & Moral Education - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 25 (1):129.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2. Morally Good Intentions.Michael Stocker - 1970 - The Monist 54 (1):124-141.
    In this paper I present an analysis of morally good intentions. My starting point is one version of what can be called The Traditional Analysis.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  11
    Moral Goodness.Richard Swinburne - 1989 - In Responsibility and atonement. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter distinguishes various kinds of moral goodness. Actions may be objectively good and/or subjectively good; and they may be supererogatory or obligatory. Actions may be objectively or subjectively bad, and wrong or merely infrarvetatory. There is goodness either in good actions being done naturally, or in their being done contrary to inclination. There are three kinds of goodness of character: agents may be naturally inclined to do actions that are in fact good, they may have (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  66
    Moral goodness, esteem, and acting from duty.Noah M. Lemos - 1991 - Journal of Value Inquiry 25 (2):103-117.
    There is a long tradition in moral philosophy which maintains that a necessary condition for moral goodness is that one act from a sense of duty. Kant is perhaps the best known and most discussed representative of this view, but one finds others prior to Kant, such as Butler and Price, and Kant's contemporaries, such as Reid, expressing similar ideas. Price, for example writes, ". . . what I have chiefly insisted on, is, that we characterize as virtuous no actions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. Divine moral goodness, supererogation and The Euthyphro Dilemma.Alfred Archer - 2016 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 79 (2):147-160.
    How can we make sense of God’s moral goodness if God cannot be subject to moral obligations? This question is troubling for divine command theorists, as if we cannot make sense of God’s moral goodness then it seems hard to see how God’s commands could be morally good. Alston argues that the concept of supererogation solves this problem. If we accept the existence of acts that are morally good but not morally required then we should (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6. The Moral Aspect of Nonmoral Goods and Evils.I. What Admirable Immorality & Nonadmirable Morality Are - 1999 - Utilitas 11 (1).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  20
    Economic Inequality Increases the Preference for Status Consumption.Andrea Velandia-Morales, Rosa Rodríguez-Bailón & Rocío Martínez - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Prior research has shown the relationship between objective economic inequality and searching for positional goods. It also investigated the relationship between social class and low income with conspicuous consumption. However, the causal relationship between economic inequality has been less explored. Furthermore, there are also few studies looking for the psychological mechanisms that underlie these effects. The current research’s main goal is to analyze the consequences of perceived economic inequality on conspicuous and status consumption and the possible psychological mechanisms that could (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  68
    An interdisciplinary approach to brain evolution: A long due debate.Francisco Aboitiz, Daniver Morales & Juan Montiel - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (5):572-576.
    A dorsalization mechanism is a good candidate for the evolutionary origin of the isocortex, producing a radial and tangential expansion of the dorsal pallium (and perhaps other structures that acquired a cortical phenotype). Evidence suggests that a large part of the dorsal ventricular ridge (DVR) of reptiles and birds derives from the embryonic ventral pallium, whereas the isocortex possibly derives mostly from the dorsal pallium. In early mammals, the development of olfactory-hippocampal associative networks may have been pivotal in facilitating (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Moral goodness as happiness according to Aristotle-formal definition and metaphysical prerequisites.Horst Seidl - 1975 - Philosophisches Jahrbuch 82 (1):31-53.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  47
    Toward safe AI.Andres Morales-Forero, Samuel Bassetto & Eric Coatanea - 2023 - AI and Society 38 (2):685-696.
    Since some AI algorithms with high predictive power have impacted human integrity, safety has become a crucial challenge in adopting and deploying AI. Although it is impossible to prevent an algorithm from failing in complex tasks, it is crucial to ensure that it fails safely, especially if it is a critical system. Moreover, due to AI’s unbridled development, it is imperative to minimize the methodological gaps in these systems’ engineering. This paper uses the well-known Box-Jenkins method for statistical modeling as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  22
    The Moral Good and Normative Nature in the Aristotelian Ethics.Robert Geis - 2013 - Review of Metaphysics 67 (2):291-310.
