Results for 'Stephen Lendman'

941 found
Order:
  1. Sowing the seeds of destruction.Stephen Lendman - 2008 - Nexus 15 (2):13-20.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  14
    Reconciling the Teachings of Cyril of Alexandria and Thomas Aquinas on the Universal Headship of Christ.Daniel Lendman - 2022 - Heythrop Journal 63 (4):731-741.
    The Heythrop Journal, Volume 63, Issue 4, Page 731-741, July 2022.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  32
    The Weak Will as Cause in Acts of the Incontinent: A Response to Bonnie Kent.Daniel Lendman - 2018 - New Blackfriars 101 (1095):505-518.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  85
    The Heart and Its Attitudes.Stephen Darwall - 2024 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This book is a systematic treatment-perhaps the first-of “attitudes of the heart”-remorse (versus guilt), love, trust, gratitude, personal anger (versus righteous anger), jealousy, and others-and their role in mediating personal relationship, attachment, and connection. This is obviously interesting in its own right, but it also shows how heartfelt attitudes mirror more extensively studied “reactive attitudes” of guilt, resentment, and blame (“attitudes of the will”). Whereas the latter mediate moral relations of mutual respect and accountability, attitudes of the heart are the (...)
  5.  38
    Index.Stephen Yablo - 2014 - In Aboutness. Oxford: Princeton University Press. pp. 219-222.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  6. (1 other version)Dispositions.Stephen Mumford - 1994 - Cogito 8 (2):141-146.
    Mumford puts forward a new theory of dispositions, showing how central their role in metaphysics and philosophy of science is. Much of our understanding of the physical and psychological world is expressed in terms of dispositional properties--from the spin of a sub-atomic particle to the solubility of sugar. Mumford discusses what it means to say that something has a property of this kind and how dispositions can possibly be real things in the world.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   168 citations  
  7. (3 other versions)Meaning.Stephen Schiffer - 1972 - Philosophy 51 (195):102-109.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  8. The Emperor's New Metaphysics of Powers.Stephen Barker - 2013 - Mind 122 (487):605-653.
    This paper argues that the new metaphysics of powers, also known as dispositional essentialism or causal structuralism, is an illusory metaphysics. I argue for this in the following way. I begin by distinguishing three fundamental ways of seeing how facts of physical modality — facts about physical necessitation and possibility, causation, disposition, and chance — are grounded in the world. The first way, call it the first degree, is that the actual world or all worlds, in their entirety, are the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  9. Theories of references and truth.Stephen Leeds - 1978 - Erkenntnis 13 (1):111 - 129.
    Much recent work in the philosophy of language has been concerned with the project of constructing a theory of reference and truth for natural languages. I shall discuss certain assumptions which have been tacitly in the background of most of this work; what I hope my rather sceptical discussion will show is that the project of giving a theory of reference and truth is much more problematic - and more closely tied to questions of general philosophical interest - than is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  10. Renewing meaning: a speech-act theoretic approach.Stephen J. Barker - 2004 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    This book develops an alternative approach to sentence- and word-meaning, which I dub the speech-act theoretic approach, or STA. Instead of employing the syntactic and semantic forms of modern logic–principally, quantification theory–to construct semantic theories, STA employs speech-act structures. The structures it employs are those postulated by a novel theory of speech-acts. STA develops a compositional semantics in which surface grammar is integrated with semantic interpretation in a way not allowed by standard quantification-based theories. It provides a pragmatic theory of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  11. Dispositional Modality.Stephen Mumford & Rani Lill Anjum - 2011 - In C. F. Gethmann, Lebenswelt und Wissenschaft, Deutsches Jahrbuch Philosophie 2. Meiner Verlag.
