Results for 'independence property'

967 found
Order:
  1. Independence Properties Vis-À-Vis Several Utility Representations.A. A. J. Marley & R. Duncan Luce - 2005 - Theory and Decision 58 (1):77-143.
    A detailed theoretical analysis is presented of what five utility representations – subjective expected utility (SEU), rank-dependent (cumulative or Choquet) utility (RDU), gains decomposition utility (GDU), rank weighted utility (RWU), and a configural-weight model (TAX) that we show to be equivalent to RWU – say about a series of independence properties, many of which were suggested by M. H. Birnbaum and his coauthors. The goal is to clarify what implications to draw about the descriptive aspects of the representations from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2.  64
    Independence property and hyperbolic groups.Eric Jaligot, Alexey Muranov & Azadeh Neman - 2008 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14 (1):88 - 98.
    In continuation of [JOH04, OH07], we prove that existentially closed CSA-groups have the independence property. This is done by showing that there exist words having the independence property relative to the class of torsion-free hyperbolic groups.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  44
    The independence property in generalized dense pairs of structures.Alexander Berenstein, Alf Dolich & Alf Onshuus - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):391 - 404.
    We provide a general theorem implying that for a (strongly) dependent theory T the theory of sufficiently well-behaved pairs of models of T is again (strongly) dependent. We apply the theorem to the case of lovely pairs of thorn-rank one theories as well as to a setting of dense pairs of first-order topological theories.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  4. Theories with the Independence Property, Studia Logica 2010 95:379-405.Mlj van de Vel - 2010 - Studia Logica 95 (3):379-405.
    A first-order theory T has the Independence Property provided deduction of a statement of type (quantifiers) (P -> (P1 or P2 or .. or Pn)) in T implies that (quantifiers) (P -> Pi) can be deduced in T for some i, 1 <= i <= n). Variants of this property have been noticed for some time in logic programming and in linear programming. We show that a first-order theory has the Independence Property for the class (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  44
    On a classification of theories without the independence property.Viktor Verbovskiy - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (1-2):119-124.
    A theory is stable up to Δ if any Δ-type over a model has a few extensions up to complete types. We prove that a theory has no the independence property iff it is stable up to some Δ, where each equation image has no the independence property.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  67
    Vapnik–Chervonenkis Density in Some Theories without the Independence Property, II.Matthias Aschenbrenner, Alf Dolich, Deirdre Haskell, Dugald Macpherson & Sergei Starchenko - 2013 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (3-4):311-363.
    We study the Vapnik–Chervonenkis density of definable families in certain stable first-order theories. In particular, we obtain uniform bounds on the VC density of definable families in finite $\mathrm {U}$-rank theories without the finite cover property, and we characterize those abelian groups for which there exist uniform bounds on the VC density of definable families.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  7.  27
    Karp complexity and classes with the independence property.M. C. Laskowski & S. Shelah - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 120 (1-3):263-283.
    A class K of structures is controlled if for all cardinals λ, the relation of L∞,λ-equivalence partitions K into a set of equivalence classes . We prove that no pseudo-elementary class with the independence property is controlled. By contrast, there is a pseudo-elementary class with the strict order property that is controlled 69–88).
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8.  16
    Definable nilpotent and soluble envelopes in groups without the independence property.Ricardo de Aldama - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (3):201-205.
  9.  67
    Partially ordered sets and the independence property.James H. Schmerl - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (2):396-401.
    No theory of a partially ordered set of finite width has the independence property, generalizing Poizat's corresponding result for linearly ordered sets. In fact, a question of Poizat concerning linearly ordered sets is answered by showing, moreover, that no theory of a partially ordered set of finite width has the multi-order property. It then follows that a distributive lattice is not finite-dimensional $\operatorname{iff}$ its theory has the independence property $\operatorname{iff}$ its theory has the multi-order (...). (shrink)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  65
    Automorphism–invariant measures on ℵ0-categorical structures without the independence property.Douglas E. Ensley - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2):640 - 652.
    We address the classification of the possible finitely-additive probability measures on the Boolean algebra of definable subsets of M which are invariant under the natural action of $\operatorname{Aut}(M)$ . This pursuit requires a generalization of Shelah's forking formulas [8] to "essentially measure zero" sets and an application of Myer's "rank diagram" [5] of the Boolean algebra under consideration. The classification is completed for a large class of ℵ 0 -categorical structures without the independence property including those which are (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  48
    An introduction to theories without the independence property.Hans Adler - unknown
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  12.  17
    A logical notion of conditional independence: properties and applications.Adnan Darwiche - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 97 (1-2):45-82.
