Results for ' foundationalist versus nonfoundationalist views of law'

980 found
Order:
  1.  11
    Legal Pragmatism.Richard Warner - 1996 - In Dennis M. Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Blackwell. pp. 406–414.
    This chapter contains sections titled: What Is Pragmatism? Foundationalist versus Nonfoundationalist Views of the Law Pragmatism and Legitimacy Rejecting the Demand References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  88
    Objectivist Versus Subjectivist Views of Criminality: A Study in the Role of Social Science in Criminal Law Theory.Paul H. Robinson & John M. Darley - 1998 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 18 (3):409-447.
    The authors use social science methodology to determine whether a doctrinal shift—from an objectivist view of criminality in the common law to a subjectivist view in modem criminal codes—is consistent with lay intuitions of the principles of justice. Commentators have suggested that lay perceptions of criminality have shifted in a way reflected in the doctrinal change, but the study results suggest a more nuanced conclusion: that the modern lay view agrees with the subjectivist view of modern codes in defining the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  68
    Hume's Naturalized Philosophy.Yves Michaud - 1987 - Hume Studies 13 (2):360-380.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:360 HUME'S NATURALI Z EP PHILOSOPHY In "Epistemology Naturalized," Quine claimed that the failure of reductive-foundationalist attempts in epistemology, after the model of Carnap' s Aufbau, must lead to a redefinition of epistemology's task. Instead of setting out to reconstruct the whole fabric of our knowledge from absolute data through deductive operations, we should investigate how human subjects derive their knowledge of nature from sensory inputs. Thus epistemology (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  31
    Presumption of Innocence Versus a Principle of Fairness.Magnus Ulväng - 2013 - Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 42 (3):205-224.
    Presumption of Innocence Versus a Principle of Fairness. A Response to Duff In my response to Duff I focus mainly on the following two issues. Firstly, I examine what kind of a norm the presumption of innocence (PoI) really is and how it ontologically differs from other types of rules, principles, rationales, etc. My tentative conclusion is that a PoI does not suffice the requirement of being a dogmatic rule and, thus, has less weight than what Duff perhaps assumes.Secondly, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  15
    Law and morals: proceedings of the special workshop held at the 28th World Congress of the International Association for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy in Lisbon, Portugal, 2017.André Ferreira Leite de Paula & Andrés Santacoloma Santacoloma (eds.) - 2019 - Stuttgart: Nomos.
    The relationship between law and morality is a topic which receives special importance and attention, especially in "liberal democracies" in which the law is supposed to regulate highly pluralized and fragmented societies. Under conditions of plurality of values, many social forces and legal theories require a certain kind of neutrality from the legal system, a means of compatibility of the many "world views" and "moral systems" that are present within the same social space. Such a conciliating commitment sounds particularly (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  96
    The mixed constitution versus the separation of powers: Monarchical and aristocratic aspects of modern democracy.Mogens Hansen - 2010 - History of Political Thought 31 (3):509-531.
    The theory of the separation of powers between a legislature, an executive and a judiciary is still the foundation of modern representative democracy. It was developed by Montesquieu and came to replace the older theory of the mixed constitution which goes back to Plato, Aristotle and Polybios: there are three types of constitution: monarchy, oligarchy and democracy; when institutions from each of the three types are mixed, an interplay between the institutions emerges that affects all functions of state: legislation, implementation (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7. Are all laws of nature created equal? Meta-laws versus more necessary laws.Salim Hirèche, Niels Linnemann & Robert Michels - 2023 - Erkenntnis:1-19.
    Two approaches to elevating certain laws of nature over others have come to prominence recently. On the one hand, according to the meta-laws approach, there are meta-laws, laws which relate to laws as those laws relate to particular facts. On the other hand, according to the modal, or non-absolutist, approach, some laws are necessary in a stricter sense than others. Both approaches play an important role in current research, questioning the ‘orthodoxy’ represented by the leading philosophical theories of natural laws—Humeanism, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  55
    Critical Notice of child versus childmaker: Future persons and present duties in ethics and the law.Peter Vallentyne - 2000 - Noûs 34 (4):634–647.
    In Child versus Childmaker Melinda Roberts provides an enlightening analysis and a cogent defense of a version of the person-affecting restriction in ethics. The rough idea of this restriction is that an action, state of affairs, or world, cannot be wrong, or bad, unless it would wrong, or be bad for, someone. I shall focus solely on Roberts’s core principles, and thus shall not address her interesting chapter-length discussions of wrongful life cases and of human cloning cases. The person-affecting (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. MaxCon extended simples and the dispositionalist ontology of laws.Travis Dumsday - 2017 - Synthese 194 (5).
