Results for 'Aristotelian materialism'

949 found
Order:
  1. Aristotelian materialism.L. S. Carrier - 2006 - Philosophia 34 (3):253-266.
    I argue that a modern gloss on Aristotle’s notions of Form and Matter not only allows us to escape a dualism of the psychological and the physical, but also results in a plausible sort of materialism. This is because Aristotle held that the essential nature of any psychological state, including perception and human thought, is to be some physical property. I also show that Hilary Putnam and Martha Nussbaum are mistaken in saying that Aristotle was not a materialist, but (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  57
    Aristotelian Hylomorphism and Non-Reductive Materialism.John Mouracade - 2008 - Apeiron 41 (3):153-178.
  3. Historical Materialism, Ideological Illusion, and the Aristotelian Heart of Marx’s Condemnation of Capitalism.Andrew N. Carpenter - 2013 - Studia Philosophica Wratislaviensia 8.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Pregnant Materialist Natural Law: Bloch and Spartacus’s Priestess of Dionysus.Joshua M. Hall - 2022 - Idealistic Studies 52 (2):111-132.
    In this article, I explore two neglected works by the twentieth-century Jewish German Marxist philosopher Ernst Bloch, Avicenna and the Aristotelian Left and Natural Law and Human Dignity. Drawing on previous analyses of leftist Aristotelians and natural law, I blend Bloch’s two texts’ concepts of pregnant matter and maternal law into “pregnant materialist natural law.” More precisely, Aristotelian Left articulates a concept of matter as a dynamic, impersonal agential force, ever pregnant with possible forms delivered by artist-midwives, building (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  15
    Unitarian materialism. Christoph Stegmann, Joseph Priestley, and their concepts of matter and soul.Sascha Salatowsky - 2020 - Intellectual History Review 30 (1):7-29.
    This paper describes the affinities between Socinian and Unitarian materialism. Based on different philosophical traditions, the Socinian Christoph Stegmann and the Unitarian Joseph Priestley developed a strong “system of materialism” which fit very well with Christian doctrines and the Bible. The conviction that the whole man is material and therefore mortal became the common basis for these radical thinkers. Stegmann formulated within the Aristotelian tradition a “non-reductive” materialism in which matter, not form, became the fundamental principle (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  65
    XI—Materialism and Immaterialism.M. J. Budd - 1970 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 70 (1):197-220.
    M. J. Budd; XI—Materialism and Immaterialism, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 70, Issue 1, 1 June 1970, Pages 197–220, https://doi.org/10.1093/a.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  18
    Epicurean Materialism.Alexander Bown - 2023 - In David Charles, The History of Hylomorphism: From Aristotle to Descartes. New York, NY, United States of America: Oxford University Press. pp. 44-68.
    My aim in this chapter is to present the fundamentals of Epicurus’ views on physics and ontology and to raise some questions that a competitor to Aristotelian hylomorphism ought to be able to handle. In section 1, I present the basic ontological framework; in section 2, I introduce atoms, which most closely correspond in Epicurus’ system to Aristotelian matter, and show how he attempted to account for some phenomenal and psychological properties of compound bodies by appealing just to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  24
    Atheist Therapy: Radical Embodiment in Early Modern Medical Materialism.Charles Wolfe - forthcoming - Diametros:1-16.
    Materialism as a doctrine is, of course, a part of the history of philosophy, even if it was often a polemical construct, and it took until the 18th century for philosophers to be willing to call themselves materialists. Difficulties also have been pointed out in terms of “continuity,” i.e., does what Democritus, Lucretius, Hobbes and Diderot have to say about matter, the body and the soul all belong in one discursive and conceptual frame? Interestingly, materialism is also a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Zombies v. Materialists.Robert Kirk & J. E. R. Squires - 1974 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 48 (1):135-164.
  10.  24
    Transcendental naturalism and skeptical materialism.David A. Dilworth - 2022 - Cognitio 23 (1):59920-59920.