  13. Independence and Property in Kant's Rechtslehre.David James - 2016 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (2):302-322.
    I argue that the freedom which is to coexist with the freedom of choice of others in accordance with a universal law mentioned in Kant's Rechtslehre is not itself freedom of choice. Rather, it is the independence which is a condition of being able to exercise genuine free choice by not having to act in accordance with the choices of others. Kant's distinction between active and passive citizenship appears, however, to undermine this idea of independence, because the possession (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  1
    Overcoming Revolutions: Property, Independence, and Relation in Mary Wollstonecraft.Carlotta Cossutta - 2025 - Rivista Italiana di Filosofia Politica 7:103-121.
    The article examines Mary Wollstonecraft’s interpretation of revolutionary movements, particularly through her analysis of the French Revolution. Wollstonecraft examines the oppression of women as a form of slavery, but also uses it as a lens through which to denounce socio-economic injustices and propose radical change. Her critique of mercantile society and property contrasts with her rethinking of the domestic sphere as an alternative political space. The article shows how these reflections lead to a rethinking of femininity and the construction (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  56
    Properties and Consequences of Thorn-Independence.Alf Onshuus - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (1):1 - 21.
    We develop a new notion of independence (þ-independence, read "thorn"-independence) that arises from a family of ranks suggested by Scanlon (þ-ranks). We prove that in a large class of theories (including simple theories and o-minimal theories) this notion has many of the properties needed for an adequate geometric structure. We prove that þ-independence agrees with the usual independence notions in stable, supersimple and o-minimal theories. Furthermore, we give some evidence that the equivalence between forking and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  16. Mohammed Abdellaoui/Editorial Statement 1–2 Mohammed Abdellaoui and Peter P. Wakker/The likelihood Method for Decision Under Uncertainty 3–76 AAJ Marley and R. Duncan Luce/Independence Properties Vis--Vis Several Utility Representations 77–143. [REVIEW]Davide P. Cervone, William V. Gehrlein, William S. Zwicker, Which Scoring Rule Maximizes Condorcet, Marcello Basili, Alain Chateauneuf & Fulvio Fontini - 2005 - Theory and Decision 58:409-410.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Aesthetic Properties, Mind-Independence, and Companions in Guilt.Daan Evers - 2019 - In Christopher Cowie & Rach Cosker-Rowland, Companions in Guilt: Arguments in Metaethics. Routledge.
    I first show how one might argue for a mind-independent conception of beauty and artistic merit. I then discuss whether this makes aesthetic judgements suitable to undermine skeptical worries about the existence of mind-independent moral value and categorical reasons.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  73
    Properties of independently axiomatizable bimodal logics.Marcus Kracht & Frank Wolter - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1469-1485.
  19.  28
    Independence and the finite submodel property.Vera Koponen - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 158 (1-2):58-79.
    We study a class of 0-categorical simple structures such that every M in has uncomplicated forking behavior and such that definable relations in M which do not cause forking are independent in a sense that is made precise; we call structures in independent. The SU-rank of such M may be n for any natural number n>0. The most well-known unstable member of is the random graph, which has SU-rank one. The main result is that for every strongly independent structure M (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  70
    On the Properties of Conditional Independence.Wolfgang Spohn - 1994 - In Paul Humphreys, Patrick Suppes, Scientific Philosopher Vol. 1: Probability and Probabilistic Causality. Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    As the paper explains, it is crucial to epistemology in general and to the theory of causation in particular to investigate the properties of conditional independence as completely as possible. The paper summarizes the most important results concerning conditional independence with respect to two important representations of epistemic states, namely (strictly positive) probability measures and natural conditional (or disbelief or ranking) functions. It finally adds some new observations.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  21.  27
    The notion of independence in categories of algebraic structures, part I: Basic properties.Gabriel Srour - 1988 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 38 (2):185-213.
    We define a formula φ in a first-order language L , to be an equation in a category of L -structures K if for any H in K , and set p = {φ;i ϵI, a i ϵ H} there is a finite set I 0 ⊂ I such that for any f : H → F in K , ▪. We say that an elementary first-order theory T which has the amalgamation property over substructures is equational if every (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  22. The material conditions of non-domination: Property, independence, and the means of production.Alexander Bryan - 2023 - European Journal of Political Theory 22 (3):425-444.
    While it is a point of agreement in contemporary republican political theory that property ownership is closely connected to freedom as non-domination, surprisingly little work has been done to elucidate the nature of this connection or the constraints on property regimes that might be required as a result. In this paper, I provide a systematic model of the boundaries within which republican property systems must sit and explore some of the wider implications that thinking of property (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  36
    Aronszajn trees and the independence of the transfer property.William Mitchell - 1972 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 5 (1):21.
