Results for ' Analytical functionalism ‐ Lewis's expedition into philosophy of mind'

960 found
Order:
  1.  9
    The Lewis Twist: Mind Over Matter.Elijah Millgram - 2009 - In Hard Truths. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 177–192.
    This chapter contains sections titled: 10.1 10.2 10.3 10.4 10.5.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  46
    Analytic Functionalism.Wolfgang Schwarz - 2015 - In Barry Loewer & Jonathan Schaffer, A companion to David Lewis. Chichester, West Sussex ;: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 504–518.
    David Lewis's position, often called analytic functionalism, was inspired by Ryle's analytic behaviorism, which took psychological predicates to express complex sets of behavioral dispositions. In this chapter, the author reviews some tenets of Lewis's philosophy of mind and begins with some comments on the methodology Lewis employed in his analysis of psychological terms, which has become standard in functionalist accounts across philosophy. Then, he discusses the difference between what are often called “realizer functionalism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  3.  18
    Whitehead, God and evil.Lewis S. Ford - 1981 - Philosophical Topics 12 (2):305-307.
  4. Pantheism vs. Theism: A Re-appraisal.Lewis S. Ford - 1997 - The Monist 80 (2):286 - 306.
    If pantheism is by definition the belief in impersonal deity, then there is little point in exploring any inter-connection with personalistic theism. Theism would exclude pantheism, and pantheism theism. To be sure, there are strong reasons why pantheism has insisted upon divine impersonality, and these need to be explored and assessed. That is our task in the first part of the paper, while the second part will introduce a way of considering the correlation of pantheism and theism in a new (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  65
    The Ramifications of Whitehead’s Theory of Experience.Lewis S. Ford - 1985 - The Monist 68 (4):439-450.
  6. Safeguarding Vulnerable Autonomy? Situational Vulnerability, The Inherent Jurisdiction and Insights from Feminist Philosophy.Jonathan Lewis - 2021 - Medical Law Review 29 (2):306-336.
    The High Court continues to exercise its inherent jurisdiction to make declarations about interventions into the lives of situationally vulnerable adults with mental capacity. In light of protective responses of health care providers and the courts to decision-making situations involving capacitous vulnerable adults, this paper has two aims. The first is diagnostic. The second is normative. The first aim is to identify the harms to a capacitous vulnerable adult’s autonomy that arise on the basis of the characterisation of situational (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  7. David Lewis.Brian Weatherson - 2009 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    David Lewis (1941–2001) was one of the most important philosophers of the 20th Century. He made significant contributions to philosophy of language, philosophy of mathematics, philosophy of science, decision theory, epistemology, meta-ethics and aesthetics. In most of these fields he is essential reading; in many of them he is among the most important figures of recent decades. And this list leaves out his two most significant contributions. -/- In philosophy of mind, Lewis developed and defended (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  8.  73
    Whitehead’s Categoreal Derivation of Divine Existence.Lewis S. Ford - 1970 - The Monist 54 (3):374-400.
    Gottfried Martin has recently reminded us of a useful distinction between two possible ways of doing metaphysics. We may proceed by framing a “theory of principles” or by proposing a “theory of being”. Aristotle explicitly formulates both possibilities as the task of metaphysics, formulating a theory of principles in his doctrine of the four types of causal explanation in the first book of the Metaphysics, while exploring the theory of being in a number of other passages, such as Book I, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Normative Functionalism in the Pittsburgh School.Patrick J. Reider - 2012 - Normative Functionalism and the Pittsburgh School.
    Sellars, Brandom, and McDowell (whom Maher aptly calls the “Pittsburgh School”) have tremendous influence on the current shape of the analytic tradition. Despite their differing views on philosophy of language, the philosophy of mind, philosophy of action, and epistemology, their shared application of ‘normative functionalism’ highlights important similarities in their approaches to the aforementioned disciplines. Normative functionalism interprets the ability to form judgments, possess concepts, rationally defend or be critical of judgments, and consequently act (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  26
    Analytical solipsism.William Lewis Todd - 1969 - The Hague,: Martinus Nijhoff.
