Results for 'least action'

941 found
Order:
  1.  50
    Dispositions and the Least Action Principle.Diego Maltrana & Federico Benitez - 2022 - Disputatio 14 (65):91-104.
    This work deals with obstacles hindering a metaphysics of laws of nature in terms of dispositions, i.e., of fundamental properties that are causal powers. A recent analysis of the principle of least action has put into question the viability of dispositionalism in the case of classical mechanics, generally seen as the physical theory most easily amenable to a dispositional ontology. Here, a proper consideration of the framework role played by the least action principle within the classical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. The principle of least action as the logical empiricist's shibboleth.Michael Stöltzner - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 34 (2):285-318.
    The present paper investigates why logical empiricists remained silent about one of the most philosophy-laden matters of theoretical physics of their day, the principle of least action (PLA). In the two decades around 1900, the PLA enjoyed a remarkable renaissance as a formal unification of mechanics, electrodynamics, thermodynamics, and relativity theory. Taking Ernst Mach's historico-critical stance, it could be liberated from much of its physico-theological dross. Variational calculus, the mathematical discipline on which the PLA was based, obtained a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  3.  46
    The principle of least action and teleological explanation in physics.David Glick - 2023 - Synthese 202 (1):1-15.
    The principle of least action (PLA) has often been cited as a counterexample to the dominant mode of causal explanation in physics. In particular, PLA seems to involve an appeal to final causes or some other teleological ideology. However, Ben-Menahem (Causation in science, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2018) argues that such implications no longer apply given that PLA can be recovered as limiting case from quantum theory. In this paper, I argue that the metaphysical implications of PLA-based explanations (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Dispositions and the principle of least action.J. Katzav - 2004 - Analysis 64 (3):206-214.
    My aim is to argue for the incompatibility of one of the central principles of physics, namely the principle of least action (PLA), with the increasingly popular view that the world is, ultimately, merely something like a con- glomerate of objects and irreducible dispositions. First, I argue that the essentialist implications many suppose this view has are not compatible with the PLA. Second, I argue that, irrespective of whether this view has any essentialist implications, it is not compatible (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  5.  58
    The principle of least action as a psychological principle.W. R. Boyce Gibson - 1900 - Mind 9 (36):469-495.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  35
    Between Old and New Teleology. Kant on Maupertuis’ Principle of Least Action.Rudolf Meer - 2022 - Open Philosophy 5 (1):265-280.
    In the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic, Kant formulates teleological principles, or rather ideas, and explicates them referring to concrete examples of natural science such as chemistry, astronomy, biology, empirical psychology, and physical geography. Despite the increasing interest in the systematic relevance of the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic and its importance for Kant’s conception of natural science, the numerous historical sources for the regulative use of reason have not yet been investigated. One that is very central is Maupertuis’ principle (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  8
    The “Tenderness” of the Principle of Least Action: From the Philosophy of Physics to the Paradigm for Sustainable Development.Мария Янушевна Мацевич - 2023 - Russian Journal of Philosophical Sciences 66 (3):122-159.
    The paper delves into the methodological aspects of how foundational mathematical and physical tenets, most notably the principle of least action, are interpreted and assimilated within humanities discourse. The pursuit of the article’s objectives is driven by the necessity for a philosophical and methodological analysis of the current conceptual status of the principle of least action. This analysis is informed by cognitive-axiological and teleological imperatives of a “synthetic” development program for the principle. Any fundamental principle will (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Metaphysics of the principle of least action.Vladislav Terekhovich - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 62:189-201.
    Despite the importance of the variational principles of physics, there have been relatively few attempts to consider them for a realistic framework. In addition to the old teleological question, this paper continues the recent discussion regarding the modal involvement of the principle of least action and its relations with the Humean view of the laws of nature. The reality of possible paths in the principle of least action is examined from the perspectives of the contemporary metaphysics (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  9.  69
    The Principle of Least Action.Philip E. B. Jourdain - 1912 - The Monist 22 (2):285-304.
  10.  11
    Eulers “Harmony” Between the Principles of “Rest” and “Least Action”: The Conceptual Making of Analytical Mechanics.Penha Maria Cardoso Dias - 1999 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 54 (1):67-86.
    In 1751, LEONHARD EULER established “harmony” between two principles that had been stated by PIERRE-LOUIS-MOREAU DE MAUPERTUIS a few years earlier. These principles are intended to be the foundations of Mechanics; they are the principle of rest and the principle of least action.My claim is that the way in which “harmony” is achieved sets the foundations of so called Analytical Mechanics: it discloses the physical bases of the general ideas, concepts, and motivations of the formalism. My paper intends (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Dispositions and the principle of least action revisited.Benjamin T. H. Smart & Karim P. Y. Thébault - 2015 - Analysis 75 (3):386-395.
