Results for 'Anttoni E. A. Kuusela'

964 found
Order:
  1.  1
    Empty Education: A Dialogue of Nishitani and Rancière.Anttoni E. A. Kuusela & Sari Hietamäki - forthcoming - Journal of Philosophy of Education.
    In this article, we study the educational views of two philosophers from two different intellectual traditions: those of the East and West. We aim to explore comparative philosophy, a method intrinsic to the Kyoto School, as a practice, using it to engage the ideas of Nishitani Keiji and Jacques Rancière in dialogue. This dialogue takes place between Nishitani’s concept of emptiness and Rancière’s concept of equality. Taking inspiration from what Anton Luis Sevilla has termed ‘negative education’, we propose an alternative (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  12
    (1 other version)Listening Without a Listener – Understanding the Self and the Activity of Listening to Music Through Nishitani Keiji’ Philosophy.Anttoni Kuusela - 2025 - Journal of East Asian Philosophy 4 (2):123-136.
    In our everyday life, music is taken as an object – an object that is helpful in one sense or the other: Music can help alleviate sadness, lift the mood if life seems a bit dull, or enhance an already great atmosphere. In other words, music is often approached as an instrument of so-called affective scaffolding. Yet music is more than an instrument which can be used to gain desired affective states. In the present paper, the possibility of an experience (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  96
    From metaphysics and philosophical theses to grammar: Wittgenstein's turn.Oskari Kuusela - 2005 - Philosophical Investigations 28 (2):95–133.
    The paper discusses Wittgenstein's conception of philosophy as devoid of theses. Although already the _Tractatus aims to abandon philosophical theses, it relapses to such theses. In his later work Wittgenstein develops a novel conception of the status of philosophical statements. Rather than to state what his object of investigation, e.g., the use of a word, must be, the philosopher is to employ rules, examples etc., as 'objects of comparison'. A philosophical statement does not describe a necessity in reality. The modality (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  4. The struggle against dogmatism: Wittgenstein and the concept of philosophy.Oskari Kuusela - 2008 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Wittgenstein on philosophical problems : from one fundamental problem to particular problems -- The Tractatus on philosophical problems -- Wittgenstein's later conception of philosophical problems -- Examples of philosophical problems as based on misunderstandings -- Tendencies and inclinations of thinking : philosophy as therapy -- Wittgenstein's notion of peace in philosophy : the contrast with the Tractatus -- Two conceptions of clarification -- The Tractatus's conception of philosophy as logical analysis -- Wittgenstein's later critique of the Tractatus's notion of logical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  5.  63
    Wittgenstein and the unity of good.Oskari Kuusela - 2020 - European Journal of Philosophy 28 (2):428-444.
    This paper discusses the problem of the unity of moral good, concerning the kind of unity that moral good or the concept thereof constitutes. In particular, I am concerned with how Wittgenstein’s identification of various complex modes of conceptual unity, and his introduction of a methodology of clarification for dealing with such complex concepts, can help with the problem of unity, as it rises from the moral philosophical tradition. Relating to this I also address the disputed question, whether Wittgenstein regards (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  6.  27
    Wittgenstein on Logic and Philosophical Method.Oskari Kuusela - 2022 - Cambridge University Press.
    This Element outlines Wittgenstein's early and later philosophies of logic, and explains Wittgenstein's views regarding the methodological significance of logic for philosophy. Wittgenstein's early philosophy of logic is presented as a further development of Frege's and Russell's accounts of logic, and Wittgenstein later philosophy as a response to problems with his early views, including confusions about idealization and abstraction in logic. The later Wittgenstein's novel logical methods, such as the method of language-games, are outlined, and the new kind of logical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7. Carnap and the Tractatus' Philosophy of Logic.Oskari Kuusela - 2012 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 1 (3):1-25.
    This article discusses the relation between the early Wittgenstein’s and Carnap’s philosophies of logic, arguing that Carnap’s position in The Logical Syntax of Language is in certain respects much closer to the Tractatus than has been recognized. In Carnapian terms, the Tractatus’ goal is to introduce, by means of quasi-syntactical sentences, syntactical principles and concepts to be used in philosophical clarification in the formal mode. A distinction between the material and formal mode is therefore already part of the Tractatus’ view, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  8. Wittgenstein, Ethics and Philosophical Clarification.Oskari Kuusela - 2017 - In Reshef Agam-Segal & Edmund Dain, Wittgenstein’s Moral Thought. New York: Routledge. pp. 37-65.