    The article begins with a comparative hermeneutic of the incongruent legacy worldviews of Emerson’s transcendentalism and Santayana’s skeptical materialism, proceeds on to Peirce’s convergence with Emerson’s transcendentalism in a neo- Neoplatonic and neo-Aristotelian configuration, with particular reference to the sweep of the Cambridge Conference Lectures of 1898.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  8
    Politics of Materialism in Thomas Hobbes.David Emanuel De Souza Coelho - 2022 - Revista de Filosofia Moderna E Contemporânea 10 (2):199-222.
    Hobbes makes a new interpretation about politics backgrounded in full materialistic conception. His materialistic ontology denies the separate essences from the traditional metaphysics and denies the Aristotelian idea of politics as essential nature of humanity. Unlike this view, Hobbes shows that the politics is created by human beings from the power fight and power is a way of satisfying the human desires by synthetized objects and relations. In this way, politics aims to satisfy concrete human needs and the power (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  60
    Symposium: Materialism in the Light of Modern Scientific Thought.L. J. Russell, L. S. Stebbing & A. E. Heath - 1928 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 8 (1):99 - 142.
  13. Materialism and Phenomenal Qualities.Les Holborow & David Mellor - 1973 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 47 (1):87-120.
  14. Zombies v. Materialists.Robert Kirk & Roger Squires - 1974 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 48:135-163.
  15. An Augustinian philosopher between dualism and materialism: Ernan McMullin on human emergence.Paul L. Allen - 2013 - Zygon 48 (2):294-304.
    In claiming the independence of theology from science, Ernan McMullin nevertheless saw the danger of separating these disciplines on questions of mutual significance, as his accompanying article “Biology and the Theology of the Human” in this edition of Zygon shows. This paper analyzes McMullin's adoption of emergence as a qualified endorsement of a view that avoids the excesses of both dualism and materialism. I argue that McMullin's distinctive contribution is the conceptual clarification of emergence in the light of a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  38
    III.—The New Materialism.C. A. Richardson - 1921 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 21 (1):51-70.
  17.  19
    A Modern Materialist: A Study of the Philosophy of George Santayana.D. L. Murray - 1912 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 12:294 - 325.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  27
    XI.—The Materialist Conception of History.H. B. Acton - 1952 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 52 (1):207-224.
  19.  12
    Chapter Six. Thought and Materialism.Edwin Hartman - 1977 - In Substance, Body and Soul: Aristotelian Investigations. Princeton University Press. pp. 220-270.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  11
    Chapter Five. Perception and Materialism.Edwin Hartman - 1977 - In Substance, Body and Soul: Aristotelian Investigations. Princeton University Press. pp. 167-219.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  16
    Avicenna and the Aristotelian left.Ernst Bloch - 2018 - New York: Columbia University Press.
    Ernst Bloch gives a striking account of materialism that traces emancipatory elements of modern thought to medieval Islamic philosophers' encounter with Aristotle. He argues that the great medieval Islamic philosopher Avicenna (Ibn Sina) planted the seeds of a radical materialism still relevant for critical theory today.
  22.  65
    An Aristotelian-Thomistic Approach to Management Practice.Surendra Arjoon - 2010 - Philosophy of Management 9 (2):47-64.
    Every academic endeavour rests ultimately on a particular assumption of human nature. Two views of human nature are compared and contrasted: (1) a utilitarian naturalistic humanism which holds essentially the view that human nature is materialistic, and (2) an Aristotelian-Thomistic natural law/virtue ethics humanism which holds the view that human nature is both materialistic and spiritualistic. This paper argues that the latter view better captures and explains the metaphysical realities of human nature. In addition, the role of virtues and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  57
    On Some Criticisms of Historical Materialism.Gerald A. Cohen & H. B. Acton - 1970 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 44 (1):121-156.