  24. Hume’s Argument for the Ontological Independence of Simple Properties.Jani Hakkarainen - 2011 - Metaphysica 12 (2):197-212.
    In this paper, I will reconstruct Hume's argument for the ontological (in the sense of rigid existential) independence of simple properties in A Treatise of Human Nature , Book 1 (1739). According to my reconstruction, the main premises of the argument are the real distinctness of every perception of a simple property, Hume's Separability Principle and his Conceivability Principle. In my view, Hume grounds the real distinctness of every perception of a simple property in his atomistic theory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  30
    Model-theoretic properties of ultrafilters built by independent families of functions.M. Malliaris & S. Shelah - 2014 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 79 (1):103-134.
  26.  19
    Separate but equal: Property rights and the legal independence of Buddhist nuns and monks in early north India.Gregory Schopen - 2008 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 128 (4):625-640.
  27. Background Independence: Lessons for Further Decades of Dispute.Trevor Teitel - 2019 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 65:41-54.
    Background independence begins life as an informal property that a physical theory might have, often glossed as 'doesn't posit a fixed spacetime background'. Interest in trying to offer a precise account of background independence has been sparked by the pronouncements of several theorists working on quantum gravity that background independence embodies in some sense an essential discovery of the General Theory of Relativity, and a feature we should strive to carry forward to future physical theories. This (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  80
    Privileging properties.Mary Kate McGowan - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 105 (1):1-23.
    The idea that the world is human construction is fairly familiar and generally disparaged. One version of this claim is partially defendedhere. This subjectivist thesis concerns a debate about the objectivityof rightness of categorization. A problem about the discriminatoryrole of properties is both presented and motivated. The subjectivistthesis is articulated and defended against two powerful objections.Finally, this thesis is shown to be conceptually independent ofboth verificationism and empirical idealism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  26
    The Property Right to Voice.Avital Margalit & Shai Stern - 2024 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 37 (1):167-197.
    Should property owners have a unique right to express their opinion just because they own property? While current law recognizes owners’ rights to express their voices in certain instances, it does not provide comprehensive and coherent answers to this question. This article provides an analytical framework for recognizing the owners’ right to voice as an independent property entitlement within the owners’ property bundle of rights and delineates its boundaries. Yet even when the owners’ voice is (...)-dependent, there is a difference between voice that facilitates the realization of another property entitlement (such as the right to exclude, use, or trade) and voice that is constitutive to ownership in and of itself. Only the latter instances justify recognition of the owners’ right to a voice as an independent property entitlement. By examining different branches of both tangible and intellectual property law, such as inheritance law, eminent domain, homeowners’ association law, zoning law, and copyright law, this article demonstrates the usefulness of the proposed analytical framework in explaining certain parts of the current law and suggests modifications of other parts. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Independence for full conditional measures, graphoids and bayesian networks.Teddy Seidenfeld - unknown
    This paper examines definitions of independence for events and variables in the context of full conditional measures; that is, when conditional probability is a primitive notion and conditioning is allowed on null events. Several independence concepts are evaluated with respect to graphoid properties; we show that properties of weak union, contraction and intersection may fail when null events are present. We propose a concept of “full” independence, characterize the form of a full conditional measure under full (...), and suggest how to build a theory of Bayesian networks that accommodates null events. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  20
    Topological properties of definable sets in ordered Abelian groups of burden 2.Alfred Dolich & John Goodrick - 2023 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 69 (2):147-164.
    We obtain some new results on the topology of unary definable sets in expansions of densely ordered Abelian groups of burden 2. In the special case in which the structure has dp‐rank 2, we show that the existence of an infinite definable discrete set precludes the definability of a set which is dense and codense in an interval, or of a set which is topologically like the Cantor middle‐third set (Theorem 2.9). If it has burden 2 and both an infinite (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  21
    Property‐Owning Democracy.Ben Jackson - 2012-02-17 - In Martin O'Neill & Thad Williamson, Property‐Owning Democracy. Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 33–52.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Property‐Owning Democracy Before Socialism: The Rise of Commercial Republicanism Property‐Owning Democracy at the Socialist High Tide (i): Progressive Conservative Origins Property‐Owning Democracy at the Socialist High Tide (ii): Liberals and Labour Revisionists Property‐Owning Democracy at the Socialist High Tide (iii): James Meade Property‐Owning Democracy After Socialism? Rawlsian and Neoliberal Lineages References.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33. Properties: Qualities, Powers, or Both?Rögnvaldur Ingthorsson - 2013 - Dialectica 67 (1):55-80.