    Extended simples are physical objects that, while spatially extended, possess no actual proper parts. The theory that physical reality bottoms out at extended simples is one of the principal competing views concerning the fundamental composition of matter, the others being atomism and the theory of gunk. Among advocates of extended simples, Markosian’s ‘MaxCon’ version of the theory has justly achieved particular prominence. On the assumption of causal realism, I argue here that the reality of MaxCon simples would entail the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10. Sociability versus Conflict. Grotius’s Critique of the Doctrine of Raison d’État.W. Julian Korab-Karpowicz - 2011 - Archiwum Historii Filozofii I Myśli Społecznej 56:117-131.
    This article presents Grotius’s argument against raison d’état and his defense of the rule of law in international relations. Grotius remains an important voice in the debate about the character of international politics. He challenges the views of the adherents of the doctrine of raison d’état who, following Machiavelli, give rulers the license to disobey legal and ethical norms whenever the vital interests of the state are at stake, and to use any means to achieve their goals, including warfare. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. The Law Governed Universe.John T. Roberts - 2008 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The law-governed world-picture -- A remarkable idea about the way the universe is cosmos and compulsion -- The laws as the cosmic order : the best-system approach -- The three ways : no-laws, non-governing-laws, governing-laws -- Work that laws do in science -- An important difference between the laws of nature and the cosmic order -- The picture in four theses -- The strategy of this book -- The meta-theoretic conception of laws -- The measurability approach to laws -- What (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  12.  9
    Communicative Reason, Deconstruction, and Foundationalism.Lasse Thomassen - 2013 - Political Theory 41 (3):482-488.
    How should we read Jürgen Habermas, and is it possible to defend a nonfoundationalist conception of communicative reason? In “‘No-Saying’ in Habermas,” Stephen K. White and Evan Robert Farr read Habermas’s writings on civil disobedience through the idea of no-saying, which they believe to be “just as primordial” as consensus or yes-saying in Habermas’s theory of communicative reason. By underlining this otherwise underdeveloped aspect of no-saying in Habermas’s work, White and Farr believe that it is possible to avoid an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  36
    Hobbes versus Hart: Reflections on Legal Positivism and the Point of Punishment.Margaret Martin - 2022 - In Matthew C. Altman (ed.), The Palgrave Handbook on the Philosophy of Punishment. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 53-74.
    Martin highlights the degree to which H. L. A. Hart’s legal positivism relies on Hobbesian assumptions. Like Hart, Hobbes combines utilitarian and retributivist elements. The best way to make sense of Hobbes’s theory of punishment is to follow Quentin Skinner and view both the “sovereign” and the “state” as distinct legal fictions. Unlike Hobbes, Hart asserts these fictions as facts. As a result, Hart’s philosophy of criminal law in Punishment and Responsibility is in tension with his legal philosophy in The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  73
    Intrinsic versus contingent claims about the harmfulness of prostitution.Rosalind J. McDougall - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (2):83-83.
    Moen targets a view about the intrinsic harmfulness of prostitution that he sees as widespread in healthcare, academia and public policy.1 He argues that the exchange of sex for money is not intrinsically harmful by systematically rejecting various possible proposed harms. He further suggests that it is the social context of discriminating laws and stigma that accounts for the harms experienced by prostitutes, rather than any intrinsic feature of exchanging sex for money.One striking aspect of his argument is the particular (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  44
    International Criminal Justice Between Scylla and Charybdis—the “Peace Versus Justice” Dilemma Analysed Through the Lenses of Judith Shklar’s and Hannah Arendt’s Legal and Political Theories.Christof Royer - 2017 - Human Rights Review 18 (4):395-416.
    The present article discusses the “peace versus justice” dilemma in international criminal justice through the lenses of the respective legal theories of Judith Shklar and Hannah Arendt—two thinkers who have recently been described as theorists of international criminal law. The article claims that in interventions carried out by the International Criminal Court, there is an ever-present potentiality for the “peace versus justice” dilemma to occur. Unfortunately, there is no abstract solution to this problem, insofar as ICC interventions will (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  20
    A Unified versus Componential View of Understanding Minds.Lily Tsoi - 2016 - In Wesley Buckwalter & Justin Sytsma (eds.), Blackwell Companion to Experimental Philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell. pp. 279–291.