  24.  14
    Chapter Four. The Heart, the Soul, and Materialism.Edwin Hartman - 1977 - In Substance, Body and Soul: Aristotelian Investigations. Princeton University Press. pp. 131-166.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  33
    Symposium: The New Physics and Metaphysical Materialism.L. Susan Stebbing, J. H. Jeans, R. B. Braithwaite & E. T. Whittaker - 1943 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 43:167 - 214.
  26.  65
    Aristotelian Metaphysics and the Distinction between Consciousness and the Real World in Husserl and Ingarden.Jeff Mitscherling - 2010 - Polish Journal of Philosophy 4 (2):137-156.
    While Ingarden makes only infrequent reference to Aristotle, The Philosopher’s presence can be discerned throughout his published works. Perhaps mostsignificantly, when Ingarden returned to work on Controversy over the Existence of the World in 1938, he immersed himself in the study of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, and the entire framework of Controversy appears to have been inspired by reflection on central Aristotelian concepts. Ingarden’s understanding of the Aristotelian conception of the relation between form and matter, and indeed the Aristotelian (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  39
    VIII.—Symposium: The New Physics and Metaphysical Materialism.L. Susan Stebbing, J. H. Jeans, R. B. Braithwaite & E. T. Whittaker - 1943 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 43 (1):167-184.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  30
    Political friendship, respect, community: Hannah Arendt’s de-materialization of Aristotelian political friendship.Alex Cain - forthcoming - Philosophy and Social Criticism.
    In this article I demonstrate how Hannah Arendt both appropriates and transforms Aristotle’s view of political friendship. I argue that the brief discussion of Aristotelian political friendship in The Human Condition relies on an earlier de-materialization of Aristotle’s work on friendship. This de-materialization of Aristotle’s view of friendship allows Arendt to discuss Aristotelian friendship as a kind of ‘respect’, where ‘respect’ is a philosophical notion unavailable to Aristotle. Ultimately, for Arendt, the experience of friendship opens up a space (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Measuring the Immeasurable Mind: Where Contemporary Neuroscience Meets the Aristotelian Tradition.Matthew Owen - 2021 - Lexington Books (Rowman & Littlefield).
    In Measuring the Immeasurable Mind: Where Contemporary Neuroscience Meets the Aristotelian Tradition, Matthew Owen argues that despite its nonphysical character, it is possible to empirically detect and measure consciousness. -/- Toward the end of the previous century, the neuroscience of consciousness set its roots and sprouted within a materialist milieu that reduced the mind to matter. Several decades later, dualism is being dusted off and reconsidered. Although some may see this revival as a threat to consciousness science aimed at (...)
  30.  45
    The Mechanization of Aristotelianism: The Late Aristotelian Setting of Thomas Hobbes' Natural Philosophy. [REVIEW]George Wright - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (1):101-103.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 42.1 (2004) 101-103 [Access article in PDF] Cees Leijenhorst. The Mechanization of Aristotelianism: The Late Aristotelian Setting of Thomas Hobbes' Natural Philosophy. Leiden: Brill, 2002. Pp. xv + 242. Cloth, $97.00. Cees Leijenhorst, the young Dutch scholar and student of the late Karl Schuhmann, has written the most important book on Thomas Hobbes's natural science since Frithiof Brandt's Thomas Hobbes's Mechanical Conception (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. The ontological and epistemological superiority of hylomorphism.Robert C. Koons - 2017 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 3):885-903.