    Powers are popularly assumed to be distinct from, and dependent upon, inert qualities, mainly because it is believed that qualities have their nature independently of other properties while powers have their nature in virtue of a relation to distinct manifestation property. George Molnar and Alexander Bird, on the other hand, characterize powers as intrinsic and relational. The difficulties of reconciling the characteristics of being intrinsic and at the same time essentially related are illustrated in this paper and it is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  34.  19
    Property, Sovereignty, and the Public Trust.Laura S. Underkuffler - 2017 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 18 (2):329-353.
    Generally, in liberal democratic systems, it is assumed that government should forbear from interference with existing individual property entitlements. It is assumed that existing individual property entitlements should be respected, with government reluctant to interfere. Despite the ubiquity of this assumption, the theoretical underpinning for it is not obvious. A sovereign must respond to the needs of all of the members of the greater community for which it speaks. In view of this obligation, irrevocably assigning property rights (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Property Rights, Social Norms and the Law: A Natural Law Theory of Property.Matthew Noah Smith - 2004 - Dissertation, The University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill
    The problem area of distributive justice includes at its core questions about what ought to be owned, how it can be owned and who ought to own it. A fundamental assumption behind recent attempts to address these questions is that the power to shape the property institutions of a society lies entirely in that society's laws. This view, I argue, is mistaken. In this dissertation I provide an account of how property institutions are related to other social practices (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  52
    Intrinsicality, Independence and Grounding.Sophie R. Allen - 2020 - Metaphysica 21 (1):71-97.
    This paper investigates the plausibility of Witmer, Butchard and Trogdon’s proposal to distinguish intrinsic properties from extrinsic ones in terms of independence from accompaniment and grounding. I argue that the proposed criterion is not adequate to determine intrinsicality, since according to it some intuitively extrinsic properties turn out to be intrinsic. I suggest and evaluate two responses: first, one could characterize a conception of independence which is specific to the individual instantiating the property; and second, one could (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Background-independence.Gordon Belot - 2011 - General Relativity and Gravitation 43:2865-2884.
    Intuitively, a classical field theory is background-in- dependent if the structure required to make sense of its equations is itself subject to dynamical evolution, rather than being imposed ab initio. The aim of this paper is to provide an explication of this intuitive notion. Background-independence is not a not formal property of theories: the question whether a theory is background-independent depends upon how the theory is interpreted. Under the approach proposed here, a theory is fully background-independent relative to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  38.  34
    Neostability-properties of Fraïssé limits of 2-nilpotent groups of exponent $${p > 2}$$ p > 2.Andreas Baudisch - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (3-4):397-403.
    Let L\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${L}$$\end{document} be the language of group theory with n additional new constant symbols c1,…,cn\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${c_1,\ldots,c_n}$$\end{document}. In L\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${L}$$\end{document} we consider the class K\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${{\mathbb{K}}}$$\end{document} of all finite groups G of exponent p>2\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${p > 2}$$\end{document}, where G′⊆⟨c1G,…,cnG⟩⊆Z\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Helmholtz on Perceptual Properties.R. Brian Tracz - 2018 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 6 (3).
    Hermann von Helmholtz’s work on perceptual science had a fundamental impact on Neo-Kantian movements in the late nineteenth century, and his influence continues to be felt in psychology and analytic philosophy of perception. As is widely acknowledged, Helmholtz denied that we can perceive mind-independent properties of external objects, a view I label Ignorance. Given his commitment to Ignorance, Helmholtz might seem to be committed to a subjectivism according to which we only perceive properties of our own representations. Against this, I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40. On the structural properties of the colours.Jonathan Cohen - 2003 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (1):78-95.
    Primary quality theories of color claim that colors are intrinsic, objective, mind-independent properties of external objects — that colors, like size and shape, are examples of the sort of properties moderns such as Boyle and Locke called primary qualities of body.1 Primary quality theories have long been seen as one of the main philosophical options for understanding the nature of color.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  41. Natural Kinds, Mind-independence, and Unification Principles.Tuomas E. Tahko - 2022 - Synthese 200 (2):1-23.
    There have been many attempts to determine what makes a natural kind real, chief among them is the criterion according to which natural kinds must be mind-independent. But it is difficult to specify this criterion: many supposed natural kinds have an element of mind-dependence. I will argue that the mind-independence criterion is nevertheless a good one, if correctly understood: the mind-independence criterion concerns the unification principles for natural kinds. Unification principles determine how natural kinds unify their properties, and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  42.  71
    Is Mind an Emergent Property?John-Michael Kuczynski - 1999 - Cogito 13 (2):117-119.