    Some time ago, Joel Katzav and Brian Ellis debated the compatibility of dispositional essentialism with the principle of least action. Surprisingly, very little has been said on the matter since, even by the most naturalistically inclined metaphysicians. Here, we revisit the Katzav–Ellis arguments of 2004–05. We outline the two problems for the dispositionalist identified Katzav in his 2004 , and claim they are not as problematic for the dispositional essentialist at it first seems – but not for the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  12.  27
    Quantum Mechanics Based on an Extended Least Action Principle and Information Metrics of Vacuum Fluctuations.Jianhao M. Yang - 2024 - Foundations of Physics 54 (3):1-31.
    We show that the formulations of non-relativistic quantum mechanics can be derived from an extended least action principle. The principle can be considered as an extension of the least action principle from classical mechanics by factoring in two assumptions. First, the Planck constant defines the minimal amount of action a physical system needs to exhibit during its dynamics in order to be observable. Second, there is constant vacuum fluctuation along a classical trajectory. A novel method (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. The Principle of Least Action and the three orders of formal teleology in the'Physics'.M. Stoltzner - 2000 - Archives de Philosophie 63 (4):621-655.
  14. The Principle of Least Action as a Psychological Principle.W. R. Boyce-Gibson - 1901 - Philosophical Review 10:206.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  3
    Voltaire, Maupertuis and the 18th century debate on the principle of least action: scientific and extrascientific features.Roberto de Andrade Martins & Ana Paula Bispo da Silva - 2021 - Filosofia Unisinos 8 (2).
    Towards the middle of the 18th century, Pierre-Louis Moreau de Maupertuis proposed the “principle of least action” as a fundamental law of physics and as a proof of the existence of God. Samuel König and other contemporary authors criticized Maupertuis’ work. There ensued a fierce discussion concerning this subject, in which Leonhard Euler, the king Frédéric II of Prussia and Voltaire took part. This paper discusses that debate, emphasizing its extrascientific features and analyzing the interests that motivated the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Maupertuis, Euler, and the Leibnizian Metaphysics behind the Principle of Least Action.Ansgar Lyssy - 2022 - Oxford University Studies in the Enlightenment Series 2022:123–152.
    Maupertuis and Euler had an ambivalent and tense relationship to their Leibniz, especially concerning his grounding of physics in metaphysics. Consequently, this paper has two intersecting goals: first, it attempts to flesh out some aspects of the reception of Leibnizian thought in the context of Enlightenment physics, more precisely, in the deduction of the Principle of least action (henceforth PLA). Second, it also highlights a specific approach towards the intersection of physics and metaphysics that was championed by the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  39
    The Principle of Least Action.Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 2009 - In Timothy McGrew, Marc Alspector-Kelly & Fritz Allhoff (eds.), The philosophy of science: an historical anthology. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
  18.  49
    Pilot-Wave Quantum Theory in Discrete Space and Time and the Principle of Least Action.Janusz Gluza & Jerzy Kosek - 2016 - Foundations of Physics 46 (11):1502-1521.
    The idea of obtaining a pilot-wave quantum theory on a lattice with discrete time is presented. The motion of quantum particles is described by a \-distributed Markov chain. Stochastic matrices of the process are found by the discrete version of the least-action principle. Probability currents are the consequence of Hamilton’s principle and the stochasticity of the Markov process is minimized. As an example, stochastic motion of single particles in a double-slit experiment is examined.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  9
    Correction: Quantum Mechanics Based on an Extended Least Action Principle and Information Metrics of Vacuum Fluctuations.Jianhao M. Yang - 2024 - Foundations of Physics 54 (4):1-1.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. The tension between the mathematical and metaphysical strands of Maupertuis' Principle of Least Action.Yannick Van den Abbeel - 2017 - Noctua 4 (1-2):56-90.
    Without doubt, the principle of least action is a fundamental principle in classical mechanics. Contemporary physicists, however, consider the PLA as a purely mathematical principle – even an axiom which they cannot completely justify. Such an account stands in sharp contrast with the historical meaning of the PLA. When the principle was introduced in the 1740s, by Pierre-Louis Moreau de Maupertuis, its meaning was much more versatile. For Maupertuis the principle of least action signified that nature (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. From The Principle Of Least Action To The Conservation Of Quantum Information In Chemistry: Can One Generalize The Periodic Table?Vasil Penchev - 2019 - Chemistry: Bulgarian Journal of Science Education 28 (4):525-539.