    Materialism—the view that all of reality is wholly determined by the very, very small—and extreme nominalism—the view that properties, kinds, and qualities do not really exist—have been the dominant view in analytic philosophy for the last 100 years or so. Both views, however, have failed to provide adequate accounts for the possibility of intentionality and of knowledge. We must therefore look to alternatives. One well-tested alternative, the hylomorphism of Aristotle and the medieval scholastics, was rejected without being refuted and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  32. Thomas Hobbes.Stewart Duncan - 2009 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679), whose current reputation rests largely on his political philosophy, was a thinker with wide ranging interests. In philosophy, he defended a range of materialist, nominalist, and empiricist views against Cartesian and Aristotelian alternatives. In physics, his work was influential on Leibniz, and lead him into disputes with Boyle and the experimentalists of the early Royal Society. In history, he translated Thucydides's History of the Peloponnesian War into English, and later wrote his own history of the Long (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33.  24
    Hegel's Solution to the Mind‐Body Problem.Richard Dien Winfield - 2011 - In Stephen Houlgate & Michael Baur, A Companion to Hegel. Malden, MA: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 225–242.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Traditional Dilemma Beyond Mind‐Body Dualisms The Failed Remedies of Spinoza and Materialist Reductions Dilemmas of the Aristotelian Solution Hegel's Conceptual Breakthrough for Comprehending the Nondualist Relation of Mind and Body Limits of Searle's Parallel Proposal The Self‐Development of Embodied Mind.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Brentano's Argument against Aristotle for the Immateriality of the Soul.Susan Krantz - 1988 - Brentano Studien 1:63-74.
    The Aristotelian conception of the soul as Brentano understood it is examined, with respect to the nature of the soul and mainly to what Aristotle called the sensitive soul, since this is where the issue of the soul's corporeity becomes important. Secondly the difficulties are discussed which Brentano saw in the Aristotelian semi-materialistic conception concerning the intellectual, as distinct from the sensitive soul from Brentano's reistic point of view which and that it is an immaterial substance. Finally there (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. Aristotle and Agent-Directed Neuroplasticity.Eric Larock - 2013 - International Philosophical Quarterly 53 (4):385-408.
    I propose an Aristotelian approach to agent causation that is consistent with the hypothesis of strong emergence. This approach motivates a wider ontology than materialism by maintaining (1) that the agent is generated by the brain without being reducible to it on grounds of the unity of experience and (2) that the agent possesses (formal) causal power to affect (i.e., mold, sculpt, or organize) the brain on grounds of agent-directed neuroplasticity. After providing recent empirical evidence for the strong (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  65
    Promises of Non/Living Monsters and Uncontainable Life.Marietta Radomska - 2018 - Somatechnics 8 (2):215-231.
    In the Western cultural imaginaries the monstrous is defined – following Aristotelian categorisations – by its excess, deficiency or displacement of organic matter. These characteristics come to the fore in the field of bioart: a current in contemporary art that involves the use of biological materials (various kinds of soma: cells, tissues, organisms), and scientific procedures, technologies, protocols, and tools. Bioartistic projects and objects not only challenge the conventional ideas of embodiment and bodily boundaries, but also explore the relation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37. A Personalistic Appraisal of Maslow’s Needs Theory of Motivation: From “Humanistic” Psychology to Integral Humanism.Alma Acevedo - 2018 - Journal of Business Ethics 148 (4):741-763.
    Abraham Maslow’s needs theory is one of the most influential motivation theories in management and organizational behavior. What are its anthropological and ethical presuppositions? Are they consistent with sound business philosophy and ethics? This paper analyzes and assesses the anthropological and ethical underpinnings of Maslow’s needs theory from a personalistic framework, and concludes that they are flawed. Built on materialistic naturalism, the theory’s “humanistic” claims are subverted by its reductionist, individualistic approach to the human being, which ends up in a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  31
    Natural Philosophy: On Retrieving a Lost Disciplinary Imaginary by Alister E. McGRATH (review).Jack Zupko - 2023 - Review of Metaphysics 77 (1):158-159.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Natural Philosophy: On Retrieving a Lost Disciplinary Imaginary by Alister E. McGRATHJack ZupkoMcGRATH, Alister E. Natural Philosophy: On Retrieving a Lost Disciplinary Imaginary. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2023. viii + 248 pp. Cloth, $39.95This book attempts to retrieve and reimagine the tradition of natural philosophy as an antidote for what the author sees as the fragmented, instrumentalized, and ethically disengaged understanding of the natural world most of us (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Seele und Unsterblichkeitshoffnung.Edmund Runggaldier - 2008 - Theologie Und Philosophie 83 (4):562-573.
