Results for ' pleasure – Aristotle: byproduct of virtuous activity'

975 found
Order:
  1.  15
    Hume and Austen on Pleasure, Sentiment, and Virtue.E. M. Dadlez - 2009-04-17 - In Dominic McIver Lopes & Berys Gaut (eds.), Mirrors to One Another. Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 58–75.
  2.  16
    (1 other version)Aristotle on the Pleasure of Courage.Erica A. Holberg - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 2 (2):153-157.
    Because virtuous action is the fulfillment of our nature and so is constitutive of good living, Aristotle argues for a conceptual connection be-tween virtuous action and pleasure. Yet courage does not seem to conform to this account of virtuous action. Because courageous action involves confronting the fearful, which is painful, and because courageous action can fail to achieve the desired goal, it seems contrary to experience to claim that all truly courageous action is pleasant. I (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  38
    Pleasure and Friendship in Aristotle’s Ethics.Andreas Vakirtzis - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 2 (2):331-335.
    Why do we choose agent X and not Y to be our friend? I examine aspects of Aristotle’s theories of virtuous friendship and pleasure to answer this question. Specifically, I argue that pleasure is connected to the good, and has two fundamental functions for Aristotle: 1) it is a judgment of value, and 2) it accompanies good activity. Furthermore, I show that the pleasure from the good plays an instrumental role in the friendship (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Aristotle on “Steering the Young by Pleasure and Pain”.Marta Jimenez - 2015 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 29 (2):137-164.
    At least since Burnyeat’s “Aristotle on Learning to Be Good,” one of the most popular ways of explaining moral development in Aristotle is by appealing to mechanisms of pleasure and pain. Aristotle himself suggests this kind of explanation when he says that “in educating the young we steer them by the rudders of pleasure and pain” (Nicomachean Ethics X.1, 1172a21). However, I argue that, contrary to the dominant view, Aristotle’s view on moral development in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  5. Wishing for Fortune, Choosing Activity: Aristotle on External Goods and Happiness.Eric Brown - 2006 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 22 (1):221-256.
    Aristotle's account of external goods in Nicomachean Ethics I 8-12 is often thought to amend his narrow claim that happiness is virtuous activity. I argue, to the contrary, that on Aristotle's account, external goods are necessary for happiness only because they are necessary for virtuous activity. My case innovates in three main respects: I offer a new map of EN I 8-12; I identify two mechanisms to explain why virtuous activity requires external (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  6. Aristotle on Self-Knowledge and Friendship.Zena Hitz - 2011 - Philosophers' Imprint 11:1-28.
    In Nicomachean Ethics 10.7, Aristotle says that the contemplative wise person living the happiest and most self-sufficient life will need other people less than a person living a life of practical virtue. This seems to be in tension with Aristotle's emphasis elsewhere on the political nature of human beings. I analyze in detail Aristotle's most elaborate defense of the need for friends in the happy life in Nicomachean Ethics 9.9 to see whether and how he resolves the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  7. The motivational state of the virtuous agent.Lorraine Besser-Jones - 2012 - Philosophical Psychology 25 (1):93 - 108.
    Julia Annas argues that Aristotle's understanding of the phenomenological experience of the virtuous agent corresponds to psychologist Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi's concept of the ?flow,? which is a form of intrinsic motivation. In this paper, I explore whether or not Annas? understanding of virtuous agency is a plausible one. After a thorough analysis of psychological accounts of intrinsic and extrinsic states of motivation, I argue that despite the attractiveness of Annas? understanding of virtuous agency, it is subject to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8.  3
    When Moral Pleasure Conflicts with Moral Sorrow.Drishtti Rawat - forthcoming - Journal of Value Inquiry:1-11.
    In this paper, I discuss two of Aristotle’s major requirements for the virtuous person. First, the virtuous person takes pleasure in virtuous activity. Second, the virtuous person experiences the appropriate affective states in the appropriate situations. However, in some situations, the appropriate affective state is sorrow. In such situations, it appears that the virtuous person is expected to experience two conflicting emotions, namely, moral pleasure and moral sorrow. This conflict raises the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Does a Perfect Activity Necessarily Yield Pleasure? An Evaluation of the Relation between Pleasure and Activity in Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics VII and X.Gerd Van Riel - 1999 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 7 (2):211-224.