    Nature as the source of moral ordinance in Aristotle received doubt with the publication of J. Donald Monan’s Moral Knowledge and Its Methodology in Aristotle. Arguing for an earlier versus later Aristotle, he opined for the φρόνιμος as Aristotle’s final word on the criterion for ethical right. “Normative Nature and the Moral Good in the Aristotelian Ethics” argues exegetically and on Aristotelian grounds the inaccuracy of such a view. As early as the Protrepticus, Nature as the guide to proper (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  43
    The Moral Good and the Natural Good in Kant's Ethics.John R. Silber - 1982 - Review of Metaphysics 36 (2):397 - 437.
    THE heterogeneity of the good--its division into the moral good, as virtue, and the natural good, as happiness--is central to Kant's philosophy. In order to clarify and sustain this division, Kant was compelled to specify the valuational characteristics of each kind of good and their relation to one another. But in trying to analyze the good in its heterogeneity Kant faced a terminological difficulty. He could no longer speak simply of "the good" without speaking (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  28
    Moral Goodness Alone Is ‘Good Without Qualifications’.Josef Seifert - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 44:223-230.
    Kant says that moral values are ‘good without qualification.’ This assertion and similar remarks of Plato can be understood in terms of a return to moral data themselves in the following ways: 1. Moral values are objectively good and not relative to our judgments; 2. Moral goodness is intrinsic goodness grounded in the nature of acts and independent of our subjective satisfaction; 3. Moral goodness expresses in an essentially new and higher sense of the idea of value as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  16
    Moral Goodness.W. D. Ross - 1930 - In William David Ross, The Right and the Good. Some Problems in Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    This is the last of five chapters on good, and examines moral goodness. Ross explains the concept of morally good as either being a certain sort of character or being related in one of certain definite ways to a certain sort of character. The matter of what kinds of things are morally good is then addressed, and further advances made in defining moral goodness. These begin by considering Immanuel Kant's views on the desire to do (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. God’s moral goodness and supererogation.Elizabeth Drummond Young - 2013 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 73 (2):83-95.
    What do we understand by God’s goodness? William Alston claims that by answering this question convincingly, divine command theory can be strengthened against some major objections. He rejects the idea that God’s goodness lies in the area of moral obligations. Instead, he proposes that God’s goodness is best described by the phenomenon of supererogation. Joseph Lombardi, in response, agrees with Alston that God does not have moral obligations but says that having rejected moral obligation as the content of divine goodness, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16. Equality as Reciprocity: John Stuart Mill's "the Subjection of Women".Maria Helena Morales - 1992 - Dissertation, University of Pennsylvania
    I put equality at the center of John Stuart Mill's practical philosophy. His principle of "perfect equality" embodies a substantive relational ideal, which I call "equality as reciprocity." This ideal requires removing injustices due to domination and subjection in human associations, including the family. Justice grounded on perfect equality must be the basis of personal, social, and political life, because the moral sentiments, chief among human beings' "higher" faculties, find adequate channels only under equality. Genuine happiness, which involves the exercise (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  33
    On understanding people, structure, desires, and ourselves.Felipe Morales - 2021 - Cinta de Moebio 72:183-193.
    Stephen Grimm defends the idea that for understanding people, we need to think of understanding not only in terms of grasp of structure but also in terms of a notion of understanding-as-taking-to-be-good. In this paper, I critically examine this idea. First, I argue that in some cases, understanding-as-taking-to-be-good can be explained in terms of understanding-as-grasp-of-structure. Then, I consider one further way in which understanding-as-taking-to-be-good could be obtained through something which is not a form of grasp of structure, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  49
    Immediate Certainty and the Morally Good: Luther, Kierkegaard and Cognitive Psychology.Jörg Disse - 2020 - In Marius Timmann Mjaaland, The Reformation of Philosophy. Mohr Siebeck. pp. 109-118.
    I consider the relationship between the notion of certainty and the notion of a form of life. There are circumstances under which a feeling of certainty may become the ground for adopting a certain form of life. The forms of life I have in mind are those with a formal orientation towards the realization of the (morally) good for its own sake. The article proceeds in three steps: First I consider Luther’s certainty of salvation as a kind of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  92
    Morally Good and Morally Right.John A. Oesterle - 1970 - The Monist 54 (1):31-39.