    Wie soll die Unsterlichkeitshoffnung gedeutet werden, um überhaupt konsistent sein zu können? Um die Frage zu klären, bezieht sich der Artikel auf den Substanzdualismus von R. Swinburne, die Constitution Theory von L. R. Baker, die christlichen Materialisten, den aristotelischen Hylemorphismus sowie die Seelen-Lehre von Thomas v. Aquin. Die thomanischen Prämissen legen nahe, Unsterblichkeit weder präsentistisch - als ständige Gegenwart - noch äternalistisch - als unendliche Erstreckung in der Zeit - zu verstehen, sondern als endgültige participatio an der Ewigkeit Gottes, die (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Whose History? Spinoza’s Critique of Religion As an Other Modernity.Idit Dobbs-Weinstein - 2003 - Idealistic Studies 33 (2-3):219-235.
    This paper discusses Spinoza's critique of religion as a visible moment of a radically occluded materialist Judeo-Arabic Aristotelian philosophical tradition. While the prevailing (Christo-Platonic) tradition begins with the familiar gesture to metaphysics as first philosophy, Spinoza's thought (and thus, this Other Tradition) takes politics as its point of departure with its concrete emphasis on a critique of dogma. This paper will show-by way of differing readings of Spinoza-how this materialist tradition becomes occluded by the prevailing tradition, even in the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. Spiritual Presence and Dimensional Space beyond the Cosmos.Hylarie Kochiras - 2012 - Intellectual History Review 22 (1):41-68.
    This paper examines connections between concepts of space and extension on the one hand and immaterial spirits on the other, specifically the immanentist concept of spirits as present in rerum natura. Those holding an immanentist concept, such as Thomas Aquinas, typically understood spirits non-dimensionally as present by essence and power; and that concept was historically linked to holenmerism, the doctrine that the spirit is whole in every part. Yet as Aristotelian ideas about extension were challenged and an actual, infinite, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42. Modern Physics and the Ontology of Events.Leemon McHenry - forthcoming - In James Bahoh & Marta Cassina, 21st-Century Philosophy of Events: Beyond the Analytic / Continental Divide. Edinburgh University Press.
    In this paper, I examine some of the most important theories of modern physics that support the notion that events are the basic ontological units of reality. The two main themes of this paper include: (1) physical evidence in support of an ontology of events, and (2) the increasing unification of physical theory until we arrive at the current state of two highly successful theories that are presently disunified within the search for a comprehensive, unified theory. With the revolutionary developments (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  24
    La ciencia lo dijo. Relaciones entre ciencia, razón y fe.Ignacio Sols - 2013 - Scientia et Fides 1 (1):87.
    After a description of the method of mathematics and empirical sciences, brief but explicit enough to show their limits with philosophical and theological reflection, I comment the harmonic relations of mutual help among them, and also, unfortunately, the historical occasions in which these limits have been trespassed. And after a fast view of the image of the world–matter and life–presented to us by nowadays established science, I recall the main items of opposition to faith posed by science, although sometimes just (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44. The Theologian's Doubts: Natural Philosophy and the Skeptical Games of Ghazali.Leor Halevi - 2002 - Journal of the History of Ideas 63 (1):19-39.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Theologian's Doubts:Natural Philosophy and the Skeptical Games of GhazālīLeor HaleviIn the history of skeptical thought, which normally leaps from the Pyrrhonists to the rediscovery of Sextus Empiricus in the sixteenth century, Abū Ḥāmid Muḥammad al-Ghazālī (1058-1111) figures as a medieval curiosity. Skeptical enough to merit passing acknowledgment, he has proven too baffling to be treated fully alongside pagan, atheist, or materialist philosophers. As a theologian defending certain Muslim (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45. Imagery and the Coherence of Imagination: A Critique of White.Nigel J. T. Thomas - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Research 22:95-127.
