Results for 'Theory of computation'

966 found
Order:
  1. A theory of computational implementation.Michael Rescorla - 2014 - Synthese 191 (6):1277-1307.
    I articulate and defend a new theory of what it is for a physical system to implement an abstract computational model. According to my descriptivist theory, a physical system implements a computational model just in case the model accurately describes the system. Specifically, the system must reliably transit between computational states in accord with mechanical instructions encoded by the model. I contrast my theory with an influential approach to computational implementation espoused by Chalmers, Putnam, and others. I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  2. Scientific Theories of Computational Systems in Model Checking.Nicola Angius & Guglielmo Tamburrini - 2011 - Minds and Machines 21 (2):323-336.
    Model checking, a prominent formal method used to predict and explain the behaviour of software and hardware systems, is examined on the basis of reflective work in the philosophy of science concerning the ontology of scientific theories and model-based reasoning. The empirical theories of computational systems that model checking techniques enable one to build are identified, in the light of the semantic conception of scientific theories, with families of models that are interconnected by simulation relations. And the mappings between these (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  3. Against Structuralist Theories of Computational Implementation.Michael Rescorla - 2013 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 64 (4):681-707.
    Under what conditions does a physical system implement or realize a computation? Structuralism about computational implementation, espoused by Chalmers and others, holds that a physical system realizes a computation just in case the system instantiates a pattern of causal organization isomorphic to the computation’s formal structure. I argue against structuralism through counter-examples drawn from computer science. On my opposing view, computational implementation sometimes requires instantiating semantic properties that outstrip any relevant pattern of causal organization. In developing my (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  4.  37
    A New Approach to Computing Using Informons and Holons: Towards a Theory of Computing Science.F. David de la Peña, Juan A. Lara, David Lizcano, María Aurora Martínez & Juan Pazos - 2020 - Foundations of Science 25 (4):1173-1201.
    The state of computing science and, particularly, software engineering and knowledge engineering is generally considered immature. The best starting point for achieving a mature engineering discipline is a solid scientific theory, and the primary reason behind the immaturity in these fields is precisely that computing science still has no such agreed upon underlying theory. As theories in other fields of science do, this paper formally establishes the fundamental elements and postulates making up a first attempt at a (...) in this field, considering the features and peculiarities of computing science. The fundamental elements of this approach are informons and holons, and it is a general and comprehensive theory of software engineering and knowledge engineering that related disciplines (e.g., information systems) can particularise and/or extend to take benefit from it (Lakatos’ concepts of core theory and protective belt theories). (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  84
    (1 other version)Towards a general theory of computability.Richard Montague - 1960 - Synthese 12 (4):429 - 438.
  6.  44
    A Pragmatic Theory of Computational Artefacts.Alessandro G. Buda & Giuseppe Primiero - 2024 - Minds and Machines 34 (1):139-170.
    Some computational phenomena rely essentially on pragmatic considerations, and seem to undermine the independence of the specification from the implementation. These include software development, deviant uses, esoteric languages and recent data-driven applications. To account for them, the interaction between pragmatics, epistemology and ontology in computational artefacts seems essential, indicating the need to recover the role of the language metaphor. We propose a User Levels (ULs) structure as a pragmatic complement to the Levels of Abstraction (LoAs)-based structure defining the ontology and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. The Theory of Computability Developed in Terms of Satisfaction.James Cain - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (4):515-532.
    The notion of computability is developed through the study of the behavior of a set of languages interpreted over the natural numbers which contain their own fully defined satisfaction predicate and whose only other vocabulary is limited to "0", individual variables, the successor function, the identity relation and operators for disjunction, conjunction, and existential quantification.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  35
    The theory of ceers computes true arithmetic.Uri Andrews, Noah Schweber & Andrea Sorbi - 2020 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 171 (8):102811.
    We show that the theory of the partial order of computably enumerable equivalence relations (ceers) under computable reduction is 1-equivalent to true arithmetic. We show the same result for the structure comprised of the dark ceers and the structure comprised of the light ceers. We also show the same for the structure of L-degrees in the dark, light, or complete structure. In each case, we show that there is an interpretable copy of (N, +, \times) .