    In his discussion of pleasure, Aristotle assumes the thesis that a perfect activity always and necessarily yields pleasure. The occurrence of pleasure is even presented as a sign that the activity is perfect. But this assumption seems to be too easy. It is possible that we do feel pleasure in activities which are not perfectly performed, and on the other hand, it is not certain at all that I will enjoy a perfect (...). Pleasure falls into the category of what J. Elster has called 'states that are essentially by-products'. Up to a point, Aristotle acknowledges this, but he does not follow this analysis to its final consequences. If one agrees, as Aristotle does, that there is a difference between the perfect activity and pleasure, it should be possible that an activity is perfect without yielding pleasure, or that pleasure will accompany even an activity which is not perfect. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  67
    Aristotle on Choosing Virtuous Action for its Own Sake.Yannig Luthra - 2015 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 96 (3):423-441.
    While Aristotle claims that virtuous actions are choiceworthy for their own sakes, he also claims that many virtuous actions are to be chosen as instrumental means to securing further ends. It would seem that an action is choiceworthy for its own sake only if it would be choiceworthy whether or not it served further ends. How, then, can such virtuous actions be choiceworthy for their own sakes? This article criticizes John Ackrill's and Jennifer Whiting's answers to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  37
    The Pleasure Thesis in the Eudemian Ethics.Giulia Bonasio - 2022 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 60 (4):521-536.
    Abstractabstract:This paper argues that in the Eudemian Ethics (EE), Aristotle aims to prove the Pleasure Thesis (PT). According to the Pleasure Thesis, happiness is the most pleasant thing of all. Through a reconstruction of the argument in favor of PT, this paper shows that happiness is most pleasant for three reasons: (1) it is pleasant by definition; (2) it is constituted by the most pleasant activities (virtuous actions and contemplation); (3) it is pleasant by nature. A (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  11
    The Theology of Play and the Play of Theology in Thomas Aquinas.I. I. I. David L. Whidden - 2016 - The Thomist 80 (2):273-284.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Theology of Play and the Play of Theology in Thomas AquinasDavid L. Whidden IIISTUDENTS OF THOMAS AQUINAS have argued over many issues in the last 150 years or so; in fact, it is nearly impossible to get out of the very first question of the Summa Theologiae without entering into a century-long debate about the status of sacred doctrine as an Aristotelian science. We ponder whether theology meets (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Hate and Happiness in Aristotle.Jozef Müller - 2022 - In Noell Birondo (ed.), The Moral Psychology of Hate. Lanham and London: Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 2-21.
    Aristotle tells us that in order to develop virtue, one needs to come to love and hate the right sorts of things. However, his description of the virtuous person clearly privileges love to hate. It is love rather than hate that is the main driving force of a good life. It is because of her love of knowledge, truth and beauty that the virtuous person organizes her life in a certain way and pursues these rather than other (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  23
    Living Together: Essays on Aristotle's Ethics.Jennifer Whiting - 2023 - New York, US: OUP Usa.
    This book comprises essays centered on Aristotle’s objectivist conception of eudaimonia, especially the roles played in it by activities of theoretical and practical intellect and the quality of our relationships with one another. Common objections to grounding this conception in the “proper function” of a human being are answered by appeal to the role played by Aristotle’s teleologically driven essentialism. His struggle to reconcile living in accordance with distinctively human virtues with the ideal of living a “divine” contemplative (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  59
    Aristotle on How Pleasure Perfects Activity (Nicomachean Ethics x.5 1175a29-b14): The Optimising-View.David Machek - 2022 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 104 (3):448-467.
    This article offers a new interpretation of Aristotle’s ambiguous and much-discussed claim that pleasure perfects activity. This interpretation provides an alternative to the two main competing readings of this claim in the scholarship: the addition-view, which envisages the perfection conferred by pleasure as an extra perfection beyond the perfection of activity itself; and the identity-view, according to which pleasure just is the perfect activity itself. The proposed interpretation departs from both these views in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16. The phenomenology of virtue.Julia Annas - 2008 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (1):21-34.
    What is it like to be a good person? I examine and reject suggestions that this will involve having thoughts which have virtue or being a good person as part of their content, as well as suggestions that it might be the presence of feelings distinct from the virtuous person’s thoughts. Is there, then, anything after all to the phenomenology of virtue? I suggest that an answer is to be found in looking to Aristotle’s suggestion that virtuous (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  17.  43
    Reading Aristotle’s Ethics. Virtue, Rhetoric, and Political Philosophy. [REVIEW]Leo J. Elders - 1998 - Review of Metaphysics 52 (2):493-494.