    There has been much discussion of powers or real dispositions in the past decade, but there remains an issue that has been inadequately treated. This concerns the precise modal value that comes with dispositionality. We contend in this paper that dispositionality involves a non-alethic, sui generis, irreducible modality. Dispositions only tend towards their manifestations; they do not necessitate them. Tendency is, of course, a dispositional term itself, so this last statement offers little by way of illumination. But given our thesis (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  12.  44
    Methodologies and communities in comparative philosophy.Stephen C. Angle - 2024 - Metaphilosophy 55 (3):423-439.
    There is considerable disagreement and even confusion over what forms of border‐crossing philosophizing are most appropriate to our times. Are comparative, cross‐cultural, intercultural, blended, and fusion philosophy all the same thing? Some critics find what they call “comparative philosophy” to be moribund or problematically colonialist; others assert that projects like “fusion philosophy” are intellectually irresponsible and colonialist in their own way. Can we nonetheless identify a distinctive project of comparative philosophy and say why it is important? Based on a broad (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13. Consequences of a Functional Account of Information.Stephen Francis Mann - 2018 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 11 (3):1-19.
    This paper aims to establish several interconnected points. First, a particular interpretation of the mathematical definition of information, known as the causal interpretation, is supported largely by misunderstandings of the engineering context from which it was taken. A better interpretation, which makes the definition and quantification of information relative to the function of its user, is outlined. The first half of the paper is given over to introducing communication theory and its competing interpretations. The second half explores three consequences of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  14. Number and natural language.Stephen Laurence & Eric Margolis - 2005 - In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich, The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents. New York, US: Oxford University Press on Demand. pp. 1--216.
    One of the most important abilities we have as humans is the ability to think about number. In this chapter, we examine the question of whether there is an essential connection between language and number. We provide a careful examination of two prominent theories according to which concepts of the positive integers are dependent on language. The first of these claims that language creates the positive integers on the basis of an innate capacity to represent real numbers. The second claims (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  15.  71
    The Epistemic Goals of the Humanities.Stephen R. Grimm - 2024 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 98 (1):209-232.
    The sciences aim to get at the truth about the nature of the world. Do the humanities have a similar goal—namely, to get at the truth about things like novels, paintings, and historical events? I consider a few different ways in which the humanities aim at the truth about their objects, in the process giving rise to epistemic goods such as knowledge and understanding. Two works in the humanities are used as test cases: the historian Tyler Stovall’sParis Noir (1996) and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. (1 other version)Naming, Necessity, and Natural Kinds.Stephen P. Schwartz - 1978 - Philosophy 53 (203):126-127.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  17. Should uterus transplants be publicly funded?Stephen Wilkinson & Nicola Jane Williams - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (9):559-565.
    Since 2000, 11 human uterine transplantation procedures (UTx) have been performed across Europe and Asia. Five of these have, to date, resulted in pregnancy and four live births have now been recorded. The most significant obstacles to the availability of UTx are presently scientific and technical, relating to the safety and efficacy of the procedure itself. However, if and when such obstacles are overcome, the most likely barriers to its availability will be social and financial in nature, relating in particular (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  18. If-Thenism.Stephen Yablo - 2017 - Australasian Philosophical Review 1 (2):115-132.
    ABSTRACTAn undemanding claim ϕ sometimes implies, or seems to, a more demanding one ψ. Some have posited, to explain this, a confusion between ϕ and ϕ*, an analogue of ϕ that does not imply ψ. If-thenists take ϕ* to be If ψ then ϕ. Incrementalism is the form of if-thenism that construes If ψ then ϕ as the surplus content of ϕ over ψ. The paper argues that it is the only form of if-thenism that stands a chance of being (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  19. Truth, correspondence, and success.Stephen Leeds - 1995 - Philosophical Studies 79 (1):1 - 36.
  20. Descartes.Stephen Gaukroger - 1993 - In George Henry Radcliffe Parkinson, The Renaissance and seventeenth-century rationalism. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  21. Morality and practical reason: A Kantian approach.Stephen Darwall - 2006 - In David Copp, The Oxford handbook of ethical theory. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 282--320.