    Much of the research on theory of mind (ToM) approaches ToM as a unitary construct; on such an account, mental state understanding across different contexts reflects the same cognitive process. Some researchers, however, suggest that ToM can be separated into different components that contribute differently to the understanding of people's minds. Evidence from developmental psychology and cognitive neuroscience supports the notion that ToM consists of at least two components. Three different componential views are discussed: (1) early‐ versus late‐developing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  12
    Artificial intelligence, ethics, law: a view on the Italian and American debate (and on their differences).Alice Giannini - 2022 - Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 51 (2):248-263.
    Artificial intelligence, ethics, law: a view on the Italian and American debate (and on their differences) In the past ten years the scientific discourse on artificial intelligence (AI) has thrived. What are the challenges that AI poses to the law? If something goes wrong, who should be blamed? In the pursuit of answers to these questions, legal scholars – as the authors of the reviewed books – jumped on the AI bandwagon, joining philosophers, ethicists, computer scientists.The essay highlights recurring traits (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  41
    Communicative Reason, Deconstruction, and Foundationalism: Reply to White and Farr.Lasse Thomassen - 2013 - Political Theory 41 (3):0090591713476871.
    How should we read Jürgen Habermas, and is it possible to defend a nonfoundationalist conception of communicative reason? In “‘No-Saying’ in Habermas,” Stephen K. White and Evan Robert Farr read Habermas’s writings on civil disobedience through the idea of no-saying, which they believe to be “just as primordial” as consensus or yes-saying in Habermas’s theory of communicative reason. By underlining this otherwise underdeveloped aspect of no-saying in Habermas’s work, White and Farr believe that it is possible to avoid an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  13
    Genetics and the Law.Aubrey Milunsky, George J. Annas, National Genetics Foundation & American Society of Law and Medicine - 2012 - Springer.
    Society has historically not taken a benign view of genetic disease. The laws permitting sterilization of the mentally re tarded~ and those proscribing consanguineous marriages are but two examples. Indeed as far back as the 5th-10th centuries, B.C.E., consanguineous unions were outlawed (Leviticus XVIII, 6). Case law has traditionally tended toward the conservative. It is reactive rather than directive, exerting its influence only after an individual or group has sustained injury and brought suit. In contrast, state legislatures have not been (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  55
    Finnis’s divided view of law: problems for adjudicative theory.Hillary Nye - 2020 - Jurisprudence 11 (4):503-529.
    Finnis’s theory of law distinguishes between law in the focal sense and law in the legal sense. Law in the focal sense is law that promotes the common good. Citizens may appeal to considerations of...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  27
    Utopia versus Realism? Several upstream reflections.Giovanni Giorgini - 2016 - Governare la Paura. Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies 9 (1).
    The author challenges the canonical opposition of utopia vs. realism in political thought. Although this opposition traces back to the very origins of Western political theory, in the works of such authors as Thucydides and Plato, the author maintains that both ‘utopian’ and ‘realist’ thinkers of every age keep the reality of their society in the background of their political constructions. The real difference is in their view of human nature: ‘utopian’ thinkers have a more optimistic view of human nature, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  21
    6. Bridging scientia and experience: the last evolution of Cartesian foundationalism.Andrea Strazzoni - 2018 - In Dutch Cartesianism and the Birth of Philosophy of Science: From Regius to ‘s Gravesande. Berlin-Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 126-170.
    The sixth chapter focuses on the evolution of Cartesianism in the last quarter of the seventeenth century in Leiden and Amsterdam, against the background of the emergence of alternative views in natural philosophy capable of replacing it as a dominant paradigm, namely, the experimental philosophy of Robert Boyle and the mathematical-experimental approach of Huygens and Newton. The last evolution of Cartesianism is reconstructed in this chapter by considering the ‘Cartesian empiricism’ of Burchard de Volder, and the reflections on the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  44
    Rousseau versus Rawls on International Relations.Grace Roosevelt - 2006 - European Journal of Political Theory 5 (3):301-320.