    It is often said that (M) "mind is an emergent property of matter." M is ambiguous, the reason being that, for all x and y, "x is an emergent property of y" has two distinct and mutually opposed meanings, namely: (i) x is a product of y (in the sense in which a chair is the product of the activity of a furniture-maker); and (ii) y is either identical or constitutive of x, but, relative to the information available (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  52
    Independent choices and the interpretation of IF logic.Theo M. V. Janssen - 2002 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 11 (3):367-387.
    In this paper it is argued that Hintikka's game theoreticalsemantics for Independence Friendly logic does not formalize theintuitions about independent choices; it rather is aformalization of imperfect information. Furthermore it is shownthat the logic has several remarkable properties (e.g.,renaming of bound variables is not allowed). An alternativesemantics is proposed which formalizes intuitions aboutindependence.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  44. Nonnaturalism, the Supervenience Challenge, Higher-Order Properties, and Trope Theory.Jussi Suikkanen - 2024 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 26 (3):601-632.
    Nonnaturalist realism is the view that normative properties are unique kind of stance-independent properties. It has been argued that such views fail to explain why two actions that are exactly alike otherwise must also have the same normative properties. Mark Schroeder and Knut Olav Skarsaune have recently suggested that nonnaturalist realists can respond to this supervenience challenge by taking the primary bearers of normative properties to be action kinds. This paper develops their response in two ways. First, it provides additional (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. Defending the medium-independence of computation.Zoe Drayson - forthcoming - Mind and Language.
    The computational properties of a system are generally thought to be independent in some sense from its physical properties, in virtue of the fact that computation is a formally characterized concept. Several philosophers have recently challenged the idea that such “medium-independence” is an essential feature of computation by arguing that some kinds of computation lack medium-independence. This paper explores and rejects three such arguments in an attempt to defend the essential medium-independence of computation.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  23
    Mind‐Independence.Matthew H. Kramer - 2009-04-10 - In Marcia Baron & Michael Slote, Moral Realism as a Moral Doctrine. Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 23–85.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Two Dichotomies The Existential Mind‐Independence of Moral Principles The Strong Observational Mind‐Independence of Moral Principles Appendix.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  32
    Thorn independence in the field of real numbers with a small multiplicative group.Alexander Berenstein, Clifton Ealy & Ayhan Günaydın - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 150 (1-3):1-18.
    We characterize þ-independence in a variety of structures, focusing on the field of real numbers expanded by predicate defining a dense multiplicative subgroup, G, satisfying the Mann property and whose pth powers are of finite index in G. We also show such structures are super-rosy and eliminate imaginaries up to codes for small sets.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  48. Natural Properties Do Not Support Essentialism in Counterpart Theory: A Reflection on Buras’s Proposal.Cristina Nencha - 2017 - Argumenta 2 (2):281-292.
    David Lewis may be regarded as an antiessentialist. The reason is that he is said to believe that individuals do not have essential properties independent of the ways they are represented. According to him, indeed, the properties that are determined to be essential to individuals are a matter of which similarity relations among individuals are salient, and salience, in turn, is a contextual matter also determined to some extent by the ways individuals are represented. Todd Buras argues that the acknowledgment (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  40
    Independence, dimension and continuity in non-forking frames.Adi Jarden & Alon Sitton - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (2):602-632.
    The notion $J$ is independent in $(M,M_0,N)$ was established by Shelah, for an AEC (abstract elementary class) which is stable in some cardinal $\lambda$ and has a non-forking relation, satisfying the good $\lambda$-frame axioms and some additional hypotheses. Shelah uses independence to define dimension. Here, we show the connection between the continuity property and dimension: if a non-forking satisfies natural conditions and the continuity property, then the dimension is well-behaved. As a corollary, we weaken the stability hypothesis (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50.  74
    Property dualism, phenomenal concepts, and the semantic premise.Stephen L. White - 2006 - In Torin Alter & Sven Walter, Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism. New York, US: Oxford University Press. pp. 210-248.
    This chapter defends the property dualism argument. The term “semantic premise” mentioned is used to refers to an assumption identified by Brian Loar that antiphysicalist arguments, such as the property dualism argument, tacitly assume that a statement of property identity that links conceptually independent concepts is true only if at least one concept picks out the property it refers to by connoting a contingent property of that property. It is argued that, the property (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
1 — 50 / 967