    Philosophers usually have been anxious to avoid solipsism. A large number of good and great philosophers have tried to refute it. Of course, these philosophers have not always had the same target in mind and, like everything else, solipsism over the centuries has become increasingly elusive and subtle. In this book I undertake to state the position in its most modern and what I take to be its most plausible form. At some points in the history of philosophy (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11. Great Philosophical Arguments: An Introduction to Philosophy.Lewis Vaughn - 2011 - Oup Usa.
    The purpose of this text is to introduce students to great philosophy and great philosophers through an intense focus on argument. Like other topically organized introductory philosophy readers, this book is organized around the existence of God, knowledge and skepticism, mind and body, free will and determinism, ethics, and contemporary ethical debates, including abortion, euthanasia, and global hunger and poverty. 78 selections are grouped into six topical chapters-and the selections within those chapters are organized by argument. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  40
    Explorations and Emendations.Lewis S. Ford - 2014 - Process Studies 43 (1):75-96.
    These seven short essays record several recent explorations together with some corrections to earlier views which need revision in the light of further evidence. Topics considered include temporal atomism, a critique of nontemporal concresence, divine subjectivity and conceptual activity, a reexamination of physical purpose and negative prehension, and an alternate theory of life and mind.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  15
    Reasons, Causes, and Decisions.Lewis S. Ford - 1972 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 3 (2):51-62.
  14.  5
    Philosophical letters of David K. Lewis.David Kellogg Lewis - 2020 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Edited by Helen Beebee & A. R. J. Fisher.
    David Kellogg Lewis (1941-2001) was one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century. He made significant contributions to almost every area of analytic philosophy including metaphysics, philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of science, and set the agenda for various debates in these areas which carry on to this day. In several respects he remains a contemporary figure, yet enough time has now passed for historians of philosophy to begin to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  15
    The Active Future as Divine.Lewis S. Ford - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 36:75-79.
    Normally, activity is regarded as discernible, but according to relativity theory whatever is discernible lies in the past of the discernible. Only the present subjective immediacy is properly active. Subjectivity is properly understood as present becoming; objectivity as past being. I propose that we extend the domain of subjective immediacy to include the future as well as the present. This future universal activity is pluralized in the present in terms of the many actualities coming into being. Subjectivity is the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  86
    Reply to Mr. Ushenko’s Addendum.C. I. Lewis - 1933 - The Monist 43 (2):295-296.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  90
    The controversy between Schelling and Jacobi.Lewis S. Ford - 1965 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 3 (1):75-89.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Controversy Between Schelling and Jacobi LEWIS S. FORD SCHELLING, ALONGWITH FICHTE, has suffered the fate of being labelled one of tIegel's predecessors. Richard Kroner provides the classic expression of this viewpoint in his monumental study, Von Kant bis Hegel, which examines Schelling's thought primarily for its contribution to Hegel's final synthesis.I In English we have Josiah Royce's sympathetic and lively account of Schelling's early romantic exuberance, regarded as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  16
    On Genetic Successiveness.Lewis S. Ford - 1969 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 7 (4):423-427.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  36
    Prefatory Remarks.Lewis S. Ford - 1969 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 7 (4):327-328.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Wittgenstein, Tolstoy, and Shakespeare.Peter B. Lewis - 2005 - Philosophy and Literature 29 (2):241-255.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Wittgenstein, Tolstoy, and ShakespearePeter B. LewisNear the middle of the first of his 1938 Lectures on Aesthetics, Wittgenstein talks about what he calls "the tremendous things in art"(LC, I 23 8, italics in original).1 Apart from a brief indication of the way in which our response to the tremendous differs from the non-tremendous, he does not refer again in this way to the tremendous things in art, though he (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  82
    Memes, minds and evolution.David Holdcroft & Harry Lewis - 2000 - Philosophy 75 (2):161-182.
    It is common in the history of science to try to extend an idea first demonstrated in one domain into others. Sometimes the extension is literal, and sometimes it is frankly metaphorical. Sometimes, however, when an extension is claimed to be literal, it is far from easy to see that it is. If an extension does not make use of entities and mechanisms involved in the original domain, and introduces novel entities and mechanisms, then it is not unreasonable to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  94
    Causality in the social sciences.Lewis S. Feuer - 1954 - Journal of Philosophy 51 (23):681-695.
  23.  52
    Neville on the one and the many.Lewis S. Ford - 1972 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 10 (1):79-84.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Extended Cognition and Functionalism.Mark Sprevak - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy 106 (9):503-527.