    The author sees his scholarly book as a contribution to the “remarkable resurgence of interest in Aristotle’s moral and political philosophy.” Despite the difficulty of integrating the various parts of the Nicomachean Ethics into a harmonious doctrine, Tessitore defends the cogency of the text. In five chapters he deals with several of the main topics studied by Aristotle. The Ethics is addressed to morally serious persons. The second chapter discusses the virtues treated in books 2–7. Special attention is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. The Advantages of Civic Friendship.Joyce L. Jenkins - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Research 24:459-471.
    Aristotle distinguishes three types of friendship: virtue or character friendship, advantage friendship, and pleasure friendship. He also holds that the civic relation is a friendship, but it is unclear to which of the three types it belongs. There appear to be two candidates. It is either a character friendship, or an advantage friendship. I argue that it cannot be a character friendship, since that would entail that citizens have active goodwill toward one another, and Aristotle claims that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  66
    Ethics and Political Philosophy. Vol 2 of The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, and: The Common Good in Late Medieval Political Thought (review).Thomas Michael Osborne - 2002 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 40 (1):119-121.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 40.1 (2002) 119-121 [Access article in PDF] Book Review Ethics and Political Philosophy The Common Good in Late Medieval Political Thought Arthur Stephen McGrade, John Kilcullen, and Matthew Kempshall, editors. Ethics and Political Philosophy. Vol. 2 of The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000. Pp. xii + 664. Cloth, $85.00. Paper, $29.95. M. S. Kempshall. The Common (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Aristotle on the Heterogeneity of Pleasure.Matthew Strohl - 2018 - In Lisa Shapiro (ed.), Pleasure: A History. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, Usa.
    In Nicomachean Ethics X.5, Aristotle gives a series of arguments for the claim that pleasures differ from one another in kind in accordance with the differences in kind among the activities they arise in connection with. I develop an interpretation of these arguments based on an interpretation of his theory of pleasure (which I have defended elsewhere) according to which pleasure is the perfection of perfect activity. In the course of developing this interpretation, I reconstruct (...)’s phenomenology of pleasure, arguing that while he denies that all pleasures share any given phenomenal element, he does think that all pleasures have a common phenomenal structure. Finally, I argue that Aristotle’s view that pleasures differ in kind does not imply that they cannot be compared in pleasantness. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  50
    Pleasure and the Good Life: Plato, Aristotle, and the Neoplatonists.Paul van Riel - 2000 - Boston: Brill.
    This volume deals with the general theory of pleasure of Plato and his successors. The first part describes the two paradigms between which all theories of pleasure oscillate: Plato's definition of pleasure as the repletion of a lack, and Aristotle's view that pleasure is the perfect performance of an activity. After an excursus on Epicureans and Stoics, the book concentrates on Neoplatonism, opposing the 'standard Neoplatonic view' of Plotinus and Proclus to the original viewpoint (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  1
    Pleasure and Desire - A Continuity of Aristotle’s Understanding of Pleasure in the Rhetoric and the Nicomachean Ethics -. 권혁성 - 2024 - CHUL HAK SA SANG - Journal of Philosophical Ideas 93 (93):3-40.
    본고는 아리스토텔레스의 즐거움 이해에서『수사학』과『니코마코스윤리학』이 갖는 관계를, 이 즐거움 이해의 ‘연속성’에 주목하여, 새로이 규명하려 한다. 이 연속성은 양 저술의 즐거움 논의가 ‘즐거움은 욕구의 실현’이라는 생각을 공통된 근간 논제로 삼고 있다는 것이다. 이에 따라『니코마코스 윤리학』의 즐거움 논의는,『수사학』에 수용된 플라톤적 즐거움 개념이 ‘즐거움은 운동의 과정이니 좋은 것일 수 없다’고 설명하므로, 이를 윤리학적 목적에 따라 비판하고 이 목적에 부합하는 학문적 엄밀성을 가진 대안으로서 ‘활동’ 개념을 제시하면서도, 이 플라톤적 개념이 즐거움을 욕구의 실현으로 이해하기에 기본적으로 진리성을 갖는다고 인정한다. 이 진리성은『수사학』의 목적에 부합하는 수사학적 진리성인데,『수사학』의 즐거움 논의는 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. The Activity of Happiness In Aristotle’s Ethics.Gary M. Gurtler - 2003 - Review of Metaphysics 56 (4):801-834.