    Let us understand at the outset that by “morally good” we mean the state of possessing what is generally regarded as good character, rooted in virtue, in the broad sense of this term that embraces a variety of particular virtues such as courage, justice, temperance and the like. It is the meaning behind such popular expressions as ‘he is a man of upright character’, ‘a solid citizen’, or, simply, ‘he is a good man’. Let us understand (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  59
    The assessment of individual moral goodness.Raymond B. Chiu & Rick D. Hackett - 2016 - Business Ethics: A European Review 26 (1):31-46.
    In a field dominated by research on moral prescription and moral prediction, there is poor understanding of the place of moral perceptions in organizations alongside philosophical ethics and causal models of ethical outcomes. As leadership failures continue to plague organizational health and firms recognize the wide-ranging impact of subjective bias, scholars and practitioners need a renewed frame of reference from which to reconceptualize their current understanding of ethics as perceived in individuals. Based on an assessment and selection perspective from the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  21.  85
    Are morally good actions ever free?Cory J. Clark, Adam Shniderman, Jamie B. Luguri, Roy F. Baumeister & Peter H. Ditto - 2018 - Consciousness and Cognition 63 (C):161-182.
  22.  54
    On the Absence of Moral Goodness in Hobbes’s Ethics.Johan Olsthoorn - 2020 - The Journal of Ethics 24 (2):241-266.
    This article reassesses Hobbes’s place in the history of ethics based on the first systematic analysis of his various classifications of formal goodness. The good was traditionally divided into three: profitably good, pleasurably good, and morally good. Across his works, Hobbes replaced the last with pulchrum—a decidedly non-moral form of goodness on his account. I argue that Hobbes’s dismissal of moral goodness was informed by his hedonist conception of the good and accompanied by reinterpretations (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  20
    Morality, goodness and love: A rhetoric for resource management.Craig Millar & Hong-Key Yoon - 2000 - Philosophy and Geography 3 (2):155-172.
    Resource development takes place through the transformation of social institutions. The moral dimension is of crucial importance in the evolution of associated management regimes. More than just a code of ethics, moralities are predicated on what is understood to be ‘the good’. Recognition of the good requires a rhetoric beyond those of power and interest. This paper proposes a rhetoric of love. Within this conception of morality, the management of human relationships becomes understood as an unfolding cycle of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  71
    Morality, goodness and love: A rhetoric for resource management.Craig Millar & Hong-Key Yoon - 2000 - Ethics, Place and Environment 3 (2):155 – 172.
    Resource development takes place through the transformation of social institutions. The moral dimension is of crucial importance in the evolution of associated management regimes. More than just a code of ethics, moralities are predicated on what is understood to be 'the good'. Recognition of the good requires a rhetoric beyond those of power and interest. This paper proposes a rhetoric of love. Within this conception of morality, the management of human relationships becomes understood as an unfolding cycle of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25. Hunting as a Moral Good.Lawrence Cahoone - 2009 - Environmental Values 18 (1):67 - 89.
    I argue that hunting is not a sport, but a neo-traditional cultural trophic practice consistent with ecological ethics, including a meliorist concern for animal rights or welfare. Death by hunter is on average less painful than death in wild nature. Hunting achieves goods, including trophic responsibility, ecological expertise and a unique experience of animal inter-dependence. Hunting must then be not only permissible but morally good wherever: a) preservation of ecosystems or species requires hunting as a wildlife management tool; (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  26.  95
    Does integrity require moral goodness?Jody L. Graham - 2001 - Ratio 14 (3):234–251.
    Most accounts of integrity agree that the person of integrity must have a relatively stable sense of who he is, what is important to him, and the ability to stand by what is most important to him in the face of pressure to do otherwise. But does integrity place any constraints on the kind of principles that the person of integrity stands for? In response to several recent accounts of integrity, I argue that it is not enough that a person (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  27. Perfect Equality: John Stuart Mill on Well-Constituted Communities.Wendy Donner & Maria H. Morales - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (2):337.
    Maria Morales’s striking and thought-provoking argument in Perfect Equality is that John Stuart Mill’s egalitarianism unifies his practical philosophy and that this element of his thought has been neglected in recent revisionary scholarship. Placing Mill’s arguments for the substantive value of “perfect equality” in The Subjection of Women at the center of her analysis, Morales develops a distinctive interpretation of Mill as an egalitarian liberal. Morales also aims to counter many recent communitarian critiques of liberalism as founded upon a conception (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  39
    In Search of an Objective Moral Good.Francesco Belfiore - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 10:25-32.