    Andy Clark and David Chalmers claim that cognitive processes can and do extend outside the head.1 Call this the “hypothesis of extended cognition” (HEC). HEC has been strongly criticised by Fred Adams, Ken Aizawa and Robert Rupert.2 In this paper I argue for two claims. First, HEC is a harder target than Rupert, Adams and Aizawa have supposed. A widely-held view about the nature of the mind, functionalism—a view to which Rupert, Adams and Aizawa appear to subscribe— entails (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  25.  22
    David Lewis's Place in Analytic Philosophy.Scott Soames - 2015 - In Barry Loewer & Jonathan Schaffer, A companion to David Lewis. Chichester, West Sussex ;: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 80–98.
    A renegade positivist himself, Quine eschewed apriority, necessity, and analyticity, while (for a time) adopting a holistic version of verificationism. Despite similarities in their opposition to Quine, the differences between Lewis and Kripke were large ‐ especially in the semantics and metaphysics of modality. They also had different philosophical styles. Lewis's (1970b) was one of the cutting‐edge texts of its time ‐ along with work by Richard Montague, David Kaplan, and Robert Stalnaker. Together, they laid out a powerful framework (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  55
    Indeterminacy and economic development.Lewis S. Feuer - 1948 - Philosophy of Science 15 (3):225-241.
    It is widely believed that a study of the dynamics of capitalist development eventuates in a determinate law of economic evolution. If we trace the origins of this assumption, we find that it stems from the influence of the Hegelian dialectic upon economic theory. The metaphysic of determinism has thus obtruded its way into social science, and brought with it the corollary that economic analysis yields an insight into the necessary pattern of capitalist development.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  48
    Temporal and Nontemporal Becoming.Lewis S. Ford - 2009 - Process Studies 38 (1):5-42.
    Whitehead’s initial decision to treat actual occasions as unqualifiedly indivisible rendered the notion of succession in becoming highly problematic. Temporal phases would divide the indivisible. Thus Whitehead had originally recourse to genetic analysis. Many have interpreted this as nontemporal becoming, which is not clearly distinguished from the eternity of eternal objects. Besides, Whitehead reserved the term ‘nontemporal’ for the primordial nature. Finally Whitehead came to see that the indivisibility of occasions meant only that they could not be divided into (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Schopenhauer’s Laughter.Peter B. Lewis - 2005 - The Monist 88 (1):36-51.
    Schopenhauer is famous for his pessimism. Many people are surprised to learn that he articulated an important theory of laughter. While this theory has been scrutinised by aestheticians exploring the nature of humour, little has been written on the role of laughter in Schopenhauer’s pessimistic vision of the world. Admittedly, this latter topic is only a minor theme in Schopenhauer’s work: yet I contend that what he has to say illuminates the human predicament.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29. Aristotle on the homonymy of being.Frank A. Lewis - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (1):1–36.
    The topic of homonymy, especially the variety of homonymy that has gone under the title, “focal meaning,” is of fundamental importance to large portions of Aristotle’s work-not to mention its central place in the ongoing controversies between Aristotle and Plato. It is quite astonishing, therefore, that the topic should have gone so long without a book-length treatment. And it is all the more gratifying that the new book on homonymy by Christopher Shields should be so comprehensive, and of such uniformly (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  30.  70
    Speculative Philosophy[REVIEW]Lewis S. Ford - 1973 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 4 (2):131-135.
  31. David Lewis’s Place in Analytic Philosophy.Scott Soames - 2015 - In Barry Loewer & Jonathan Schaffer, A companion to David Lewis. Chichester, West Sussex ;: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 139-166.
    By the early 1970s, and continuing through 2001, David Lewis and Saul Kripke had taken over W.V.O. Quine’s leadership in metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of language, and philosophical logic in the English-speaking world. Quine, in turn, had inherited his position in the early 1950s from Rudolf Carnap, who had been the leading logical positivist -- first in Europe, and, after 1935, in America. A renegade positivist himself, Quine eschewed apriority, necessity, and analyticity, while (for a time) adopting a holistic version (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  20
    Stola, Joachim. Whitehead und Einstein. Wissenschaftsgeschichtliche Studien in Naturphilosophischer Absicht. [REVIEW]Lewis S. Ford - 1997 - Review of Metaphysics 50 (4):924-926.