    A central theme of Kant’s approach to moral philosophy is that moral obligations are categorical, by which he means that they provide supremely authoritative reasons for acting independently of an agent’s ends or interests. Kant argues that this is a reflection of our distinctive freedom or autonomy, as he calls it, as moral agents. A less, well- appreciated aspect of the Kantian picture of morality and respect for the dignity of each individual person is the idea of reciprocal accountability, that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  22. Aristotle's theology.Stephen Menn - 2012 - In Christopher Shields, The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 422.
    When Aristotle speaks of theologikê, he means not the study of a single God, but the study of gods and divine things in general. He never uses the phrase “the unmoved mover” to pick out just one being, and that phrase would not express the essence of the beings it applies to. To see what sort of religious interest there might be in such a being, and how the words “god” and “divine” enter into Aristotle's philosophy, it is best to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  23. Kant's Quasi‐Transcendental Argument for a Necessary and Universal Evil Propensity in Human Nature.Stephen R. Palmquist - 2008 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 46 (2):261-297.
    In Part One of Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason, Kant repeatedly refers to a “proof” that human nature has a necessary and universal “evil propensity,” but he provides only obscure hints at its location. Interpreters have failed to identify such an argument in Part One. After examining relevant passages, summarizing recent attempts to reconstruct the argument, and explaining why these do not meet Kant's stated needs, I argue that the elusive proof must have a transcendental form (called quasi‐transcendental (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  24. How literacy in its fundamental sense is central to scientific literacy.Stephen P. Norris & Linda M. Phillips - 2003 - Science Education 87 (2):224-240.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  25.  40
    A Justice-Based Defense of a Litmus Test.Stephen S. Hanson - 2024 - American Journal of Bioethics 24 (4):58-60.
    Jecker, et al., argue against rejecting a location for an international bioethics conference based on a “litmus test” for several reasons, ranging from the practical to the theoretical. However, th...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. World Hypotheses: A Study in Evidence.Stephen C. Pepper - 1945 - Philosophy 20 (75):86-89.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  27.  56
    Reflections on Church's thesis.Stephen C. Kleene - 1987 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (4):490-498.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  28.  82
    Ontology of art.Stephen Davies - 2003 - In Jerrold Levinson, The Oxford handbook of aesthetics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 155--180.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  29.  63
    5. The Truth and Something But the Truth.Stephen Yablo - manuscript
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30. Cornea, Carnap, and Current Closure Befuddlement.Stephen J. Wykstra - 2007 - Faith and Philosophy 24 (1):87-98.
    Graham and Maitzen think my CORNEA principle is in trouble because it entails “intolerable violations of closure under known entailment.” I argue that the trouble arises from current befuddlement about closure itself, and that a distinction drawn by Rudolph Carnap, suitably extended, shows how closure, when properly understood, works in tandem with CORNEA. CORNEA does not obey Closure because it shouldn’t: it applies to “dynamic” epistemic operators, whereas closure principles hold only for “static” ones. What the authors see as an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  31. Aristotle's Account of Anger: Narcissism and Illusions of Self‐Sufficiency.Stephen Leighton - 2002 - Ratio 15 (1):23–45.
    This paper considers an allegation by M. Stocker and E. Hegeman that Aristotle’s account of anger yields a narcissistic passion bedevilled by illusions of self-sufficiency. The paper argues on behalf of Aristotle’s valuing of anger within a virtuous and flourishing life, showing that and why Aristotle’s account is neither narcissistic nor involves illusions of self-sufficiency. In so arguing a deeper appreciation of Aristotle’s understanding of a self-sufficient life is reached, as are some interesting contrasts between Aristotle's understanding of anger, its (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  32.  74
    Spinoza, Emanation, and Formal Causation.Stephen Zylstra - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (4):603-625.