    The success of a few theories in statistical thermodynamics can be correlated with their selectivity to reality. These are the theories of Boltzmann, Gibbs, end Einstein. The starting point is Carnot’s theory, which defines implicitly the general selection of reality relevant to thermodynamics. The three other theories share this selection, but specify it further in detail. Each of them separates a few main aspects within the scope of the implicit thermodynamic reality. Their success grounds on that selection. Those aspects can (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  76
    Maupertuis and the Principle of Least Action.Philip E. B. Jourdain - 1912 - The Monist 22 (3):414-459.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23. Principle of Least Action: Methodological Inversion of Dynamics.Hartmut Hecht - 1995 - In Heinz Lübbig (ed.), The Inverse Problem: Symposium Ad Memoriam Hermann von Helmholtz. Wiley-Vch. pp. 181.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Philosophical and Methodological Problems of the Principle of Least Action.Vladislav Terekhovich - 2013 - Dissertation, St. Petersburg State University, Russia
    Twenty extremal principles of the natural sciences are reformulated to the general ontological scheme. The hypothesis is substantiated that the unique role of the principle of least action is based on its probabilistic interpretation. It is shown how most of the variational principles can be reduced to the principle of maximal probability, which is based on a realistic interpretation of Feynman’s path integral method.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  36
    The role of metaphor and analogy in the birth of the principle of least action of maupertuis (1698-1759).Maria Feher - 1988 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 2 (2):175 – 188.
  26.  51
    The Nature and Validity of the Principle of Least Action.Philip E. B. Jourdain - 1913 - The Monist 23 (2):277-293.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  11
    The Nature And Validity Of The Principle Of Least Action By Ph. E. B. Jourdain. [REVIEW] J. - 1913 - Isis 1:278-279.
  28. From nature that economizes to generous forces: the principle of least action between mathematics and metaphysics, Maupertuis and Euler, 1740-1751. [REVIEW]Marco Panza - 1995 - Revue d'Histoire des Sciences 48 (4):435-520.
  29.  51
    Rethinking Affirmative Action: Problematising the “Least Privileged”.Bhagat Oinam - 2024 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 41 (2):225-240.
    Affirmative action as a state policy is one of the powerful ways of empowering the underprivileged in the society. While such a policy is aimed at lifting the economic and social condition of the underprivileged, this comes with acts that are discriminatory and exclusionary. Yet these acts are termed as positive discrimination. Certain sections of the society are excluded from having access to economic resources and opportunities, while these privileges are earmarked for another section of the society considered marginalized (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  25
    Action and Responsibility.Andrew Sneddon - 2006 - Springer.
    What makes an event count as an action? Typical answers appeal to the way in which the event was produced: e.g., perhaps an arm movement is an action when caused by mental states (in particular ways), but not when caused in other ways. I argue that this type of answer, which I call "productionism", is methodologically and substantially mistaken. In particular, productionist answers to this question tend to be either individualistic or foundationalist, or both, without explicit defence. Instead, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  95
    Joint actions, commitments and the need to belong.Víctor Fernández Castro & Elisabeth Pacherie - 2020 - Synthese 198 (8):7597-7626.
    This paper concerns the credibility problem for commitments. Commitments play an important role in cooperative human interactions and can dramatically improve the performance of joint actions by stabilizing expectations, reducing the uncertainty of the interaction, providing reasons to cooperate or improving action coordination. However, commitments can only serve these functions if they are credible in the first place. What is it then that insures the credibility of commitments? To answer this question, we need to provide an account of what (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32.  42
    Demonstrations as actions.Piotr Tomasz Makowski & Tadeusz Ciecierski - 2022 - Synthese 200 (6):1-25.
    This paper presents a dual intention model (DIM) of demonstrations as actions to show the agentive nature of demonstrations. According to the DIM, demonstrations are complex actions that contain as components at least three elements: an abductive intention, a deictic intention, and a basic ostensive act of indication. This paper unpacks these three components and discusses their roles from the viewpoint of the philosophy of action and the philosophy of language. It also shows how the DIM applies in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33. Ability, action, and causation: from pure ability to force.Eleni Staraki & Anastasia Giannakidou - unknown
    Abstract In this paper, we show that Greek distinguishes empirically ability as a precondition for action, and ability as initiating and sustaining force for action. In this latter case, the ability verb behaves like an action verb, and the sentence has the logical form of a causative structure φ CAUSE [BECOME ψ] (Dowty 1979). The distinction between ability as potential for action and ability as action itself has a venerable tradition that goes back to Aristotle, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  58
    Action for the sake of ...: Caring and the rationality of (social) action.Bennett W. Helm - 2002 - Analyse & Kritik 24 (2):189--208.
