Results for 'Paul Jaskot'

926 found
Order:
  1.  23
    Art in Bourgeois Society.Paul B. Jaskot - 2000 - Historical Materialism 7 (1):281-294.
  2.  46
    Farewell to an Idea: Episodes from a History of Modernism.Paul Jaskot & Andrew Hemingway - 2000 - Historical Materialism 7 (1):257-280.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  29
    Building the Nazi Economy.Paul B. Jaskot - 2014 - Historical Materialism 22 (3-4):312-329.
    Adam Tooze’sWages of Destructionargues for the fundamental economic reasoning that brought Hitler and the Nazi elite to the conclusion that war and genocide were the twin means of achieving their ends. But what happens if we introduce culture into this equation, a term of clear importance to Hitler and to many of the individuals Tooze has identified as key to understanding the economic developments, not least of whom was Hitler’s favourite architect, Albert Speer? Culture is a field of activity of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  39
    Introduction: Spatial, Environmental, and Ecocritical Approaches to Holocaust Memory.Emily-Rose Baker, Michael Holden, Diane Otosaka, Sue Vice & Dominic Williams - 2023 - Environment, Space, Place 15 (2):1-13.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:IntroductionSpatial, Environmental, and Ecocritical Approaches to Holocaust MemoryEmily-Rose Baker (bio), Michael Holden (bio), Diane Otosaka (bio), Sue Vice (bio), and Dominic Williams (bio)The successful implementation of genocide during the Holocaust depended on the spatial organisation of mass murder. From the concentrated ghettos and camps delimited by walls and barbed wire to the open fields and camouflaged forests where victims were shot en masse, Anne Kelly Knowles et al. argue, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Twilight of the perfect model model.Paul Teller - 2001 - Erkenntnis 55 (3):393-415.
  6. Coincidence as overlap.L. A. Paul - 2006 - Noûs 40 (4):623–659.
    I discuss puzzles involving coinciding material objects (such as statues and their constitutive lumps of clay) and propose solutions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  7. What is Relativism?Paul Boghossian - 2006 - In Patrick Greenough & Michael Patrick Lynch (eds.), Truth and realism. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 13--37.
    Many philosophers, however, have been tempted to be relativists about specific domains of discourse, especially about those domains that have a normative character. Gilbert Harman, for example, has defended a relativistic view of morality, Richard Rorty a relativistic view of epistemic justification, and Crispin Wright a relativistic view of judgments of taste.¹ But what exactly is it to be a relativist about a given domain of discourse? The term ‘‘relativism’’ has, of course, been used in a bewildering variety of senses (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  8. (1 other version)Computational models.Paul Humphreys - 2002 - Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 2002 (3):S1-S11.
    A different way of thinking about how the sciences are organized is suggested by the use of cross‐disciplinary computational methods as the organizing unit of science, here called computational templates. The structure of computational models is articulated using the concepts of construction assumptions and correction sets. The existence of these features indicates that certain conventionalist views are incorrect, in particular it suggests that computational models come with an interpretation that cannot be removed as well as a prior justification. A form (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  9.  97
    Intellectual Virtues and Internet-Extended Knowledge.Paul Smart & Robert Clowes - 2021 - Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 10 (1):7-21.
    Arguments for the extended mind suggest the possibility of extended knowers, individuals whose epistemic standing is tied to the operation of cognitive circuits that extend beyond the bounds of skin and skull. When applied to the Internet, this idea yields the possibility of Internet-extended knowledge, a form of extended knowledge that derives from our interactions and engagements with the online environment. This, however, yields a tension: proponents of the extended mind have suggested that cognitive extension requires the automatic endorsement of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10. Epistemic possibility.Paul Teller - 1972 - Philosophia 2 (4):303-320.
  11. Experimental philosophy of science.Paul E. Griffiths & Karola Stotz - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 3 (3):507–521.
    Experimental philosophy of science gathers empirical data on how key scientific concepts are understood by particular scientific communities. In this paper we briefly describe two recent studies in experimental philosophy of biology, one investigating the concept of the gene, the other the concept of innateness. The use of experimental methods reveals facts about these concepts that would not be accessible using the traditional method of intuitions about possible cases. It also contributes to the study of conceptual change in science, which (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  12.  51
    The aesthetics of disappearance.Paul Virilio - 1980 - Los Angeles, CA: Semiotext. Edited by Philip Beitchman.