    In this chapter I discuss Wittgenstein’s early and later views on ethics in the light of the development of his views on logic and philosophical method, maintaining that these developments are motivated by his aspiration to discover a method that enables one to do justice to the complexity of though and language use, and the richness of phenomena. I begin by discussing certain continuous features of Wittgenstein’s views on ethics and philosophy, in particular his conception that philosophy can only offer (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9.  16
    Defending Diamond Against Harcourt: Wittgensteinian Moral Philosophy and the Subject Matter of Ethics.Oskari Kuusela - 2021 - In Maria Balaska, Cora Diamond on Ethics. Springer Verlag. pp. 81-102.
    This chapter discusses Edward Harcourt’s recent criticism of Cora Diamond’s account of Wittgensteinian moral philosophy, and the view she associates with Wittgenstein that ethics has no specific subject matter. I argue that Harcourt has misconstrued Diamond’s account, and that his own proposal for what a Wittgensteinian moral philosophy would be like is not consistent with what Wittgenstein says about morality. In particular, Wittgenstein’s suggestion in his later philosophy that goodness is not a quality or property of actions in addition to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10. Glock, Hans Johann (2007). Perspectives on Wittgenstein: an intermittently opinionated survey. In: Kahane, G; Kanterian, E; Kuusela, O. Wittgenstein's Interpreters. Essays in Memory of Gordon Baker. Oxford: Blackwell, 37-65.Hans Johann Glock, G. Kahane, E. Kanterian & O. Kuusela (eds.) - 2007
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  45
    Gordon Baker, Wittgensteinian Philosophical Conceptions and Perspicuous Representation: the Possibility of Multidimensional Logical Descriptions.Oskari Kuusela - 2014 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 3 (2):71-98.
    This paper discusses Gordon Baker’s interpretation of the later Wittgenstein, in particular his interpretation of the notion of Wittgensteinian philosophical conceptions and the notions of non-exclusivity, local incompatibility, non-additivity and global pluralism which Baker uses to characterize Wittgensteinian conceptions. On the basis of this discussion, and a critique of certain features of Baker’s interpretation of Wittgensteinian conceptions, I introduce the notion of a multidimensional logical description of language use, explaining how this notion, which Baker’s interpretation excludes, constitutes and important element (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12. Transcendental arguments and the problem of dogmatism.Oskari Kuusela - 2008 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 16 (1):57 – 75.
    Transcendental arguments have been described as undogmatic or non-dogmatic arguments. This paper examines this contention critically and addresses the question of what is required from an argument for which the characterization is valid. I shall argue that although transcendental arguments do in certain respects meet what one should require from non-dogmatic arguments, they - or more specifically, what I shall call 'general transcendental arguments' - involve an assumption about conceptual unity that constitutes a reason for not attributing to them the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  80
    Ethics in the Wake of Wittgenstein.Benjamin De Mesel & Oskari Kuusela (eds.) - 2019 - New York: Routledge.
    Edited collection on Wittgensteinian ethics. With contributions by Oskari Kuusela, Edward Harcourt, Anne-Marie Christensen, Sabina Lovibond, Alexander Miller, Benjamin De Mesel, Cora Diamond, Lars Hertzberg, Jeremy Johnson, Craig Taylor, Alice Crary, Lynette Reid.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  13
    Bad Faith or True Desire?Antti Kuusela - 2010 - In Fritz Allhoff, Michael Bruce & Robert M. Stewart, College Sex ‐ Philosophy for Everyone. Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 220–231.
    This chapter contains sections titled: An Authentic Self College, the Place to Feel Inadequate about Sex The Look The Nature of College Sex Bad Faith or True Desire.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  46
    Wittgenstein’s Comparison between Philosophy, Aesthetics and Ethics.Oskari Kuusela - 2017 - In Anja Weiberg & Stefan Majetschak, Aesthetics Today: Contemporary Approaches to the Aesthetics of Nature and of Arts. Proceedings of the 39th International Wittgenstein Symposium in Kirchberg. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 333-348.
    Wittgenstein compares philosophical explanations with explanations in aesthetics and ethics. According to him, the similarity between aesthetics and philosophy ‘reaches very far’, and as I aim to show, the comparison can be used to elucidate certain characteristic features of Wittgenstein’s philosophical approach. In particular, it can explain how his approach differs from metaphysical philosophy as well as clarifying the sense in which there are no theses or theories in philosophy, as Wittgenstein conceives it. In the last section of the essay, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  7
    Carnap and Wittgenstein: Tolerance, Arbitrariness, and Truth.Oskari Kuusela - 2024 - Philosophies 9 (4):114.