    My aim is to understand at least some of the non-instrumental reasons we can have for action in a way that can provide a satisfying non-egoist account of 'social actions' - actions undertaken for the sake of others. I do this in part by presenting, in terms of a discussion of the rationality of emotions, an account of what it is for something to have import to an agent . I then extend this account to include our caring (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Desire: Its Role in Practical Reason and the Explanation of Action.G. F. Schueler - 1995 - MIT Press.
    Does action always arise out of desire? G. F. Schueler examines this hotly debated topic in philosophy of action and moral philosophy, arguing that once two senses of "desire" are distinguished - roughly, genuine desires and pro attitudes - apparently plausible explanations of action in terms of the agent's desires can be seen to be mistaken. Desire probes a fundamental issue in philosophy of mind, the nature of desires and how, if at all, they motivate and justify (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  36.  38
    Comment: Do Emotions Influence Action? – Of Course, They Are Hypo-Phenomena of Motivation.Guido H. E. Gendolla - 2017 - Emotion Review 9 (4):348-350.
    The target articles in this special section shed new light on the old question whether and how emotions influence action. However, what is missing is a straightforward motivational analysis—considering what we have learned from the science of explaining the “why” and “how” of behavior. I posit that emotions can influence the motivation process and thus action by fulfilling at least three functions: First, being grounded in needs, experienced emotions can function as strong need-like motivational states. Second, anticipated (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  18
    Disciplinary Actions by State Professional Licensing Boards: Are They Fair?Cynthia L. Krom - 2019 - Journal of Business Ethics 158 (2):567-583.
    This study examines 14,900 disciplinary actions by the professional licensing boards for attorneys, CPAs, and physicians in four states from 2008 through 2014. It was found that both attorneys and physicians are disciplined at a rate at least seven times that of CPAs. While the majority of disciplinary actions are for misconduct directly related to the professional practice, nearly 14% of sanctions were the result of “social crimes” such as failure to pay child support or student loans, driving under (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  32
    ‘At least I have done something’: A qualitative study of women's social egg freezing experiences.Michiel De Proost, Gily Coene, Julie Nekkebroeck & Veerle Provoost - 2022 - Clinical Ethics 17 (4):425-431.
    Social egg freezing has become an expanding clinical practice and there is a growing body of empirical literature on women's attitudes and the sociocultural implications of this phenomenon. Yet, its impact remains subject to ethical controversy. This article reports on a qualitative study, drawing on 18 interviews with women who had elected to initiate at least one egg freezing cycle in Belgium. Our findings, facilitated by a ‘symbiotic empirical ethics’ approach, shed light on the concerns and perceptions that accompany (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. Intentional action, folk judgments, and stories: Sorting things out.Alfred R. Mele & Fiery Cushman - 2007 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31 (1):184–201.
    How are our actions sorted into those that are intentional and those that are not? The philosophical and psychological literature on this topic is livelier now than ever, and we seek to make a contribution to it here. Our guiding question in this article is easy to state and hard to answer: How do various factors— specifically, features of vignettes—that contribute to majority folk judgments that an action is or is not intentional interact in producing the judgment? In pursuing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  40.  72
    Pictures, action properties and motor related effects.Gabriele Ferretti - 2016 - Synthese 193 (12):3787-3817.
    The most important question concerning picture perception is: what perceptual state are we in when we see an object in a picture? In order to answer this question, philosophers have used the results of the two visual systems model, according to which our visual system can be divided into two streams, a ventral stream for object recognition, allowing one to perceive from an allocentric frame of reference, and a dorsal stream for visually guided motor interaction, thus allowing one to perceive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  41. Volition and basic action.Hugh McCann - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (4):451-473.
    The purpose of this paper is to defend the view that the bodily actions of men typicaly involve a mental action of voliton or willing, and that such mental acts are, in at least one important sense, the basic actions we perform when we do things like raise an arm, move a finger, or flex a muscle.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  42. The normativity of action.Mark Rowlands - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (3):401-416.