    Stolz's primary concern is to interject Whitehead's thought into the contemporary scientific situation. He holds that Whitehead's development primarily proceeds out the scientific discussion of his time and only secondarily from the current philosophical discussion. He believes that the scientific community will be more open to this foundational reflection, so he has concentrated on the earlier material.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  32
    The So-called (and Actual!) Realism of the Tractatus.Gary W. Lewis - 1998 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 54:45-70.
    David Pears's contention that the Tractatus is to be understood as advancing a form of metaphysical realism is defended against McGuinness's view that Tractatus 1-2.063 is to be treated just as introducing a metaphysical myth that may be employed to bring into prominence salient features of propositions. Starting with a discussion of the involved difficulties, e.g., determining (1) whether Wittgenstein does in fact provide an argument for the existence of simple objects (2) what this object is and (3) what (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  32
    Psychoanalysis as Natural Philosophy.R. D. Hinshelwood - 2005 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 12 (4):325-329.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 12.4 (2005) 325-329 [Access article in PDF] Psychoanalysis as Natural Philosophy R. D. Hinshelwood Keywords evolution, psychopathology, ethics, unconscious phantasy Andreas De Block has offered us a most fascinating paper. We do not have to agree with all his points to be profoundly stimulated by them. His core proposition is that Freud pathologizes ordinary psychology and personalities, as well as the abnormal. There (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  35
    L'effet Whitehead. [REVIEW]Lewis S. Ford - 1996 - Review of Metaphysics 50 (1):189-191.
    German scholarship with respect to Whitehead is currently quite vigorous, more so than American, at least in philosophical circles. British scholarship, on the other hand, is nearly nonexistent. French scholarship is in between. Adventures of Ideas was translated into French in 1993, and the translation of Process and Reality should be out shortly. But there are few books or collections of essays about his philosophy. Now, however, Isabelle Stengers, co-author with Ilya Prigogine of Order Out of Chaos, has (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  42
    An Appraisal of Whiteheadian Nontheism 1.Lewis S. Ford - 1977 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 15 (1):27-35.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  78
    Perception and the Inhuman Gaze: Perspectives from Philosophy, Phenomenology and the Sciences.Fred Cummins, Anya Daly, James Jardine & Dermot Moran (eds.) - 2020 - New York, NY, USA; London, UK: Routledge.
    The diverse essays in this volume speak to the relevance of phenomenological and psychological questioning regarding perceptions of the human. This designation, human, can be used beyond the mere identification of a species to underwrite exclusion, denigration, dehumanization and demonization, and to set up a pervasive opposition in Othering all deemed inhuman, nonhuman, or posthuman. As alerted to by Merleau-Ponty, one crucial key for a deeper understanding of these issues is consideration of the nature and scope of perception. Perception defines (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  85
    The Social Theories of Talcott Parsons: A Critical Examination. [REVIEW]Lewis S. Feuer - 1962 - Journal of Philosophy 59 (7):182-193.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  39.  19
    Whitehead's Conception of Divine Spatiality.Lewis S. Ford - 1968 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 6 (1):1-13.
  40.  51
    God, guilt, and logic: The psychological basis of the ontological argument.Lewis S. Feuer - 1968 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 11 (1-4):257 – 281.
    The most eminent exponents of the ontological argument for the existence of God have been characterized as well by a common emotional ingredient — a concern with individual guilt. Anselm, Josiah Royce, Karl Barth, and Norman Malcolm in their respective ways have made the experience of guilt a central one in their metaphysical standpoints. The hypothesis is therefore advanced that the validity which such thinkers have found in the ontological argument is the expression of a frame of mind which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  47
    What is philosophy of history?Lewis S. Feuer - 1952 - Journal of Philosophy 49 (10):329-340.
  42.  28
    Heidegger and Whitehead: A Phenomenological Examination into the Intelligibility of Experience. By Ron L. Cooper. [REVIEW]Lewis S. Ford - 1994 - Modern Schoolman 72 (1):85-86.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  81
    Was Hume a proper functionalist?Kevin Meeker - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (1):120–136.