    This article uses Rousseau’s little-known responses to the Abbé de Saint-Pierre’s Project for Perpetual Peace and his fragments on ‘The State of War’ as a foil for Rawls’s claim that the international society he envisions in The Law of Peoples constitutes a ‘realistic utopia’. The main conclusion is that in a post-9/11 world Rousseau may have more to teach us about the possibilities for international security than Rawls does, since Rousseau’s theory accounts for the moral corruptibility of both individuals and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  49
    BOOK REVIEW: Melinda A. Roberts. CHILD VERSUS CHILDMAKER: FUTURE PERSONS AND PRESENT DUTIES IN ETHICS AND THE LAW. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield, 1998. [REVIEW]Axel Gosseries - 2001 - Ethics and the Environment 6 (2):114-118.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Ethics & the Enviornment 6.2 (2001) 114-118 [Access article in PDF] Book Review Child versus Childmaker: Future Persons and Present Duties in Ethics and the Law Child versus Childmaker: Future Persons and Present Duties in Ethics and the Law. Melinda A. Roberts. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield, 1998. Pp. 235. ISBN 0-8476-8901-8 (Paperback) This book will provide the reader with a systematic examination of some of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  9
    4 On the Instrumental View of Law in American.Brian Z. Tamanaha - 2009 - In Francis J. Mootz (ed.), On Philosophy in American Law. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 27.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. On the instrumental view of law in American legal culture.Brian Z. Tamanaha - 2009 - In Francis J. Mootz (ed.), On Philosophy in American Law. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  27.  61
    What If? The Farther Shores of Neuroethics: Commentary on “Neuroscience May Supersede Ethics and Law”.Henry T. Greely - 2012 - Science and Engineering Ethics 18 (3):439-446.
    Neuroscience is clearly making enormous progress toward understanding how human brains work. The implications of this progress for ethics, law, society, and culture are much less clear. Some have argued that neuroscience will lead to vast changes, superseding much of law and ethics. The likely limits to the explanatory power of neuroscience argue against that position, as do the limits to the social relevance of what neuroscience will be able to explain. At the same time neuroscience is likely to change (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28. A practical view of law: essays in legal philosophy and sociology of law = Shi jian fa lü guan: fa zhe xue he fa she hui xue lun wen ji.Yongliu Zheng - 2022 - Beijing: Fa lü chu ban she.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  55
    Machiavelli versus Rousseau: the social divisions and their role in a well-ordered republic.Renato Moscateli - 2015 - Trans/Form/Ação 38 (s1):121-138.
    RESUMO:As relações de conflito entre os grupos sociais constituem um tópico relevante para a filosofia política, e as maneiras distintas como elas são interpretadas dependem de uma visão mais ampla sobre as condições apropriadas a um Estado bem-ordenado. Maquiavel, por exemplo, ao refletir sobre o caso da Roma Antiga, procurou refutar aqueles que condenavam os tumultos entre os nobres e a plebe da cidade, como se eles tivessem provocado apenas males à república. Para o autor, tais tumultos estavam entre as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  15
    Sociological versus metascientific views of technological Risk assessment.Deborah Mayo - 1997 - In Kristin Sharon Shrader-Frechette & Laura Westra (eds.), Technology and Values. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 217.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  23
    Phenomenological Realism Versus Scientific Realism: Reinhardt Grossmann - David M. Armstrong Metaphysical Correspondence.Javier Cumpa & Erwin Tegtmeier (eds.) - 2009 - De Gruyter.
    The two eminent metaphysicians Armstrong and Grossmann exchanged letters for ten years in which they discussed crucial points of their respective ontologies. They have a common basis. Both do metaphysics proper and not linguistic philosophy. Both advocate universals and acknowledge the key position of the category of states of affairs. However, they differ on the simplicity of universals and the nature of states of affairs. There is also a fundamental methodological disagreement between them. Armstrong accepts only the evidence of natural (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Different Views of Laws of Nature.Ömer Fatih Tekin - 2017 - Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy 7 (1):43-63.
    There are roughly two main understanding in philosophy of science: Epistemology of Science and Metaphysics of Science. It is examined that some concept such as Laws of Nature, Causation, Time and Space into the metaphysics of Science. In this paper, it has been studied laws of nature which is one the most important subjects in metaphysics of science. Let’s think outside the box, there are three significant views about laws of nature; Regularity Theory, Necessitation Theory and Dispositional Essential (...). It has been worked the views of David Lewis in regularity theory. In the section of nomic necessitation we have been scrutinised the arguments put forward by David Armstrong and finally the last section; it has been discussed Alexander Bird’s views of dispositional essentialism comparing with the other two aspects. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  37
    Physical versus historical reality.Henry Margenau - 1952 - Philosophy of Science 19 (3):193-213.