    Focusing on the logistics of perception, this title introduces the author's understanding of 'picnolepsy' - the epileptic state of consciousness produced by speed, or rather, the consciousness invented by the subject through its very absence: the gaps, glitches, and speed bumps lacing through and defining it.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  13. A computationally-discovered simplification of the ontological argument.Paul Oppenheimer & Edward N. Zalta - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (2):333 - 349.
    The authors investigated the ontological argument computationally. The premises and conclusion of the argument are represented in the syntax understood by the automated reasoning engine PROVER9. Using the logic of definite descriptions, the authors developed a valid representation of the argument that required three non-logical premises. PROVER9, however, discovered a simpler valid argument for God's existence from a single non-logical premise. Reducing the argument to one non-logical premise brings the investigation of the soundness of the argument into better focus. Also, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  14.  71
    (1 other version)Function and concatenation.Paul Pietroski - 2002 - In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter (eds.), Logical Form and Language. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 91--117.
    Paul M. Pietroski, University of Maryland For any sentence of a natural language, we can ask the following questions: what is its meaning; what is its syntactic structure; and how is its meaning related to its syntactic structure? Attending to these questions, as they apply to sentences that provide evidence for Davidsonian event analyses, suggests that we reconsider some traditional views about how the syntax of a natural sentence is related to its meaning.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  15.  74
    Maximum principles in analytical economics.Paul A. Samuelson - 1975 - Synthese 31 (2):323 - 344.
  16.  13
    The World Wide Web.Paul Smart - 2018 - In David Coady & James Chase (eds.), Routledge Handbook of Applied Epistemology. New York: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group. pp. 15–27.
  17. Is blindsight like normal, near-threshold vision?Paul Azzopardi & Alan Cowey - 1997 - Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Usa 94 (25):14190-14194.
  18. Ethology, sociobiology and evolutionary psychology.Paul Edmund Griffiths - 2008 - In Sahorta Sarkar & Anya Plutynski (eds.), Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Blackwell. pp. 393-414.
    In the years leading up to the Second World War the ethologists Konrad Lorenz and Nikolaas Tinbergen, created the tradition of rigorous, Darwinian research on animal behavior that developed into modern behavioral ecology. At first glance, research on specifically human behavior seems to exhibit greater discontinuity that research on animal behavior in general. The 'human ethology' of the 1960s appears to have been replaced in the early 1970s by a new approach called ‘sociobiology’. Sociobiology in its turn appears to have (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  19. How we dapple the world.Paul Teller - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (4):425-447.
    This essay endorses the conclusion of Sklar’s “Dappled Theories in a Uniform World” that he announces in his abstract, that notwithstanding recent attacks foundational theories are universal in their scope. But Sklar’s rejection of a “pluralist ontology” is questioned. It is concluded that so called “foundational” and “phenomenological” theories are on a much more equal footing as sources of knowledge than Sklar would allow, that “giving an ontology” generally involves dealing in idealizations, and that a transfigured “ficitonalism” provides an (in (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  20.  50
    A most peculiar paradox.Paul Meehl - 1950 - Philosophical Studies 1 (3):47 - 48.
  21.  33
    The model of the legislator: Political theory, policy, and realist utopianism.Paul Raekstad - 2021 - Contemporary Political Theory 20 (4):727-748.
    Is realism in political theory compatible with utopianism? This article shows that it is, by reconstructing a highly restrictive realist approach to political theory for guiding legislation and public policy, drawn from the work of Adam Smith, and showing how it can accommodate Piketty’s utopian proposal for a global tax on capital. This shows not only that realism and utopianism are compatible; but how realist and utopian political theory can be carried out in concrete cases. This moves debates to more (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22. Truth conditions of tensed sentence types.L. A. Paul - 1997 - Synthese 111 (1):53-72.
    Quentin Smith has argued that the new tenseless theory of time is faced with insurmountable problems and should be abandoned in favour of the tensed theory of time. Smith;s main argument attacks the fundamental premise of the tenseless theory: that tenseless truth conditions for tokens of tensed sentences adequately capture the meaning of tensed sentences. His position is that tenseless truth conditions cannot explain the logical relations between tensed sentences, thus the tensed theory must be accepted. Against Smith, this paper (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  23.  96
    Quantum mechanics and the nature of continuous physical quantities.Paul Teller - 1979 - Journal of Philosophy 76 (7):345-361.