    Nicholas Wolterstorff has claimed that David Hume hinted at a proper functionalist account that anticipates the epistemology of Alvin Plantinga. In this paper, I shall argue that we should refrain from attributing a proper functionalist epistemology to Hume. I shall first raise doubts as to how one could fit a notion of proper functioning into Hume's descriptive project. Next, I shall argue that adopting a proper functionalist epistemology would undermine some of Hume's most famous claims about causal inferences.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. Writing philosophy: a student's guide to writing philosophy essays.Lewis Vaughn - 2006 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Writing Philosophy: A Student's Guide to Writing Philosophy Essays is a concise, self-guided manual that covers the basics of argumentative essay writing and encourages students to master fundamental skills quickly, with minimal instructor input. Opening with an introductory chapter on how to read philosophy, the book then moves into the basics of writing summaries and analyzing arguments. It provides step-by-step instructions for each phase of the writing process, from formulating a thesis, to creating an outline, to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  50
    The So-called (and Actual!) Realism of the Tractatus.Gary W. Lewis - 1998 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 54:45-70.
    David Pears's contention that the Tractatus is to be understood as advancing a form of metaphysical realism is defended against McGuinness's view that Tractatus 1-2.063 is to be treated just as introducing a metaphysical myth that may be employed to bring into prominence salient features of propositions. Starting with a discussion of the involved difficulties, e.g., determining (1) whether Wittgenstein does in fact provide an argument for the existence of simple objects (2) what this object is and (3) what (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  14
    The arc of truth: the thinking of Martin Luther King Jr.Lewis V. Baldwin - 2022 - Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press. Edited by Beverly Lanzetta.
    Martin Luther King Jr. said and wrote as much or more about the meaning, nature, and power of truth as any other prominent figure in the 1950s and '60s. King was not only vastly influential as an advocate for and defender of truth; he also did more than anyone in his time to organize truth into a movement for the liberation, uplift, and empowerment of humanity, efforts that ultimately resulted in the loss of his life. Drawing on King's published (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Depression Memoirs in the Circuits of Culture: Sexism, Sanism, Neoliberalism, and Narrative Identity.Bradley Lewis - 2017 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 24 (4):303-306.
    Ginger Hoffman and Jennifer Hansen’s study of gender dynamics in psychiatric disability memoirs makes several fruitful moves for the study of psychic diversity. Perhaps the most important is that the article encourages analytic philosophers to contribute to understanding how individual mental life is affected by the larger cultural context—which we can think of as the “mind/culture” problem. This is an important move because, for the most part, analytic philosophers have paid more attention to the mind/body problem than they (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  8
    Philosophy, History and Social Action: Essays in Honor of Lewis Feuer with an Autobiographic Essay by Lewis Feuer.Lewis Samuel Feuer, Sidney Hook, William L. O'neill & Roger O'Toole - 1988 - Springer.
    Two articles by Lewis Feuer caught my attention in the '40s when 1 was wondering, asa student physicist, about the relations of physics to philosophy and to the world in turmoil. One was his essay on 'The Development of Logical Empiricism' (1941), and the other his critical review of Philipp Frank's biography of Einstein, 'Philosophy and the Theory of Relativity' (1947). How extraordinary it was to find so intelligent, independent, critical, and humane a mind; and furthermore he (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. (1 other version)David Lewis and the Kangaroo: Graphing philosophical progress.Benj Hellie - 2017 - In Russell Blackford & Damien Broderick, Philosophy's Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 213–225.
    Data-driven historiography of philosophy looks to objective modeling tools for illumination of the propagation of influence. While the system of David Lewis, the most influential philosopher of our time, raises historiographic puzzles to stymie conventional analytic methods, it proves amenable to data-driven analysis. A striking result is that Lewis only becomes the metaphysician of current legend following the midpoint of his career: his initial project is to frame a descriptive science of mind and meaning; the transition to metaphysics (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  88
    A companion to David Lewis.Barry Loewer & Jonathan Schaffer (eds.) - 2015 - Chichester, West Sussex ;: Wiley-Blackwell.
    In _A Companion to David Lewis_, Barry Loewer and Jonathan Schaffer bring together top philosophers to explain, discuss, and critically extend Lewis's seminal work in original ways. Students and scholars will discover the underlying themes and complex interconnections woven through the diverse range of his work in metaphysics, philosophy of language, logic, epistemology, philosophy of science, philosophy of mind, ethics, and aesthetics. The first and only comprehensive study of the work of David Lewis, one of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 960