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  29
    Saturation and stability in the theory of computation over the reals.Olivier Chapuis & Pascal Koiran - 1999 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 99 (1-3):1-49.
    This paper was motivated by the following two questions which arise in the theory of complexity for computation over ordered rings in the now famous computational model introduced by Blum, Shub and Smale: 1. is the answer to the question P = ?NP the same in every real-closed field?2. if P ≠ NP for , does there exist a problem of which is NP but neither P nor NP-complete ?Some unclassical complexity classes arise naturally in the study of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  53
    Theory of quantum computation and philosophy of mathematics. Part I.Krzysztof Wójtowicz - 2009 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 18 (3-4):313-332.
    The aim of this paper is to present some basic notions of the theory of quantum computing and to compare them with the basic notions of the classical theory of computation. I am convinced, that the results of quantum computation theory (QCT) are not only interesting in themselves, but also should be taken into account in discussions concerning the nature of mathematical knowledge. The philosophical discussion will however be postponed to another paper. QCT seems not (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  26
    Theory of Computation.George Tourlakis - 2012 - Hoboken, N.J.: Wiley.
    In addition, this book contains tools that, in principle, can search a set of algorithms to see whether a problem is solvable, or more specifically, if it can be solved by an algorithm whose computations are efficient.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Function Logic and the Theory of Computability.Jaakko Hintikka - 2013 - APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers 13 (1):10-19.
    An important link between model theory and proof theory is to construe a deductive disproof of S as an attempted construction of a countermodel to it. In the function logic outlined here, this idea is implemented in such a way that different kinds of individuals can be introduced into the countermodel in any order whatsoever. This imposes connections between the length of the branches of the tree that a disproof is and their number. If there are already n (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  49
    Model theory of deduction: a unified computational approach.Bruno G. Bara, Monica Bucciarelli & Vincenzo Lombardo - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (6):839-901.
    One of the most debated questions in psychology and cognitive science is the nature and the functioning of the mental processes involved in deductive reasoning. However, all existing theories refer to a specific deductive domain, like syllogistic, propositional or relational reasoning.Our goal is to unify the main types of deductive reasoning into a single set of basic procedures. In particular, we bring together the microtheories developed from a mental models perspective in a single theory, for which we provide a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  14.  65
    Can Computational Goals Inform Theories of Vision?Barton L. Anderson - 2015 - Topics in Cognitive Science 7 (2):274-286.
    One of the most lasting contributions of Marr's posthumous book is his articulation of the different “levels of analysis” that are needed to understand vision. Although a variety of work has examined how these different levels are related, there is comparatively little examination of the assumptions on which his proposed levels rest, or the plausibility of the approach Marr articulated given those assumptions. Marr placed particular significance on computational level theory, which specifies the “goal” of a computation, its (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15.  53
    Elements of the Theory of Computation.Harry R. Lewis & Christos H. Papadimitriou - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (3):989-990.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  16.  46
    Turing's Analysis of Computation and Theories of Cognitive Architecture.A. J. Wells - 1998 - Cognitive Science 22 (3):269-294.
    Turing's analysis of computation is a fundamental part of the background of cognitive science. In this paper it is argued that a re‐interpretation of Turing's work is required to underpin theorizing about cognitive architecture. It is claimed that the symbol systems view of the mind, which is the conventional way of understanding how Turing's work impacts on cognitive science, is deeply flawed. There is an alternative interpretation that is more faithful to Turing's original insights, avoids the criticisms made of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  17.  23
    Fodor's New Theory of Computation and Information.J. Andrew Brook & Robert J. Stainton - unknown
  18.  43
    Handbook of computability theory.Edward R. Griffor (ed.) - 1999 - New York: Elsevier.
    The chapters of this volume all have their own level of presentation. The topics have been chosen based on the active research interest associated with them. Since the interest in some topics is older than that in others, some presentations contain fundamental definitions and basic results while others relate very little of the elementary theory behind them and aim directly toward an exposition of advanced results. Presentations of the latter sort are in some cases restricted to a short survey (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  31
    Toward a computational theory of social groups: A finite set of cognitive primitives for representing any and all social groups in the context of conflict.David Pietraszewski - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45:e97.