  24. Expressive perception as projective imagining.Paul Noordhof - 2008 - Mind and Language 23 (3):329–358.
    I argue that our experience of expressive properties (such as the joyfulness or sadness of a piece of music) essentially involves the sensuous imagination (through simulation) of an emotion-guided process which would result in the production of the properties which constitute the realisation of the expressive properties experienced. I compare this proposal with arousal theories, Wollheim’s Freudian account, and other more closely related theories appealing to imagination such as Kendall Walton’s. I explain why the proposal is most naturally developed in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  25. The nature of natural norms: Why selected functions are systemic capacity functions.Paul Sheldon Davies - 2000 - Noûs 34 (1):85–107.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  26.  74
    Frames, knowledge, and inference.Paul R. Thagard - 1984 - Synthese 61 (2):233 - 259.
  27.  93
    Some aspects of language and construction in the madhyamaka.Paul M. Williams - 1980 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 8 (1):1-45.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  28. (1 other version)The task of defining a work of art.Paul Ziff - 1953 - Philosophical Review 62 (1):58-78.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  29. Moral worth.Paul Benson - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 51 (3):365 - 382.
  30. Realism and truth.Paul Horwich - 1996 - Philosophical Perspectives 10:187 - 197.
  31. The justification of a priori intuitions.Paul Tidman - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (1):161-171.
    There are propositions that upon understanding them it seems that one can “just see” that they are necessary or impossible. A commonly discussed example is the claim that it is not possible for an object to be red and green all over at the same time. My purpose in this paper is to account for how it is that such beliefs are justified. I begin by criticizing a suggestion defended lately by Laurence BonJour and others. BonJour argues that because these (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  32. Towards a 'Machiavellian' theory of emotional appraisal.Paul E. Griffiths - 2004 - In Dylan Evans & Pierre Cruse (eds.), Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality. Oxford University Press.
    The aim of appraisal theory in the psychology of emotion is to identify the features of the emotion-eliciting situation that lead to the production of one emotion rather than another2. A model of emotional appraisal takes the form of a set of dimensions against which potentially emotion-eliciting situations are assessed. The dimensions of the emotion hyperspace might include, for example, whether the eliciting situation fulfills or frustrates the subject’s goals or whether an actor in the eliciting situation has violated a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  33.  42
    Architecture et Narrativité.Paul Ricoeur - 2016 - Études Ricoeuriennes / Ricoeur Studies 7 (2):20-30.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34. Psychological essentialism in selecting the 14th Dalai Lama.Paul Bloom - 2008 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12 (7):243.
  35. Prolegomenon to a proper interpretation of quantum field theory.Paul Teller - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (4):594-618.
    This paper digests technical commonplaces of quantum field theory to present an informal interpretation of the theory by emphasizing its connections with the harmonic oscillator. The resulting "harmonic oscillator interpretation" enables newcomers to the subject to get some intuitive feel for the theory. The interpretation clarifies how the theory relates to observation and to quantum mechanical problems connected with observation. Finally the interpretation moves some way towards helping us see what the theory comes to physically. The paper also argues that, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  36. Beyond the Baldwin effect: James Mark Baldwin's 'social heredity', epigenetic inheritance, and niche construction.Paul E. Griffiths - 2003 - In Bruce H. Weber & David J. Depew (eds.), Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered. MIT Press. pp. 193--215.
    I argue that too much attention has been paid to the Baldwin effect. George Gaylord Simpson was probably right when he said that the effect is theoretically possible and may have actually occurred but that this has no major implications for evolutionary theory. The Baldwin effect is not even central to Baldwin's own account of social heredity and biology-culture co-evolution, an account that in important respects resembles the modern ideas of epigenetic inheritance and niche-construction.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37.  35
    Identity-Directed Norm Transformations and Moral Progress.Paul Morrow - 2020 - Journal of Value Inquiry 54 (3):493-509.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  59
    On the interpretation of madhyamaka thought.Paul Williams - 1991 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 19 (2):191-218.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  39.  13
    A world-championship-level Othello program.Paul S. Rosenbloom - 1982 - Artificial Intelligence 19 (3):279-320.