    The science of the 19th and early 20th century permitted the view that all human experience is subject to the deterministic laws of physics. Reality was conformable with these laws, and the laws could be used to designate what is real.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Two Views of the Nature of The Theory of Law: A Partial Comparison.Joseph Raz - 2000 - In Jules L. Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postscript: Essays on the Postscript to `the Concept of Law'. New York: Oxford University Press UK.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  35.  23
    Cloak of Law on Stature of Morality: a critical view on Patrick Devlin's attitude toward legal enforcement of conventional morality.Mohammad Najafi Kalyani, Seyyed Mohammad Hosseini, Kaveh Behbahani & Hossein Dabbagh - 2022 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations 16 (39):542-561.
    The relationship between morality and law is one of the issues that has provoked considerable controversies. Among others, an important discussion is whether obeying “conventional morality” in public and/or private spheres should be legally enforced by legislators. In this paper, we will look at the controversies over the issue of the “legal enforcement of morality” in the well-known debate between Herbert Hart and Patrick Devlin. In light of Richard Hare's moral philosophy, we will begin by distinguishing three realms of morality. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  48
    The state as the mystical foundation of authority.Brian T. Trainor - 2006 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 32 (6):767-779.
    In this article I argue that Jacques Derrida is correct in holding that the law is always an authorized force but that he is mistaken in suggesting that its ultimate font or origin (what he calls the ‘mystical foundation of authority’) is an originary or ‘foundationalional’ act of violence. I suggest that Derrida and, more recently, Jens Bartelson fall prey to a curious, one-sided narrow view of ‘foundationalism’ and contrast their overly ‘architecturalized’ image of the ‘foundation’ of authority with the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  13
    Two Views of the City: Republicanism and Law.John Ferejohn - 2013 - In Andreas Niederberger & Philipp Schink (eds.), Republican democracy: liberty, law and politics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
    Republicans have traditionally opposed democracy, arguing that rule by a majority is a form of despotic or lawless rule, and liberalism due to its emphasis on private goods over public projects and shared or public interests. Today, however, republicanism is associated with certain kinds of ‘democratic’ institutions and deliberative practices, whereas democracy is considered a means of assuring significant liberal protections for individual freedom. This chapter examines the link between republicanism and the nature of law. It describes at least two (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Property and Disagreement, in Philosophical Foundations of Property Law.Stephen R. Munzer (ed.) - 2013 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Legal philosophers and property scholars sometimes disagree over one or more of the following: the meaning of the word 'property,' the concept of property, and the nature of property. For much of the twentieth century, the work of W.N. Hohfeld and Tony Honoré represented a consensus around property. The consensus often went under the heading of property as bundle of rights, or more accurately as a set of normative relations between persons with respect to things. But by the mid-l 990s, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  85
    Categoricalism Versus Dispositionalism: A Case Study in Metametaphysics.Cord Friebe - 2014 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 45 (1):5-15.
    Using meta-metaphysical instruments, the paper analyzes the dispute between ‘reductionist’ Humean categoricalism and ‘bold’ Anti-Humean dispositionalism. It is argued that both views are non-Quinean, hence, heavyweight ontological realisms: careful analysis of specific scientific theories alone is not sufficient. Further, sophisticated philosophical reasoning is needed to defend Anti-Humeanism as well as Humeanism. The paper finally suggests that most if not all ontological disputes are unavoidably “speculative” due to essentialism which cannot be read off contemporary physical theories.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  17
    Science as a way of knowing: the foundations of modern biology.John Alexander Moore - 1993 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Introduction A Brief Conceptual Framework for Biology PART ONE: UNDERSTANDING NATURE 1. The Antecedents of Scientific Thought Animism, Totemism, and Shamanism The Paleolithic View Mesopotamia Egypt 2. Aristotle and the Greek View of Nature The Science of Animal Biology The Parts of Animals The Classification of Animals The Aristotelian System Basic Questions 3. Those Rational Greeks? Theophrastus and the Science of Botany The Roman Pliny Hippocrates, the Father of Medicine Erasistratus Galen of Pergamum The Greek Miracle 4. The Judeo-Christian Worldview (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41. The ultimate argument against Armstrong's contingent necessitation view of laws.Alexander Bird - 2005 - Analysis 65 (2):147-155.