    Some recent scholars have argued that Spinoza's conception of causation should be understood in terms of the Aristotelian notion of a formal cause. I argue that while they are right to identify causation in Spinoza as a relation of entailment from an essence, they are mistaken about its philosophical pedigree. I examine three suggested lines of influence: (a) the late scholastic conception of emanation; (b) early modern philosophy of mathematics; and (c) Descartes's notion of the causa sui. In each case, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Ways of Watching Sport.Stephen Mumford - 2013 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 73:3-15.
    There are many ways that we can watch sport but not all of them are philosophically interesting. One can watch it enthusiastically, casually, fanatically or drunkenly. One might watch only because one has bet on the outcome. Some watch a friend or relative compete and have a narrow focus on one individual's performance. A coach or scout on the lookout for new talent may have completely different interests to a supporter of a team. But what of the ways of watching (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34.  10
    Fraud and misconduct in medical research.Stephen Lock & Frank O. Wells (eds.) - 1993 - London: BMJ.
    A review of fraud in medical research in Britain, Europe, the USA and Australia. It includes a history of known cases of fraud since 1974 and discusses ways for detecting and dealing with fraud that have been devised by government agencies, pharmaceutical companies, academic institutions and scientific publications (especially medical journals).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  35. Constructive empiricism.Stephen Leeds - 1994 - Synthese 101 (2):187 - 221.
    Constructive Empiricism, the view introduced in The Scientific Image, is a view of science, an answer to the question “what is science?” Arthur Fine’s and Paul Teller’s contributions to this symposium challenge especially two key ideas required to formu- late that view, namely the observable/unobservable and accept- ance/belief distinctions. I wish to thank them not only for their insightful critique but also for the support they include. For they illuminate and counter some misunderstandings of Constructive Empiricism along the way. That (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  36. On Myles Burnyeat’s Map of Metaphysics Zeta.Stephen Menn - 2011 - Ancient Philosophy 31 (1):161-202.
  37.  57
    Charles Darwin's use of theology in the Origin of Species.Stephen Dilley - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Science 45 (1):29-56.
    This essay examines Darwin's positiva use of theology in the first edition of the Origin of Species in three steps. First, the essay analyses the Origin's theological language about God's accessibility, honesty, methods of creating, relationship to natural laws and lack of responsibility for natural suffering; the essay contends that Darwin utilized positiva theology in order to help justify descent with modification and to attack special creation. Second, the essay offers critical analysis of this theology, drawing in part on Darwin's (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  38.  17
    The effect of thematic content on cognitive strategies in the four-card selection task.Stephen A. Yachanin & Ryan D. Tweney - 1982 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 19 (2):87-90.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  39.  32
    Corrigendum.Stephen Turner, Deborah Tollefsen, Paul Roth, Mark Risjord, Kareem Khalifa & David Henderson - 2023 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 53 (2):163-163.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  38
    In Defense of Capitalism: Modern Slavery Would Be Much Worse Without It.Sarah Lilian Stephen & Punit Arora - 2023 - Business and Society 62 (3):475-481.
    Some scholars blame capitalism for the prevalence of modern slavery. However, data reveal that it is wrong to blame capitalism for a problem that long preceded it and would likely be much worse without it. We explain why this is the case.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  52
    The aesthetics of organization.Stephen Linstead & Heather Joy Höpfl (eds.) - 2000 - Thousand Oaks, Calif.: SAGE Publications.
    Organizational aesthetics, both as a body of theory and a method of inquiry, is a rapidly expanding area of the organizational sciences. The Aesthetics of Organization accessibly draws key contributions delineating the emerging parameters of the field. It explains the significance of concepts devised by postmodern thinkers, through which emerge meaning and order in organizations. Methodological problems associated with investigations of the aesthetic are also highlighted so the reader can identify and understand the importance of recent ideas on vision, perspective (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  42.  49
    A Nonstandard Counterpart of WWKL.Stephen G. Simpson & Keita Yokoyama - 2011 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 52 (3):229-243.