    This article examines happiness as an activity, modeled on pleasure in NE 10, 1-5. Aristotle is not proposing a choice, but defining the formal nature of happiness. Contemplation, as the activity of wisdom, constitutes happiness in the strict and formal sense. It has all the attributes of happiness, highest, most continuous, most pleasant, most self-sufficient, leisured, and an end in itself. Practical virtues are formally secondary, as including elements outside the activity of the best part (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  76
    The value of pleasure in Plato's Philebus and Aristotle's Ethics.Joachim Aufderheide - unknown
    This thesis is a study of the theories of pleasure as proposed in Plato’s Philebus, Aristotle’s EN VII.11-14 and EN X.1-5, with particular emphasis on the value of pleasure. Focusing on the Philebus in Chapters 1 and 2, I argue that the account of pleasure as restorative process of a harmonious state in the soul is in tension with Plato’s claim that some pleasures are good in their own right. I show that there are in fact (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  57
    The Better Part.Stephen R. L. Clark - 1993 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 35:29-49.
    According to Aristotle, the goal of anyone who is not simply stupid or slavish is to live a worthwhile life. There are, no doubt, people who have no goal at all beyond the moment's pleasure or release from pain. There may be people incapable of reaching any reasoned decision about what to do, and acting on it. But anyone who asks how she should live implicitly agrees that her goal is to live well, to live a life that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Aristotle, Egoism and the Virtuous Person’s Point of View’.Stephen Gardiner - 2001 - In D. Blyth D. Baltzly (ed.), Power and Pleasure, Virtues and Vices: Essays in Ancient Moral Philosophy. pp. 239-262.
    According to the traditional interpretation, Aristotle’s ethics, and ancient virtue ethics more generally, is fundamentally grounded in self-interest, and so in some sense egoistic. Most contemporary ethical theorists regard egoism as morally repellent, and so dismiss Aristotle’s approach. But recent traditional interpreters have argued that Aristotle’s egoism is not vulnerable to this criticism. Indeed, they claim that Aristotle’s egoism actually accommodates morality. For, they say, Aristotle’s view is that an agent’s best interests are partially constituted (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  37
    Aristotle's poetics as an extension of his ethical and political theory.Anne Hewitt - 2006 - History of Political Thought 27 (1):10-26.
    In this paper I seek to link Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics and Politics to his Poetics. Specifically, I wish to argue that his ethical and political works imply that the realization of the human good, virtuous activity, can come about only given extended political experience. I then suggest that poetry (as presented by Aristotle in the Poetics) might itself be seen as a form of political experience that can strengthen and clarify ethical and political theory and aid (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Virtue Habituation and the Skill of Emotion Regulation.Paul E. Carron - 2021 - In Tom P. S. Angier & Lisa Ann Raphals (eds.), Skill in Ancient Ethics: The Legacy of China, Greece and Rome. New York: Bloomsbury Academic. pp. pp. 115-140.
    In Nicomachean Ethics 2.1, Aristotle draws a now familiar analogy between aretai ('virtues') and technai ('skills'). The apparent basis of this comparison is that both virtue and skill are developed through practice and repetition, specifically by the learner performing the same kinds of actions as the expert: in other words, we become virtuous by performing virtuous actions. Aristotle’s claim that “like states arise from like activities” has led some philosophers to challenge the virtue-skill analogy. In particular, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  39
    The Importance of Love in Aristotle's Ethics.Richard Kraut - 1975 - Philosophy Research Archives 1:300-322.
    My aim is to show how Aristotle's theory of friendship supports his thesis that happiness requires virtuous activity. Ethical behavior is valuable, according to the Nicomachean Ethics, not solely because it uses reason (the immoral can use reason too), but also because it is the expression of a loving attitude towards other persons. By emphasizing this aspect of virtuous activity, I defend Aristotle against the charge that his high estimation for pure intellectual activity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  3
    An Evaluation on "The Literature of the Nafs" in Mawardi's Work Named Kitab Aadab al-Dunya w'al-Din.Özkan Kerimoğlu - 2025 - Fırat Üniversitesi İlahiyat Fakültesi Dergisi 29 (2):79-95.