    We don't yet have adequate theories of what the human mind is representing when it represents a social group. Worse still, many people think we do. This mistaken belief is a consequence of the state of play: Until now, researchers have relied on their own intuitions to link up the conceptsocial groupon the one hand and the results of particular studies or models on the other. While necessary, this reliance on intuition has been purchased at a considerable cost. When looked (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20. An analysis of the criteria for evaluating adequate theories of computation.Nir Fresco - 2008 - Minds and Machines 18 (3):379-401.
    This paper deals with the question: What are the criteria that an adequate theory of computation has to meet? 1. Smith's answer: it has to meet the empirical criterion (i.e. doing justice to computational practice), the conceptual criterion (i.e. explaining all the underlying concepts) and the cognitive criterion (i.e. providing solid grounds for computationalism). 2. Piccinini's answer: it has to meet the objectivity criterion (i.e. identifying computation as a matter of fact), the explanation criterion (i.e. explaining the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21.  16
    Computational theories of cognition.Herbert A. Simon - 1996 - In William T. O'Donohue & Richard F. Kitchener (eds.), The philosophy of psychology. Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage Publications. pp. 160--173.
  22.  6
    Theories of cortical computation.William A. Phillips - 1997 - In Michael D. Rugg (ed.), Cognitive Neuroscience. MIT Press. pp. 11--46.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  56
    Zohar Manna. Mathematical theory of computation. McGraw-Hill Book Company, New York etc. 1974, x + 448 pp. [REVIEW]Andrzej Blikle - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (1):122-124.
  24. Theory of recursive functions and effective computability.Hartley Rogers - 1987 - Cambridge: MIT Press.
  25.  15
    The Universal Theory of the Hyperfinite II $_1$ Factor is Not Computable.Isaac Goldbring & Bradd Hart - 2024 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 30 (2):181-198.
    We show that the universal theory of the hyperfinite II $_1$ factor is not computable. The proof uses the recent result that MIP*=RE. Combined with an earlier observation of the authors, this yields a proof that the Connes Embedding Problem has a negative solution that avoids the equivalences with Kirchberg’s QWEP Conjecture and Tsirelson’s Problem.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Computational theories of object recognition.Shimon Edelman - 1997 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 1 (8):296-304.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  27. The Computational Theory of Mind.John-Michael Kuczynski - 2014 - Madison, WI, USA: Philosophypedia.
    The widespread belief that the mind is a computer embodies a failure to distinguish between computers and information-processing systems. Minds are information-processing systems, but they are not computers.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Theory of incursive synchronization of delayed systems and anticipatory computing of chaos.Daniel M. Dubois - 2002 - In Robert Trappl (ed.), Cybernetics and Systems. Austrian Society for Cybernetics Studies. pp. 1--17.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  44
    The Abstraction/Representation Account of Computation and Subjective Experience.Jochen Szangolies - 2020 - Minds and Machines 30 (2):259-299.
    I examine the abstraction/representation theory of computation put forward by Horsman et al., connecting it to the broader notion of modeling, and in particular, model-based explanation, as considered by Rosen. I argue that the ‘representational entities’ it depends on cannot themselves be computational, and that, in particular, their representational capacities cannot be realized by computational means, and must remain explanatorily opaque to them. I then propose that representation might be realized by subjective experience (qualia), through being the bearer (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  17
    Handbook of computational social science: theory, case studies and ethics.Uwe Engel, Anabel Quan-Haase, Sunny Xun Liu & Lars Lyberg (eds.) - 2022 - New York, NY: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.
    The Handbook of Computational Social Science is a comprehensive reference source for scholars across multiple disciplines. It outlines key debates in the field, showcasing novel statistical modeling and machine learning methods, and draws from specific case studies to demonstrate the opportunities and challenges in CSS approaches. The Handbook is divided into two volumes written by outstanding, internationally renowned scholars in the field. This first volume focuses on the scope of computational social science, ethics, and case studies. It covers a range (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  57
    Nicholas Pippenger, Theories of computability. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, New York, and Oakleigh, Victoria, 1997, ix + 251 pp. [REVIEW]Hans Huttel - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):913-914.