  40.  42
    The moral psychology of conflicts of interest: Insights from affective neuroscience.Paul Thagard - 2007 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 24 (4):367–380.
    abstract This paper is an investigation of the moral psychology of decisions that involve a conflict of interest. It draws on the burgeoning field of affective neuroscience, which is the study of the neurobiology of emotional systems in the brain. I show that a recent neurocomputational model of how the brain integrates cognitive and affective information in decision‐making can help to answer some important descriptive and normative questions about the moral psychology of conflicts of interest. These questions include: Why are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  41. (1 other version)Malcolm's conk and Danto's colors; or, four logical petitions concerning race, beauty, and aesthetics.Paul C. Taylor - 1999 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (1):16-20.
  42.  88
    Sincerity and the end of theodicy: Three remarks on Levinas and Kant.Paul Davies - 1998 - Research in Phenomenology 28 (1):126-151.
  43.  79
    Essential properties: Some problems and conjectures.Paul Teller - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (9):233-248.
  44. The concept of disease: Structure and change.Paul Thagard - 1996 - Communication and Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Journal 29 (3/4):445-478.
    By contrasting Hippocratic and nineteenth century theories of disease, this paper describes important conceptual changes that have taken place in the history of medicine. Disease concepts are presented as causal networks that represent the relations among the symptoms, causes, and treatment of a disease. The transition to the germ theory of disease produced dramatic conceptual changes as the result of a radically new view of disease causation. An analogy between disease and fermentation was important for two of the main developers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45.  34
    Fostering the trustworthiness of researchers: SPECS and the role of ethical reflexivity in novel neurotechnology research.Paul Tubig & Darcy McCusker - 2021 - Research Ethics 17 (2):143-161.
    The development of novel neurotechnologies, such as brain-computer interface (BCI) and deep-brain stimulation (DBS), are very promising in improving the welfare and life prospects many people. These include life-changing therapies for medical conditions and enhancements of cognitive, emotional, and moral capacities. Yet there are also numerous moral risks and uncertainties involved in developing novel neurotechnologies. For this reason, the progress of novel neurotechnology research requires that diverse publics place trust in researchers to develop neural interfaces in ways that are overall (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  33
    (1 other version)The Limitations of Physics as a Chemical Reducing Agent.Paul A. Bogaard - 1978 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1978:345 - 356.
  47.  25
    The genetic control of tissue polarity in Drosophila.Paul N. Adler - 1992 - Bioessays 14 (11):735-741.
    The cuticular surface of Drosophila is decorated by parallel arrays of polarized structures such as hairs and sensory bristles; for example, on the wing each cell produces a distally pointing hair. These patterns are termed [tissue polarity]. Several genes are known whose activity is essential for the development of normal tissue polarity. Mutations in these genes alter the orientation of the hair or bristle with respect to neighboring cells and the body as a whole. The phenotypes of mutations in these (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  37
    Experimental parapsychology as a rejected science.Paul D. Allison - 1979 - In Roy Wallis (ed.), On the margins of science: the social construction of rejected knowledge. Keele: University of Keele. pp. 271--291.
  49.  13
    Beyond all appearances.Paul Weiss - 1974 - Carbondale,: Southern Illinois University Press.
    An internationally renowned philoso­pher propounds a way to advance be­yond appearance to ultimate realities and a final ideal. “One of philosophy’s main functions is to arouse thought, to awaken and redirect. It asks others to think through, to assess, and at the same time to be flexible and steady. Author and reader must, despite the printed page, despite differences in age and experience, training and knowl­edge, philosophize together,” writes Paul Weiss in his brilliant new book. And this is exactly (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Evaluative Perception as Response Dependent Representation.Paul Noordhof - 2018 - In Anna Bergqvist & Robert Cowan (eds.), Evaluative Perception. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 80-108.
    One dimension of the controversy over whether evaluative properties are presented in perceptual content has general roots in the debate over whether perceptual content, in general, is rich or austere. I argue that we need to recognise a level of rich non-sensory perceptual content, drawing on experiences of chicken sexing and speech perception, to capture what our experience is like and our epistemic entitlements. In both cases (and many others), we are not conscious of the precise perceptual cues that are (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 926