    In the sacred texts, human beings are described as being created in the most beautiful way. In order to understand and define its integrity of existence in the most accurate way, it is necessary to know both its biological and spiritual aspects. In addition to the well-known and generally accepted characteristics of humans such as will and responsibility, there are also basic realities that constitute humans such as nafs, soul and mind. One of the most powerful factors that make a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  99
    Aristotle on the Good of Virtue-Friendship.D. N. Schroeder - 1992 - History of Political Thought 13 (2):203.
    Aristotle's well-known divisions of friendship, those based on utility, pleasure and virtue, are based on the kind of good each provides. It is fairly easy to see what is contributed by utility- and pleasure-friendships, but virtue-friendship presents a special difficulty. Aristotle writes that virtue-friendship occurs between good (virtuous) persons, each of whom is happy because of that goodness. Aristotle also asserts, however, that the good (happy) person, especially the philosopher, is largely self-sufficient, needing little (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32. External Goods and the Complete Exercise of Virtue in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.Sukaina Hirji - 2020 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 103 (1):29-53.
    In Nicomachean Ethics 1.8, Aristotle seems to argue that certain external goods are needed for happiness because, in the first place, they are needed for virtuous activity. This has puzzled scholars. After all, it seems possible for a virtuous agent to exercise her virtuous character even under conditions of extreme hardship or deprivation. Indeed, it is natural to think these are precisely the conditions under which one's virtue shines through most clearly. Why then does (...) think that a wide range of external goods is required for virtuous activity, and therefore, for happiness? -/- I argue that there is good sense to be made of Aristotle's stance on external goods. Specifically, I explain how, on this view, a range of external goods is required for the full exercise of virtue, and I show that it is only this full exercise that is constitutive of eudaimonia. Drawing on passages in Politics 7.13 and Nicomachean Ethics 3.1, I develop and defend a distinction between the "mere" exercise of virtue, and the full or complete exercise of virtue. I argue that, for Aristotle, the distinguishing feature of this distinction is the value of the virtuous action's ends. An action that fully expresses virtue aims at an end that is unqualifiedly good, while an action that merely exercises virtue does not. I argue that the external goods Aristotle mentions in NE 1.8 are necessary for performing actions with unqualifiedly good ends, and so necessary for the complete exercise of virtue. In addition to providing a more satisfactory account than existing proposals of the role of external goods in Aristotelian happiness, my interpretation has two additional upshots. First, it brings to light an under-appreciated and independently compelling feature of Aristotle's ethical thought: the value of virtuous actions depends in part on the value of the ends they aim to realize. Second, it finds in Aristotle a distinct and powerful way of thinking about the badness of certain kinds of misfortune and deprivation: they are bad in part because they prevent us from fully realizing our capacity for moral agency, from fully engaging with value in the world. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33.  40
    Aristotle’s Account of Moral Perception (EN.VI.8) & Nussbaum’s Priority of the Particular Thesis.Benjamin Hole - 2021 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 77 (1):357-380.
    Consider a contemporary retrieval of Aristotle’s account of moral perception. Drawing from EN.VI.8, Martha Nussbaum argues that we perceive moral particulars prior to ethical principles. First, I explain her priority of the particular thesis. The virtuous person perceives value in the world, as part of her moral deliberation. This perceptual skill is an important aspect of her virtuous activity, and hence also part of her eudaimonia. Second, I present her priority thesis with a dilemma: our perception (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  6
    Aristotle: An Unstable View.Julia Annas - 1993 - In The Morality of Happiness. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Aristotle, in making virtuous activity necessary but not sufficient for happiness, tries to do justice to the intuitive requirement that the content of happiness not be revised so as to shock our intuitions that happiness involves worldly success and enjoyment. But he also tries to do justice to the theoretical pull: happiness must involve virtuous activity over one's life as a whole. Aristotle runs into difficulties over the level of external goods required for the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Aristotle on Self-Sufficiency, External Goods, and Contemplation.Marc Gasser-Wingate - 2020 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 102 (1):1-28.
    Aristotle tells us that contemplation is the most self-sufficient form of virtuous activity: we can contemplate alone, and with minimal resources, while moral virtues like courage require other individuals to be courageous towards, or courageous with. This is hard to square with the rest of his discussion of self-sufficiency in the Ethics: Aristotle doesn't generally seek to minimize the number of resources necessary for a flourishing human life, and seems happy to grant that such a life (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36.  91
    When Aristotelian virtuous agents acquire the fine for themselves, what are they acquiring?Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - 2020 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 28 (4):674-692.