  32.  2
    Uniformly reflexive structures: towards an abstract theory of computability.Eric Gerhardt Wagner - 1963 - [New York: [S.N.].
  33. Changing the theory of theory change: Towards a computational approach.Neil Tennant - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (3):865-897.
    The Theory of theory change has contraction and revision as its central notions. Of these, contraction is the more fundamental. The best-known theory, due to Alchourrón, Gärdenfors, and Makinson, is based on a few central postulates. The most fundamental of these is the principle of recovery: if one contracts a theory with respect to a sentence, and then adds that sentence back again, one recovers the whole theory. Recovery is demonstrably false. This paper shows why, (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  34.  14
    Towards a computational network theory of social groups.Daniel Redhead, Riana Minocher & Dominik Deffner - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45.
    Network theory is necessary for the realization of cognitive representations and resulting empirical observations of social groups. We propose that the triadic primitives denoting individual roles are multilayer, with positive and negative relations feeding into cost–benefit calculations. Through this, we advance a computational theory that generalizes to different scales and to contexts where conflict is not present.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. P≠NP, By accepting to make a shift in the Theory (Time as a fuzzy concept) The Structure of a Theory (TC*, Theory of Computation based on Fuzzy time).Farzad Didehvar - manuscript
    In a series of articles we try to show the need of a novel Theory for Theory of Computation based on considering time as a Fuzzy concept. Time is a central concept In Physics. First we were forced to consider some changes and modifications in the Theories of Physics. In the second step and throughout this article we show the positive Impact of this modification on Theory of Computation and Complexity Theory to rebuild it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  54
    The Role of Executive Function and Theory of Mind in Pragmatic Computations.Sarah Fairchild & Anna Papafragou - 2021 - Cognitive Science 45 (2):e12938.
    In sentences such as “Some dogs are mammals,” the literal semantic meaning (“Some and possibly all dogs are mammals”) conflicts with the pragmatic meaning (“Not all dogs are mammals,” known as a scalar implicature). Prior work has shown that adults vary widely in the extent to which they adopt the semantic or pragmatic meaning of such utterances, yet the underlying reason for this variation is unknown. Drawing on theoretical models of scalar implicature derivation, we explore the hypothesis that the cognitive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37. Is Classical Mathematics Appropriate for Theory of Computation?Farzad Didehvar - manuscript
    Throughout this paper, we are trying to show how and why our Mathematical frame-work seems inappropriate to solve problems in Theory of Computation. More exactly, the concept of turning back in time in paradoxes causes inconsistency in modeling of the concept of Time in some semantic situations. As we see in the first chapter, by introducing a version of “Unexpected Hanging Paradox”,first we attempt to open a new explanation for some paradoxes. In the second step, by applying this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Seeing and summing: Implications of computational theories of vision.Austen Clark - 1984 - Cognition and Brain Theory 7 (1):1-23.
    Marr's computational theory of stereopsis is shown to imply that human vision employs a system of representation which has all the properties of a number system. Claims for an internal number system and for neural computation should be taken literally. I show how these ideas withstand various skeptical attacks, and analyze the requirements for describing neural operations as computations. Neural encoding of numerals is shown to be distinct from our ability to measure visual physiology. The constructs in Marr's (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Computational Theories of Conscious Experience: Between a Rock and a Hard Place.Gary Bartlett - 2012 - Erkenntnis 76 (2):195-209.
    Very plausibly, nothing can be a genuine computing system unless it meets an input-sensitivity requirement. Otherwise all sorts of objects, such as rocks or pails of water, can count as performing computations, even such as might suffice for mentality—thus threatening computationalism about the mind with panpsychism. Maudlin in J Philos 86:407–432, ( 1989 ) and Bishop ( 2002a , b ) have argued, however, that such a requirement creates difficulties for computationalism about conscious experience, putting it in conflict with the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  15
    A Basis for a Mathematical Theory of Computation, Preliminary Report.John Mccarthy, P. Braffort & D. Hirschberg - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1):117-117.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  70
    Computational complexity of logical theories of one successor and another unary function.Pascal Michel - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (2):123-148.