    The concept of action is playing an increasingly prominent role in attempts to explain how subjects can represent the world. The idea is that at least some of the role traditionally assigned to internal representations can, in fact, be played by the ability of subjects to act on the world, and the exercise of that ability on appropriate occasions. This paper argues that the appeal to action faces a serious dilemma. If the concept of action employed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  43.  24
    Ethical dilemmas and care actions in nurses providing palliative sedation.Sinyoung Kwon, Miyoung Kim & Sujin Choi - 2022 - Nursing Ethics 29 (5):1220-1230.
    Background Recently, palliative care is increasingly important, with an emphasis on the process of dying with dignity. However, nurses who care for such patients experience the associated ethical dilemmas. Objective To explore the meaning of nurses’ experiences in dealing with ethical dilemmas in relation to palliative sedation. Research design A qualitative research design was employed with a thematic analysis approach. Participants and research context Using purposive sampling, 15 nurses, working at palliative care units for at least 1 year, were (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Intentional action in ordinary language: core concept or pragmatic understanding?Fred Adams & Annie Steadman - 2004 - Analysis 64 (2):173-181.
    Among philosophers, there are at least two prevalent views about the core concept of intentional action. View I (Adams 1986, 1997; McCann 1986) holds that an agent S intentionally does an action A only if S intends to do A. View II (Bratman 1987; Harman 1976; and Mele 1992) holds that there are cases where S intentionally does A without intending to do A, as long as doing A is foreseen and S is willing to accept A (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  45.  27
    Actions, Agents, and Consequences.Re’em Segev - 2023 - Criminal Justice Ethics 42 (2):99-132.
    According to an appealing and common view, the moral status of an action – whether it is wrong, for example – is sometimes important in itself in terms of the moral status of other actions – especially those that respond to the original action. This view is especially influential with respect to the criminal law. It is accepted not only by legal moralists but also by adherents of the harm principle, for example. In this paper, I argue against (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  31
    Hateful Actions and Rational Agency.Mary Carman - 2022 - In Noell Birondo (ed.), The Moral Psychology of Hate. Lanham and London: Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 185-206.
    Philosophical discussions of hatred have tended to examine whether and when hatred can be morally or rationally justified. If hatred is rational, for instance, it might be because it is a fitting response to the given circumstances (Ben-Ze’ev 2000; Bell 2011). At the same time, hatred typically motivates action, and action of quite characteristic types. As Fischer et al. (2018) note, the so-called ‘emotivational’ goal of hatred appears to be not merely to hurt the target of hatred, but (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Parallels between joint action and biological individuality.Cedric Paternotte - 2015 - In Thomas Pradeu & Alexandre Guay (eds.), Individuals Across The Sciences. New York, État de New York, États-Unis: Oxford University Press.
    There exist many definitions of human joint action, or of what makes a group similar to an individual. However, they do not agree and are not directly reducible to each other. This multiplicity is due to a lack of constraints on them. I argue that they should at least meet an efficiency constraint: any account of joint action has to justify how it reliably leads agents to cooperation. One avenue consists in exploring the analogy between definitions of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Collective rational action: Is it possible?Jan van Eijck - unknown
    Individual rational action consists of (i) knowing what you want, (ii) taking proper steps to approach what you want as closely as possible, within the confines of the law. This one can learn, although some people are more skilled in it than others. Modern democracies are set up in such a way that they leave as much room as possible for individual rational action. Education for citizenship is sometimes taken to be: getting young citizens acquainted with the legal (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  35
    At least some electrophysiological and behavioural data cannot be reconciled with the planning–control model.P. Paolo Battaglini, Paolo Bernardis & Nicola Bruno - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (1):24-25.
    The planning/control distinction is an important tool in the study of sensorimotor transformations. However, published data from our laboratories suggest that, contrary to what is predicted by the proposed model, (1) structures in the superior parietal lobe of both monkeys and humans can be involved in movement planning; and (2) fast pointing actions can be immune to visual illusions even if they are performed without visual feedback. The planning–control model as proposed by Glover is almost certainly too schematic.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  15
    Joint Actions: We-Mode and I-Mode.Seumas Miller - 2023 - In Miguel Garcia-Godinez & Rachael Mellin (eds.), Tuomela on Sociality. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 59-78.
    Raimo Tuomela has a good deal to say about the we-mode and the I-mode in relation to joint actions and related phenomena. Moreover, he also invoked the notion of a pro-group I-mode. However, it is not always entirely clear what the basis of these distinctions is and whether, ultimately, the distinction between the we-mode and the pro-group I-mode can be satisfactorily made out. If not then, since pro-group I-mode is a species of I-mode, the fundamental distinction between we-mode and I-mode (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 941