    I show that Armstrong’s view of laws as second-order contingent relations of ‘necessitation’ among categorical properties faces a dilemma. The necessitation relation confers a relation of extensional inclusion (‘constant conjunction’) on its relata. It does so either necessarily or contingently. If necessarily, it is not a categorical relation (in the relevant sense). If contingently, then an explanation is required of how it confers extensional inclusion. That explanation will need to appeal to a third-order relation between necessitation and extensional inclusion. The (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  42.  35
    Book Review: A Biblical View of Law and Justice. [REVIEW]Gary Watt - 2006 - Studies in Christian Ethics 19 (2):251-255.
  43.  31
    Empty spaces: empire versus life.Helen Petrovsky - 2022 - Studies in East European Thought 74 (4):463-474.
    The article analyzes the ongoing Russian–Ukrainian war in terms of a colonial seizure undertaken by a fading but aggressive Russian empire. This highly political adventure is translated into more abstract terms, that is, an irresolvable conflict between existence, which is always the experience of coexistence devoid of any essence whatsoever, and imperial expansion, which is an infinite conquest of space indifferent to all forms of life. The dualism in question is backed up by the writings of two important scholars, namely, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  52
    From Umwelt to Mitwelt: Natural laws versus rule-governed sign-mediated interactions (rsi's).Guenther Witzany - 2006 - Semiotica 2006 (158):425-438.
    Within the last decade, thousands of studies have described communication processes in and between organisms. Pragmatic philosophy of biology views communication processes as rule-governed sign-mediated interactions (rsi's). As sign-using individuals exhibit a relationship to following or not-following these rules, the rsi's of living individuals dier fundamentally from cause-and-effect reactions with and between non-living matter, which exclusively underlie natural laws. Umwelt thus becomes a term in investigating physiological influences on organisms that are not components of rsi's. Mitwelt is a term (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  22
    Law without Lawyers: A Comparative View of Law in China and the United States.Victor H. Li - 1979 - Philosophy East and West 29 (2):237-240.
  46.  38
    The temporality of normativity.Carlo Invernizzi Accetti - 2016 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 42 (1):25-43.
    This article proposes an interpretation of the status of the Grundnorm in Hans Kelsen’s legal theory which addresses the broader philosophical problem of the ultimate foundation of normativity. It begins by reviewing the main objections that have been raised against Kelsen’s theory, pointing out that most of these can be met by a ‘transcendental’ interpretation of the Grundnorm as a condition of possibility for legal cognition. It then argues that in order to solve the problem of the ultimate foundation for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47. Ingarden versus Meinong o logice fikcji.Barry Smith - 1998 - In Z. Muszyński (ed.), Z badań nad prawdą i poznaniem. Wydawnictwo UMC-S. pp. 283–296.
    : For Meinong, familiarly, fictional entities are not created, but rather merely discovered (or picked out) from the inexhaustible realm of Aussersein (beyond being and non-being). The phenomenologist Roman Ingarden, in contrast, offers in his Literary Work of Art of 1931 a constructive ontology of fiction, which views fictional objects as entities which are created by the acts of an author (as laws, for example, are created by acts of parliament). We outline the logic of fiction which is implied (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. The Consistency of Positivist and Realist Views of Law.Timothy Binkley - 1970 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 51 (1):85.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  21
    Between theory and practice: A dilemma for the Morawetz-Wittgenstein view of law.Gary W. Levvis - 2006 - Philosophical Investigations 29 (2):111–128.
    Drawing deeply from Wittgenstein's later works, Thomas Morawetz has articulated a vision of legal decision making according to which it is not a defect, but inherent in the very nature of law, for there to be disagreement among judges regarding their legal decision‐making strategies. Central to Morawetz's account is the notion of a legal grammatical proposition. This essay argues that because legal grammatical remarks lack any truth‐value, they cannot play a justificatory role. This would imply that the rule of law (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Brain in a Vat or Body in a World? Brainbound versus Enactive Views of Experience.Evan Thompson & Diego Cosmelli - 2011 - Philosophical Topics 39 (1):163-180.
    We argue that the minimal biological requirements for consciousness include a living body, not just neuronal processes in the skull. Our argument proceeds by reconsidering the brain-in-a-vat thought experiment. Careful examination of this thought experiment indicates that the null hypothesis is that any adequately functional “vat” would be a surrogate body, that is, that the so-called vat would be no vat at all, but rather an embodied agent in the world. Thus, what the thought experiment actually shows is that the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
1 — 50 / 980