    In the Nicomachean Ethics, one of Aristotle’s most frequent characterizations of the virtuous agent is that she acts for the sake of the fine (to kalon). In IX.8, this pursuit of the fine receives a more specific description; virtuous agents maximally assign the fine to themselves. In this paper, I answer the question of how we are to understand the fine as individually and maximally acquirable. I analyze Nicomachean Ethics IX.7, where Aristotle highlights virtuous (...) (energeia) as central to the fine, and argue that when virtuous agents pursue the fine, what they are pursuing is virtuous activity. I then address various problems, like how virtuous people can maximize virtuous activity yet sacrifice their lives, which would seem to amount to sacrificing future opportunities to virtuous activity and therefore not maximizing it. I also eliminate alternative interpretations that do not take virtuous activity as necessary to the fine, for example the common good interpretation, whereby virtuous agents pursuing the fine amounts to their pursuing the common good. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37.  69
    Spinoza’s Virtuous Passions.Matthew J. Kisner - 2008 - Review of Metaphysics 61 (4):759-783.
    While it is often supposed that Spinoza understood a life of virtue as one of pure activity, with as few passions as possible, this paper aims to make explicit how the passions for Spinoza contribute positively to our virtue. This requires, first, explaining how a passion can increase our power, given Spinoza’s view on the passions generally, which, in turn, requires coming to terms with the problem of passive pleasure, that is, the problem of explaining how being passive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38. Resolving the Paradox of Pleasure in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics VII & X.Rashad Rehman - 2024 - Arche 7 (1):93-108.
    Many read Aristotle as having two inconsistent accounts of pleasure – what G. E. L. Owen called the ‘A’ and ‘B’ accounts of pleasure. The A account holds that pleasures are “activities” (energeiai) (NE, VII; EE, IV, 1153a9-15) and the B account holds that pleasures complete or perfect energeiai, but are not themselves energeiai (NE, X, 1174b14-75b1). Specifically for Owen, a reconciliation of the A-B dilemma involved treating A and B, respectively, as two, mutually exclusive accounts of (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  20
    The Restoration Theory of Pleasure and Its Rhetorical Usefulness : The concept of pleasure in Aristotle’s Rhetoric I 11. 한석환 - 2017 - Journal of the Society of Philosophical Studies 118:1-24.
    아리스토텔레스가 『수사학』 I 11장에서 내놓는 쾌락 정의는 그가 『니코마코스 윤리학』 7권과 10권에서 내놓는 그것과 사뭇 다르다. 전자는 쾌락을 복원이라고 하지만 후자는 활동이라고 규정하기 때문이다. 이에 이 글은 어째서 이런 차이가 나는지 그 이유를 따져 묻는다. 종국적으로는 윤리학적 쾌락이론으로는 다 설명할 수 없는 구석이 있어 청중과의 소통이 핵심 과제인 수사학에서는 통속적인 쾌락을 설명하는 데 안성맞춤인 플라톤식의 복원 이론이 인용된다는 결론에 이른다. 요는 관심의 대상이 되는 쾌락이 서로 달라 그 정의 역시 달라질 수밖에 없었다는 말이다. 그밖에도 쾌락복원모델은 혼합감정과 대립감정을 설명하는 데에 기여하는 (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  74
    Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction (review).Roderick T. Long - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):411-412.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.3 (2003) 411-412 [Access article in PDF] Deborah Achtenberg. Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction. Albany: The State University of New York Press, 2002. Pp. xiii + 218. Paper, $20.95.Deborah Achtenberg argues that, for Aristotle, virtue is a disposition to respond to situations with the appropriate emotions, where emotions are understood as perceptions of the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  79
    Aristotle on Pleasure.Robert Scott Stewart - 1990 - Auslegung 16 (1):97-108.
    Aristotle provides two extended discussions on the subject of pleasure within the Nicomachean Ethics. The first, which comprises the last four chapters of Book 7, produces a definition of pleasure in which pleasure is identified with activity (energeia). But in the second discussion of pleasure—provided in the first five chapters of Book 10-this position is characterized as "strange" or "absurd" (1175b 35). Instead of an identification between the two, pleasure is now said to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  84
    Aristotle Against Delos: Pleasure in Nicomachean Ethics x.Joachim Aufderheide - 2016 - Phronesis 61 (3):284-306.