    The moral good, being the end that human beings ought to pursue, cannot be defined without referring to what human beings, as ontological entities, actually are. According to my conception, human mind (or spirit or person) is a triadic entity made of intellect, sensitiveness, and power which, through their outward or selfish activity (directed to the external objects), produce ideas, sentiments, and actions, whereas through their inward or moral activity (directed to mind itself), produce moral thoughts, moral feelings, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  27
    How does collaborative economy contribute to common good?Rosario Gomez-Alvarez & Rafael Morales-Sánchez - 2023 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 32 (S2):68-83.
    Collaborative economy emerged as a response to the need of people to exchange, produce and share in a more humane and cooperative manner. However, the growth of collaborative economy organizations and the terminological confusion have led to debates about their possible effects, both positive and negative. In this study, we have created a guideline that can be used to evaluate the contribution of organizations considered within collaborative economy to common good. We used the conceptualization of common good, which, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  43
    Kantian Conceptions of Moral Goodness.John Campbell - 1983 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13 (4):527 - 550.
    There are two general views associated with Kant about the nature of morally good persons and their actions. One view is that one's actions have moral worth only if one is motivated by a sense of duty and not by inclination. The other view is that morally good persons are motivated by reason and not by desire. These two views are not always distinguished. But taken at face value, they do seem distinct. They seem distinct at (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  24
    Moral goodness and the human good.Erling Skorpen - 1968 - Journal of Value Inquiry 2 (2-3):137-156.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Concerning moral good and evil.Francis Hutcheson - 1997 - In Alexander Broadie, The Scottish Enlightenment: an anthology. Edinburgh: Canongate Books. pp. 119--142.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  42
    Augustinian Evil and Moral Good in Lolita.Sean Benson - 2012 - Renascence 64 (4):353-367.
  34.  57
    Moral Good and Ontological Good.Robert W. Schmidt - 1978 - New Scholasticism 52 (3):421-427.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  28
    Moral goodness and the truth of religious claims.Mark Smith - 1981 - Sophia 20 (1):17-24.
  36.  28
    Sensitivity to moral goodness under different aesthetic contexts.Chenjing Wu, Hongyan Zhu, Yameng Zhang, Wei Zhang & Xianyou He - 2024 - Ethics and Behavior 34 (4):279-293.
    Does context influence our appreciation of beauty? To answer this question, two experiments were conducted to determine the effect of contextual aesthetics on the recognition of moral behavior. Experiment 1 demonstrated that individuals in a high-aesthetic context had a quicker recognition time for moral behavior than those in a low-aesthetic context. In a low-aesthetic context, individuals recognize immoral behavior more quickly than in a high aesthetic context. Individuals showed greater recognition rates for moral behavior in a high aesthetic context and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  38
    Symposium: The Moral Good as a Relation between Persons.I. W. Phillips, A. Macbeath & H. F. Hallett - 1939 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 18 (1):106 - 178.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Omnipotence and Moral Goodness.J. E. Barnhart - 1971 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 52 (1):107.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  31
    Music and Moral Goodness.Donald Walhout - 1995 - The Journal of Aesthetic Education 29 (1):5.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  44
    Are There Non-Moral Goods?Henry B. Veatch - 1978 - New Scholasticism 52 (4):471-499.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Virtue is a Great Moral Good.Bradford Cokelet - manuscript
    According to Aristotelian virtue ethicists, virtue is a great moral good that contributes to, but cannot be reduced to, an agent's welfare. In addition, they hold that the value of virtue is different from, and in some sense greater than, the agent-neutral intrinsic goodness that consequentialists attribute to states of affair. According to Thomas Hurka (1998, 2003, 2011), these fundamental Aristotelian views are indefensible. In this paper, I rebuff Hurka's skepticism and identify an Aristotelian view that stands fast in (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Against God’s Moral Goodness.Joseph L. Lombardi - 2005 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 79 (2):313-326.