    The first-order logical theory Th $({\mathbb{N}},x + 1,F(x))$ is proved to be complete for the class ATIME-ALT $(2^{O(n)},O(n))$ when $F(x) = 2^{x}$ , and the same result holds for $F(x) = c^{x}, x^{c} (c \in {\mathbb{N}}, c \ge 2)$ , and F(x) = tower of x powers of two. The difficult part is the upper bound, which is obtained by using a bounded Ehrenfeucht–Fraïssé game.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Implications of computer science theory for the simulation hypothesis.David Wolpert - manuscript
    The simulation hypothesis has recently excited renewed interest, especially in the physics and philosophy communities. However, the hypothesis specifically concerns {computers} that simulate physical universes, which means that to properly investigate it we need to couple computer science theory with physics. Here I do this by exploiting the physical Church-Turing thesis. This allows me to introduce a preliminary investigation of some of the computer science theoretic aspects of the simulation hypothesis. In particular, building on Kleene's second recursion theorem, I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  50
    Finite axiomatizability for equational theories of computable groupoids.Peter Perkins - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (3):1018-1022.
  44. The first computational theory of mind and brain: A close look at McCulloch and Pitts' Logical Calculus of Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity.Gualtiero Piccinini - 2004 - Synthese 141 (2):175-215.
    Despite its significance in neuroscience and computation, McCulloch and Pitts's celebrated 1943 paper has received little historical and philosophical attention. In 1943 there already existed a lively community of biophysicists doing mathematical work on neural networks. What was novel in McCulloch and Pitts's paper was their use of logic and computation to understand neural, and thus mental, activity. McCulloch and Pitts's contributions included (i) a formalism whose refinement and generalization led to the notion of finite automata (an important (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  45.  46
    Theories of reasoning and the computational explanation of everyday inference.Mike Oaksford & Nick Chater - 1995 - Thinking and Reasoning 1 (2):121 – 152.
    Following Marr (1982), any computational account of cognition must satisfy constraints at three explanatory levels: computational, algorithmic, and implementational. This paper focuses on the first two levels and argues that current theories of reasoning cannot provide explanations of everyday defeasible reasoning, at either level. At the algorithmic level, current theories are not computationally tractable: they do not “scale-up” to everyday defeasible inference. In addition, at the computational level, they cannot specify why people behave as they do both on laboratory reasoning (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  46.  29
    A Simple Computational Theory of General Collective Intelligence.Peter M. Krafft - 2019 - Topics in Cognitive Science 11 (2):374-392.
    What are the conditions under which groups of agents will perform well across multiple tasks? The author establishes a set of “alignment conditions” that enforce identity of beliefs and desires across agents. These conditions are necessary and sufficient for ensuring that a multiagent system behaves as if controlled by a rational centralized controller. Several widely observed social phenomena can be understood as facilitating the alignment conditions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  48
    Quantum gravity computers: On the theory of computation with indefinite causal structure.Lucien Hardy - 2009 - In Wayne C. Myrvold & Joy Christian (eds.), Quantum Reality, Relativistic Causality, and Closing the Epistemic Circle. Springer. pp. 379--401.
  48.  24
    (1 other version)Machtey Michael and Young Paul. An introduction to the general theory of algorithms. The computer science library, Theory of computation series. North-Holland, New York, Oxford, and Shannon, 1978, vii + 264 pp. [REVIEW]Nancy Lynch - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (4):877-878.
  49.  43
    The myth of computational level theory and the vacuity of rational analysis.Barton L. Anderson - 2011 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (4):189-190.
    I extend Jones & Love's (J&L's) critique of Bayesian models and evaluate the conceptual foundations on which they are built. I argue that: (1) the part of Bayesian models is scientifically trivial; (2) theory is a fiction that arises from an inappropriate programming metaphor; and (3) the real scientific problems lie outside Bayesian theorizing.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  39
    Emotion and the computational theory of mind.Craig DeLancey - 1997 - In S. O'Nuillain, Paul McKevitt & E. MacAogain (eds.), Two Sciences of Mind. John Benjamins.
    The case for computationalism about the mind is in doubt when we acknowledge that there are mental phenomena that require, for a proper accounting, that we get below the level of symbol processing. Such phenomena show us that a computational theory of mind cannot be complete. Chief among these phenomena is emotion.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 966