    Two crucial questions, if unanswered, impede our understanding of Aristotle’s account of pleasure inenx.4-5: (1) What are the activities that pleasure is said to complete? (2) In virtue of what does pleasurealwaysaccompany these activities? The answers fall in place if we read Aristotle as responding to the Delian challenge that the finest, best and most pleasant are not united in one and the same thing (eni.8). I propose an ‘ethical’ reading ofenx.4 according to which the best (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43. From Duty and for the Sake of the Noble: Kant and Aristotle on Morally Good Action.Christine M. Korsgaard - 1996 - In Stephen Engstrom & Jennifer Whiting (eds.), Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty. Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle believes that an agent lacks virtue unless she enjoys the performance of virtuous actions, while Kant claims that the person who does her duty despite contrary inclinations exhibits a moral worth that the person who acts from inclination lacks. Despite these differences, this chapter argues that Aristotle and Kant share a distinctive view of the object of human choice and locus of moral value: that what we choose, and what has moral value, are not mere acts, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  44.  20
    Pleasure, Virtue, and Happiness in the Gorgias.Daniel Russell - 2005 - In Plato on pleasure and the good life. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter argues that Plato's reliance on the directive conception of happiness explains the general course that Socrates' discussion takes with his companions in the Gorgias. It then takes a closer look at Socrates' own argument that virtue determines happiness. Not only does Socrates' argument articulate the nature of virtue as a skill, and the nature of success and flourishing for human beings, but it also removes the gap between virtue and happiness which hedonism — and all forms of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Socrates, pleasure, and value.George Rudebusch - 1999 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this study, George Rudebusch addresses whether Socrates was a hedonist--whether he believed pleasure to be the good. In attempting to locate Socrates' position on hedonism, Rudebusch examines the passages in Plato's early dialogues that are the most disputed on the topic. He maintains that Socrates identifies pleasant activity with virtuous activity, describing Socrates' hedonism as one of activity, not sensation. This analysis allows for Socrates to find both virtue and pleasure to be the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  46.  31
    On Proper Action and Virtue: An Essay on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.Joseph Karuzis - 2015 - IAFOR Journal of Ethics, Religion and Philosophy 2 (1):19-29.
    This paper will discuss and analyze specific arguments concerning moral virtue and action that are found within the ten books of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Eudaimonia, i.e. well-being, or happiness, is the highest good for people, and in order to achieve this, a virtuous character is necessary. A virtuous character is cultivated, and the life of a virtuous human is a life that is lived well, and is lived according to moral virtues which are developed through proper (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. Aristotle on Happiness, Virtue, and Wisdom.Bryan C. Reece - 2023 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle thinks that happiness is an activity---it consists in doing something---rather than a feeling. It is the best activity of which humans are capable and is spread out over the course of a life. But what kind of activity is it? Some of his remarks indicate that it is a single best kind of activity, intellectual contemplation. Other evidence suggests that it is an overarching activity that has various virtuous activities, ethical and intellectual, (...)
  48. In Defense of Aristotle's Notion of Eudaimonia as an Activity of Contemplation.Atina Knowles - 2023 - Archeology and Anthropology Open Access 4 (5):664-70.
    The paper addresses claims that Aristotle's notion of happiness is inconsistent given his expositions of happiness in Book I and Book X of NE. It argues that such claims are rooted in the erroneous conclusion that Aristotle defines happiness in Book I as living a "good life", and an unwarranted assumption that when Aristotle identifies happiness with contemplation, he has a professional philosopher in mind and contemplation as an activity one engages in leisurely and as a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  47
    The Subjectivity and Universality of Virtues—An Investigation Based on Confucius’ and Aristotle’s Views.Shenbai Liao - 2011 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 6 (2):217-238.
    Philosophers today are inclined to propose virtues are either something subjective or something universal. However, Confucius and Aristotle, who made the most profound investigations into virtues, did not develop such theses. The deep-seated reason lies in their belief that there is always a possibility for a human being to become a man of practice, which cancels the need of proposing subjectivity thesis. The reason for their not raising the universality thesis of virtues is that they do not think that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  18
    Friendship, ēthos and equality in Aristotle’s treatment of democratic politeiai.Elena Irrera - 2022 - Araucaria 24 (49).
    The aim of this essay is to bring to light the role played by concern for the ēthos of citizens in the establishment and preservation of regimes by virtuous legislative activity, with special reference to democratic forms of government. To this goal, I will lay stress on the idea of “political friendship”, which Aristotle explores in his ethical works in relation to the power of virtuous legislative activity to shape the habits of citizens. An analysis (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 975