    While denying that God has moral obligations, William Alston defends divine moral goodness based on God’s performance of supererogatory acts. The present article argues that an agent without obligations cannot perform supererogatory acts. Hence, divine moral goodness cannot be established on that basis. Defenses of divine moral obligation by Eleonore Stump and Nicholas Wolterstorff are also questioned. Against Stump, it is argued (among other things) that the temptations of Jesus do not establish the existence of a tendency to sin in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43.  62
    Natural, Artifactual, and Moral Goodness.Judith K. Crane & Ronald Sandler - 2017 - The Journal of Ethics 21 (3):291-307.
    In Natural Goodness, Philippa Foot aims to provide an account of moral evaluation that is both naturalistic and cognitivist. She argues that moral evaluation is a variety of natural evaluation in the sense that moral judgments of human action and character have the same “grammar” or “conceptual structure” as natural judgments of the goodness of plants and animals. We argue that Foot’s naturalist project can succeed, but not in the way she envisions, because her central thesis that moral evaluation is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  31
    The Beautiful is the Symbol of the Morally Good.Naomi Fisher - 2020 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 94:215-228.
    In the Critique of the Power of Judgment, Kant claims that “the beautiful is the symbol of the morally good.” In this article I offer an interpretation of this claim. According to Kant’s conception of a symbol, the form of judgment operative in judgments of beauty can also be applied to morality. This parallel application highlights that we are directed at an end which cannot be determined by theoretical cognition. I argue that beauty’s symbolism of morality depends upon (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  84
    What is a Person?: Rethinking Humanity, Social Life, and the Moral Good From the Person Up.Christian Smith - 2010 - University of Chicago Press.
    What is a person? This fundamental question is a perennial concern of philosophers and theologians. But, Christian Smith here argues, it also lies at the center of the social scientist’s quest to interpret and explain social life. In this ambitious book, Smith presents a new model for social theory that does justice to the best of our humanistic visions of people, life, and society. Finding much current thinking on personhood to be confusing or misleading, Smith finds inspiration in critical realism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  46.  48
    Autonomy: A Moral Good, Not a Moral Obsession.Daniel Callahan - 1984 - Hastings Center Report 14 (5):40-42.
  47.  18
    The Roots of Morality and the Nature of Moral Goodness.P. M. S. Hacker - 2020 - In The moral powers: a study of human nature. Hoboken, NJ, USA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 33–64.
    Von Wright argued that moral goodness is a derivative form of goodness. He proceeded to give an account of the moral goodness of an act, in terms of the good of man. Philosophical anthropology must render the phenomenon of morality intelligible. This chapter suggests that the roots of moral value lie in human sympathy, in maternal love, in intuitive recognition of the humanity of others, and in the nature of loving friendship. The sentiment of sympathy is virtually ubiquitous, but (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Have Elephant Seals Refuted Aristotle? Nature, Function, and Moral Goodness.Micah Lott - 2012 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 9 (3):353-375.
    An influential strand of neo-Aristotelianism, represented by writers such as Philippa Foot, holds that moral virtue is a form of natural goodness in human beings, analogous to deep roots in oak trees or keen vision in hawks. Critics, however, have argued that such a view cannot get off the ground, because the neo-Aristotelian account of natural normativity is untenable in light of a Darwinian account of living things. This criticism has been developed most fully by William Fitzpatrick in his book (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  49. On Privileging God's Moral Goodness.Thomas D. Senor - 2006 - Faith and Philosophy 23 (4):409-422.
    According to Eric Funkhouser, omnipotence and necessary moral perfection (what Funkhouser calls "impeccability") are not compatible. Funkhouser gives two arguments for this claim. In this paper, I argue that neither of Funkhouser's arguments is sound. The traditional theist can reasonably claim that, contra Funkhouser, (i) there is no possible being who possesses all of God's attributes sans impeccability, and (ii) the fact that there are things that God cannot do does not entail that God lacks omnipotence. Armed with (i) and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  50. Gratitude to God for Our Own Moral Goodness.Robert J. Hartman - 2022 - Faith and Philosophy 39 (2):189-204.
    Someone owes gratitude to God for something only if God benefits her and is morally responsible for doing so. These requirements concerning benefit and moral responsibility generate reasons to doubt that human beings owe gratitude to God for their own moral goodness. First, moral character must be generated by its possessor’s own free choices, and so God cannot benefit moral character in human beings. Second, owed gratitude requires being morally responsible for providing a benefit, which rules out owed (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 966