    This article discusses the relationship between Ludwig Wittgenstein’s and Rudolf Carnap’s philosophies of logic during the time of Wittgenstein’s interactions with the Vienna Circle and up to 1934 when the German edition of Carnap’s _The Logical Syntax of Language_ was published. Whilst Section 1 focuses on the relationship between Carnap and Wittgenstein’s _Tractatus_, including Wittgenstein’s accusation of plagiarism against Carnap in 1932, Section 2 discusses the relationship between Carnap’s principle of tolerance and Wittgenstein’s similar principle of the arbitrariness of grammar. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  38
    The Problem of Domination by Reason and Its Non-Relativistic Solution.Oskari Kuusela - 2019 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 8:23-42.
    This paper outlines a solution to what can be called “the problem of domination by reason”, “conceptual domination” or “clarificatorory injustice”, connected with how a philosopher may appear to be in a position to legitimately coerce, by means of arguments, an interlocutor who shares with her a concept or a conceptual system to accept a philosophical characterization of a concept or whatever the concept concerns. The proposed solution is based on a particular interpretation of what Wittgenstein means by agreement in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  26
    Wittgenstein’s Tractatus without paradox.Oskari Kuusela - 2022 - Revista de Filosofia Aurora 34 (63).
    This article proposes an interpretation of Wittgenstein’s so-called picture theory of propositions that forgoes the attribution of unsayable truths or theses to the Tractatus. Consequently, the interpretation avoids describing the Tractatus as entangled in a paradox of nonsensical theses. Rather, I argue, the proper expression for Wittgenstein’s logical insights is a logical symbolism into whose structure they are encoded. This also applies to his account of propositions as pictures. Its purpose is to clarify the principles governing a correct logical language (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. The problem of dogmatism.Oskari Kuusela - 2009 - The Philosophers' Magazine 44 (44):36-41.
    Wittgenstein’s rejection of philosophical theories doesn’t mean that he, or whoever adopts his method, couldn’t have any positive views about the objects of philosophical investigation. It merely means not presenting those views in a dogmatic manner, as theses that all relevant cases must fit. Wittgenstein’s approach allows one not to take sides in philosophical disputes and to take on board whatever might be correct in the traditional theories.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Tractatus' Failure.Oskari Kuusela - unknown
    In this paper I discuss the role of the nonsensical ‘statements’ of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus and the aims of the book, a topic which has in recent years been the subject of, at times heated, controversy among Wittgenstein’s readers.1 In this debate the so-called ineffability interpretation argues that the role of nonsense in the Tractatus is to make us grasp ineffable truths which ‘strictly speaking’ cannot be said or thought2. By contrast, the interpretation known as the resolute reading emphasises the incomprehensibility (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  35
    The Methodological Significance of Intuitions in Philosophy.Oskari Kuusela - 2019 - In James Conant & Sebastian Sunday, Wittgenstein on Philosophy, Objectivity, and Meaning. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 62-83.
    This chapter discusses the methodological and epistemological significance of so-called intuitions in philosophy; that is, whether intuitions can be understood as evidence for or against philosophical claims or, if not, whether they might have some other kind of methodological significance. A closely connected issue which the chapter addresses, is whether our comprehension of logical, conceptual, or metaphysical possibilities and necessities can be explained by reference to intuitions or the capacity of intuition or, if not, how our capacity to understand such (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  29
    Wittgenstein’s Investigations: Awakening the Imagination by Beth Savickey.Oskari Kuusela - 2020 - Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 1 (1):86-92.
    A book review of Beth Savickey. Wittgenstein’s Investigations: Awakening the Imagination. Cham: Springer, 2017, 137 pp. ISBN 978-3-319-45308-8.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Wittgenstein's reception of Socrates.Oskari Kuusela - 2019 - In Christopher Moore, Brill's Companion to the Reception of Socrates. Leiden: Brill.