    In this paper, we introduce a system of nonstandard second-order arithmetic $\mathsf{ns}$-$\mathsf{WWKL_0}$ which consists of $\mathsf{ns}$-$\mathsf{BASIC}$ plus Loeb measure property. Then we show that $\mathsf{ns}$-$\mathsf{WWKL_0}$ is a conservative extension of $\mathsf{WWKL_0}$ and we do Reverse Mathematics for this system.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  43. Why there might not be an evolutionary explanation for psychological altruism.Stephen Stich - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 56:3-6.
  44. Knowledge of Need.Stephen K. McLeod - 2011 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19 (2):211-230.
    Some of the duties of individuals and organisations involve responsiveness to need. This requires knowledge of need, so the epistemology of need is relevant to practice. The prevailing contention among philosophers who have broached the topic is that one can know one’s own needs (as one can know some kinds of desires) by feeling them. The article argues against this view. The main positive claims made in the article are as follows. Knowledge of need, in both first‐person and second‐person cases, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45.  25
    The Harraseeket Conference – Revisiting systems for ethics oversight of research with human participants.Stephen J. Rosenfeld, George Shaler & Ross Hickey - 2023 - Research Ethics 19 (3):231-249.
    The current system of ethical oversight in the United States is based on Institutional Review Board (IRB) review. The system was established in response to well-known and egregious mistreatment of subjects in both biomedical and social and behavioral research. In the decades since the research regulations were enacted, reaction to the burden of IRB oversight has led the system to focus on compliance and limit its active oversight disproportionately to studies that could present the risk of physical harm. At the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  39
    Mathematical practitioners and instruments in Elizabethan England.Stephen Johnston - 1991 - Annals of Science 48 (4):319-344.
    Summary A new culture of mathematics was developed in sixteenth-century England, the culture of ?the mathematicalls?. Its representatives were the self-styled mathematical practitioners who presented their art as a practical and worldly activity. The careers of two practitioners, Thomas Bedwell and Thomas Hood, are used as case studies to examine the establishment of this culture of the mathematicalls. Both practitioners self-consciously used mathematical instruments as key resources in negotiating their own roles. Bedwell defined his role in contrast to mechanicians and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  47.  16
    Κίνησις ακίνητος: A Study of Spiritual Motion in the Philosophy of Proclus.Stephen Gersh - 1973 - Brill.
  48. 透視悖論--說謊者的幽默指南.Stephen R. Palmquist - 2013 - In 拒絕再 Hea ── 真理與意義的追尋. Hong Kong: 次文化 [Subculture Limited]. pp. 37-44.
    A Chinese translation of an essay entitled "Paradox in Perspective: A Liar’s Guide to Humor".
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49. Apparatuses of Animality: Foucault Goes to a Slaughterhouse.Stephen Thierman - 2010 - Foucault Studies 9:89-110.
    The work of Michel Foucault is not often considered in animal ethics discussions, but I believe that many of his insights can be fruitfully extended into this area of philosophical inquiry. In this paper, I present the slaughterhouse as a technology of power that is complicit in the domination and objectification of both human and nonhuman animal subjects. I begin by arguing that Foucault’s notion of an “apparatus” is a useful methodological tool for thinking about the constellation of spaces and (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50. “First, Do No Harm”?Stephen John & Joseph Wu - 2022 - Social Theory and Practice 48 (3):525-551.
    Screening for asymptomatic disease is a routine aspect of contemporary public health practice. However, it is also controversial, because it leads to overdiagnosis and overtreatment, with many arguing that programmes are “ineffective,” i.e., the “costs” outweigh the “benefits.” This paper explores a more fundamental objection to screening programmes: that, even if they are effective, they are ethically impermissible because they breach the principle of non-maleficence. In so doing, it suggests a new approach to the ethics of risk, justifying a concern (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 941