    Traditionally ‘imagination’ primarily denotes the faculty of mental imagery, other usages being derivative. However, contemporary philosophers commonly hold it to be a polysemous term, with several unrelated senses. This effectively eliminates this culturally important concept as an appropriate explanandum for science, and paves the way for a thoroughgoing eliminative materialism. White challenges both these views of imagination, arguing that ‘imagine’ never means ‘suppose,’ ‘believe,’ ‘pretend’ or ‘visualize,’ that imagery may occur without imagination, and that the true sense of ‘imagine’ (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  46.  34
    Marx’s Resurrection of Aristotle.Norman Levine - 2021 - Springer Verlag.
    This book seeks to show how Karl Marx’s vision of communism was a continuation of Aristotle’s classical humanist philosophy. Challenging the Engelsian distortion of Marx, it presents a negation of previous interpretations of Marx which present him in materialist terms. Engels proposed a picture of the highest stage of communist society as an economic egalitarianism, a vision which became an axiom of Leninist-Stalinist-Soviet Communism. By contrast, here it is shown that Marx embraced the Aristotelian concept of “distributive justice”, of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. Dismantling Bodily Resurrection Arguments Against Mind-Body Dualism.Brandon Rickabaugh - 2018 - In Loftin R. Keith & Farris Joshua, Christian Physicalism? Philosophical Theological Criticisms. Lexington. pp. 295-317.
    According to the Christian doctrine of bodily resurrection, human persons will have an embodied existence in eternity. Many Christian materialists, especially Lynne Rudder Baker, Trenton Merricks, and Kevin Corcoran, argue that the doctrine of bodily resurrection creates serious problems for substance dualism (dualism). These critiques argued that bodily resurrection is made trivial by dualism, that dualism makes it difficult if not impossible to explain why we need to be embodied, or that dualism should be rejected as bodily resurrection is better (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Is the Soul the Form of the Body?John Haldane - 2013 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 87 (3):481-493.
    The idea of the soul, though once common in discussions of human nature, is rarely considered in contemporary philosophy. This reflects a general physicalist turn; but besides commitment to various forms of materialism there is the objection that the very idea of the soul is incoherent. The notion of soul considered here is a broadly Aristotelian-Thomistic one according to which it is both the form of a living human being and something subsistent on its own account. Having discussed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  12
    The book of dead philosophers.Simon Critchley - 2008 - London: Granta.
    Pre-Socratics, physiologists, sages and sophists -- Platonists, Cyrenaics, Aristotelians and cynics -- Sceptics, stoics and epicureans -- Classical Chinese philosophers -- Romans (serious and ridiculous) and neoplatonists -- The deaths of Christian saints -- Medieval philosophers: Christian, Islamic, and Judaic -- Philosophy in the Latin Middle Ages -- Renaissance, Reformation and scientific revolution -- Rationalists (material and immaterial), empiricists and religious dissenters -- Philosophes, materialists and sentimentalists -- Many Germans and some non-Germans -- The masters of suspicion and some unsuspicious (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  20
    Simondon’s Heterodox Naturalism: Form, Information and Self-Organization in Imagination and Invention.Giovanni Menegalle - 2024 - Paragraph 47 (3):341-358.
    This article presents Simondon’s psycho-biological thinking as a type of heterodox naturalism centring on the self-organizing activity of vital forms. Despite his critique of classic notions of form, notably Aristotelian hylomorphism, Simondon revises this concept through a critical expansion and synthesis of information theory and Gestalt psychology. In his lecture series Imagination and Invention (1965–6) in particular, he develops an account of psycho-biological activity as governed by what he calls ‘images’: relatively autonomous informational sub-systems that serve to regulate the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 949