    A main theme of this chapter is Ludwig Wittgenstein’s critical reception of Socrates in the 1930s, during which time Wittgenstein was developing a new philosophical methodology that he described as being antithetical to that of Socrates and best explained by way of this contrast. In particular, Wittgenstein is critical of an unexamined assumption relating to conceptual unity that seems to inform Socrates’ philosophical engagements, according to which one can always define a concept, or cases that fall under it, with reference (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  86
    Wittgenstein and His Interpreters: Essays in Memory of Gordon Baker.Guy Kahane, Edward Kanterian & Oskari Kuusela (eds.) - 2007 - Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Comprising specially commissioned essays from some of the most significant contributors to the field, this volume provides a uniquely authoritative and thorough survey of the main lines of Wittgenstein scholarship over the past 50 years, tracing the history and current trends as well as anticipating the future shape of work on Wittgenstein. The first collection of its kind, this volume presents a range of perspectives on the different approaches to the philosophy of Wittgenstein Written by leading experts from America, Britain, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  25.  39
    Perspectives on Wittgenstein: an intermittently opinionated survey.Hans Johann Glock, G. Kahane, E. Kanterian & O. Kuusela - 2007 - In [no title]. pp. 37-65.
  26. Engaging Kripke with Wittgenstein: the standard metre, contingent apriori, and beyond.Martin Gustafsson, Oskari Kuusela & Jakub Mácha (eds.) - 2024 - New York, NY: Routledge.
    This volume draws connections between Wittgenstein's philosophy and the work of Saul Kripke, especially his Naming and Necessity. Saul Kripke is regarded as one of the foremost representatives of contemporary analytic philosophy. His most important contributions include the strict distinction between metaphysical and epistemological questions, the introduction of the notions of contingent a priori truth and necessary a posteriori truth and original accounts of names, descriptions, identity, necessity and realism. The chapters in this book elucidate the relevant connections between Kripke's (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Overlooked distinctions : the mirage of contingent A priori.Oskari Kuusela - 2024 - In Martin Gustafsson, Oskari Kuusela & Jakub Mácha, Engaging Kripke with Wittgenstein: the standard metre, contingent apriori, and beyond. New York, NY: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  68
    The Method of Language-Games as a Method of Logic.Oskari Kuusela - 2014 - Philosophical Topics 42 (2):129-160.
    This paper develops an account of Wittgenstein’s method of language-games as a method of logic that exhibits important continuities with Russell’s and the early Wittgenstein’s conceptions of logic and logical analysis as the method of philosophy. On the proposed interpretation, the method of language-games is a method for isolating and modeling aspects of the uses of linguistic expressions embedded in human activities that enables one to make perspicuous complex uses of expressions by gradually building up the complexity of clarificatory models. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  29.  80
    Do the concepts of grammar and use in Wittgenstein articulate a theory of language or meaning?Oskari Kuusela - 2006 - Philosophical Investigations 29 (4):309–341.
    The paper elucidates Wittgenstein's later conception of philosophy as devoid of theories or theses, comprehending this as an articulation of a strategy for avoiding dogmatism in philosophy. More specifically, it clarifies Wittgenstein's conception by using what he says about the concepts of meaning and language as an example and by developing an interpretation that purports to make plain that what Wittgenstein says about these issues does not constitute a philosophical thesis. Adopting Wittgenstein's approach, we can, arguably, have a richer view (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. Overlooked distinctions : the mirage of contingent A priori.Oskari Kuusela - 2024 - In Martin Gustafsson, Oskari Kuusela & Jakub Mácha, Engaging Kripke with Wittgenstein: the standard metre, contingent apriori, and beyond. New York, NY: Routledge.
    In this paper I argue, with reference to Wittgenstein’s discussion of the standard metre in the Philosophical Investigations, that Kripke’s introduction of the epistemological-metaphysical category of contingent a priori in Naming and Necessity fails, due to his overlooking certain important distinctions in the use of relevant expressions and due to his unrecognized or unacknowledged wavering between different uses of relevant sentences. If the argument is correct, the notion of contingent a priori truths that Kripke seeks to introduce is merely a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  57
    On Wittgenstein's and Carnap's Conceptions of the Dissolution of Philosophical Problems, and against a Therapeutic Mix: How to Solve the Paradox of the Tractatus.Oskari Kuusela - 2019 - Philosophical Investigations 42 (3):213-240.
    In this article, I distinguish Wittgenstein's conception of the dissolution of philosophical problems from that of Carnap. I argue that the conception of dissolution assumed by the therapeutic interpretations of the Tractatus is more similar to Carnap's than to Wittgenstein's for whom dissolution involves spelling out an alternative in the context of which relevant problems do not arise. To clarify this I outline a non‐therapeutic resolute reading of the Tractatus that explains how Wittgenstein thought to be able to make a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  80
    Iris Murdoch, Philosopher: A Collection of Essays, edited by Justin Broackes. [REVIEW]Silvia Panizza & Oskari Kuusela - 2015 - Mind 124 (496):1249-1254.
  33.  50
    H. Poon An James E. Mcc finnell.E. James - 2004 - In Antoine Bailly & Lay James Gibson, Applied Geography: A World Perspective. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 77--253.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Louis Couturat et les mathématiques de son époque.Jean Dieudonnée - 1983 - In Louis Couturat, L'oeuvre de Louis Couturat (1868-1914): de Leibniz à Russell. Paris: Rue d'Ulm.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Relações biológicas entre populações indígenas atuais e pré-históricas do Brasil.Marília Carvalho de Mello E. Alvim & Smfm De Sousa - 1990 - Clio: A Journal of Literature, History, and the Philosophy of History 1 (6):69-79.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Comemorações: usos do passado e do presente na construção da nação.Noé Freire Sandes E. Élio Cantalício Serpa - 2007 - In Elio Cantalício Serpa & Marcos Antonio de Menezes, Escritas da história: narrativa, arte e nação. Uberlândia, Minas Gerais: EDUFU.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Intersecções nos estudos sobre trajetórias e identidades.Cidriana Parenza E. Gisele Giuriolo - 2010 - In Naira Lisboa Franzoi, Trabalho, trabalhadores e educação: conjeturas e reflexões. Porto Alegre: Editora Evangraf.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  57
    Light, Pressure, and Rectilinear Propagation: Descartes' Celestial Optics and Newton's Hydrostatics.Alan E. Shapiro - 1974 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 5 (3):239.
  39.  25
    Locke and Scholasticism.E. J. Ashworth - 2015 - In Matthew Stuart, A Companion to Locke. Chichester, West Sussex, UK: Blackwell. pp. 82–99.
    This chapter focuses on John Locke's relation to scholasticism. It explores who the schoolmen referred to by Locke were, and what he might have learned from them, particularly with respect to topics in metaphysics, logic, and language. The chapter considers the Oxford curriculum which provided the framework for Locke's years of study and teaching there, as there is little reason to believe that he enriched his acquaintance with the schoolmen in his later career. The topic of substance was raised both (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  86
    The Interpretation of Galilean Science: Cassirer Contrasted with Husserl and Heidegger.Lawrence E. Cahoone - 1986 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 17 (1):1.
  41.  71
    The Newtonian Myth.E. B. Davies - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (4):763-780.
    I examine Popper’s claims about Newton’s use of induction in Principia with the actual contents of Principia and draw two conclusions. Firstly, in common with most other philosophers of his generation, it appears that Popper had very little acquaintance with the contents and methodological complexities of Principia beyond what was in the famous General Scholium. Secondly Popper’s ideas about induction were less sophisticated than those of Newton, who recognised that it did not provide logical proofs of the results obtained using (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42. Language and Meaning.E. J. Lowe - 2015 - In Matthew Stuart, A Companion to Locke. Chichester, West Sussex, UK: Blackwell. pp. 279-295.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  13
    Music and psychology.E. Clarke - 2003 - In Martin Clayton, Trevor Herbert & Richard Middleton, The Cultural Study of Music: A Critical Introduction. Routledge. pp. 113--123.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  17
    Methodology and the emergence of physiological chemistry.E. Glas - 1978 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 9 (4):291-312.
  45. Matthew 25:14–30.E. Carson Brisson - 2002 - Interpretation: A Journal of Bible and Theology 56 (3):307-310.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Matthew 28:1–10.E. Carson Brisson - 2011 - Interpretation: A Journal of Bible and Theology 65 (1):72-74.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Ecclesiastes 3:1–8.E. Carson Brisson - 2001 - Interpretation: A Journal of Bible and Theology 55 (3):292-295.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Luke 24:13–35.E. Harold Breitenberg - 2010 - Interpretation: A Journal of Bible and Theology 64 (1):74-76.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  63
    Essays in the history of mechanics.E. J. Aiton - 1970 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 1 (3):265-273.
  50. EL, and Bandman, B.E. Bandman - forthcoming - Bioethics and Human Rights: A Reader for Health Professionals.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 964