Results for 'shared representations'

977 found
Order:
  1.  52
    Shared Representations as Coordination Tools for Interaction.Giovanni Pezzulo - 2011 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2 (2):303-333.
    Why is interaction so simple? This article presents a theory of interaction based on the use of shared representations as “coordination tools” (e.g., roundabouts that facilitate coordination of drivers). By aligning their representations (intentionally or unintentionally), interacting agents help one another to solve interaction problems in that they remain predictable, and offer cues for action selection and goal monitoring. We illustrate how this strategy works in a joint task (building together a tower of bricks) and discuss its (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  2. Shared Representations, Perceptual Symbols, and the Vehicles of Mental Concepts.Paweł Gładziejewski - 2013 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 20 (3-4):102-124.
    The main aim of this article is to present and defend a thesis according to which conceptual representations of some types of mental states are encoded in the same neural structures that underlie the first-personal experience of those states. To support this proposal here, I will put forth a novel account of the cognitive function played by ‘shared representations’ of emotions and bodily sensations, i.e. neural structures that are active when one experiences a mental state of a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  28
    Sharing representations and creating chances through cognitive niche construction. The role of affordances and abduction.L. Magnani & E. Bardone - 2008 - In S. Iwata, Y. Oshawa, S. Tsumoto, N. Zhong, Y. Shi & L. Magnani (eds.), Communications and Discoveries From Multidisciplinary Data. Springer. pp. 3--40.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  4. Umwelt or Umwelten? How should shared representation be understood given such diversity?Colin Allen - 2014 - Semiotica 2014 (198):137-158.
    It is a truism among ethologists that one must not forget that animals perceive and represent the world differently from humans. Sometimes this caution is phrased in terms of von Uexküll’s Umwelt concept. Yet it seems possible (perhaps even unavoidable) to adopt a common ontological framework when comparing different species of mind. For some purposes it seems sufficient to ­anchor comparative cognition in common-sense categories; bats echolocate insects (or a subset of them) after all. But for other purposes it seems (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  5.  26
    Comment: Getting Our Affect Together: Shared Representations as the Core of Empathy.Abigail A. Marsh - 2022 - Emotion Review 14 (3):184-187.
    Empathy is a construct that is notoriously difficult to define. Murphy and colleagues ( 2022 ) argue for leaning into the construct's inherent fuzziness and reverting to what they term a classical definition informed by the observations of philosophers and clinicians: as a dynamic, “unfolding process of imaginatively experiencing the subjective consciousness of another person, sensing, understanding, and structuring the world as if one were that person.” Although consistent with some historical conceptualizations, this definition risks incorporating so many processes it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  20
    Comment: Getting Our Affect Together: Shared Representations as the Core of Empathy.Abigail A. Marsh - 2022 - Emotion Review 14 (3):184-187.
    Empathy is a construct that is notoriously difficult to define. Murphy and colleagues ( 2022 ) argue for leaning into the construct's inherent fuzziness and reverting to what they term a classical definition informed by the observations of philosophers and clinicians: as a dynamic, “unfolding process of imaginatively experiencing the subjective consciousness of another person, sensing, understanding, and structuring the world as if one were that person.” Although consistent with some historical conceptualizations, this definition risks incorporating so many processes it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. Body image and body schema: The shared representation of body image and the role of dynamic body schema in perspective and imitation.Alessia Tessari & Anna M. Borghi - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (2):221-222.
    Our commentary addresses two issues that are not developed enough in the target article. First, the model does not clearly address the distinction among external objects, external body parts, and internal bodies. Second, the authors could have discussed further the role of body schema with regard to its dynamic character, and its role in perspective and in imitation.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  29
    Semantic and Perceptual Representations of Color: Evidence of a Shared Color-Naming Function.Bilge Sayim, Kimberly A. Jameson, Nancy Alvarado & Monika Szeszel - 2005 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 5 (3-4):427-486.
    Much research on color representation and categorization has assumed that relations among color terms can be proxies for relations among color percepts. We test this assumption by comparing the mapping of color words with color appearances among different observer groups performing cognitive tasks: an invariance of naming task; and triad similarity judgments of color term and color appearance stimuli within and across color categories. Observer subgroups were defined by perceptual phenotype and photopigment opsin genotype analyses. Results suggest that individuals rely (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  57
    (1 other version)Reduced shared emotional representations toward women revealing more skin.Carlotta Cogoni, Andrea Carnaghi & Giorgia Silani - forthcoming - Tandf: Cognition and Emotion:1-16.
  10.  26
    Sensitising Concept, Themata and Shareness: A Dialogical Perspective of Social Representations.Li Liu - 2004 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 34 (3):249-264.
    This article aims at clarifying some critical, yet under-explored, conceptual issues of social representations from a dialogical perspective. The article recasts the notion of social representations as a sensitising, rather than a definitive, concept, based on the distinction between dialogical and monological epistemologies. It is argued that the introduction of the concept of themata into the theory suggests the dialogical interdependence between common thinking and social morphology, between the genesis and structure of social representations, and between implicit (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  84
    What is Shared in Joint Action? Issues of Co-representation, Response Conflict, and Agent Identification.Dorit Wenke, Silke Atmaca, Antje Holländer, Roman Liepelt, Pamela Baess & Wolfgang Prinz - 2011 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2 (2):147-172.
    When sharing a task with another person that requires turn taking, as in doubles games of table tennis, performance on the shared task is similar to performing the whole task alone. This has been taken to indicate that humans co-represent their partner’s task share, as if it were their own. Task co-representation allows prediction of the other’s responses when it is the other’s turn, and leads to response conflict in joint interference tasks. However, data from our lab cast doubt (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  12.  32
    Joint Action: Mental Representations, Shared Information and General Mechanisms for Coordinating with Others.Cordula Vesper, Ekaterina Abramova, Judith Bütepage, Francesca Ciardo, Benjamin Crossey, Alfred Effenberg, Dayana Hristova, April Karlinsky, Luke McEllin, Sari R. R. Nijssen, Laura Schmitz & Basil Wahn - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
  13. Shared intentionality and the representation of groups; or, how to build a socially adept robot.Ben Phillips - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45.
    Pietraszewski provides a compelling case that representations of certain interaction-types are the “cognitive primitives” that allow all tokens of group-in-conflict to be represented within the mind. Here, I argue that the folk concept GROUP encodes shared intentions and goals as more central than these interaction-types, and that providing a computational theory of social groups will be more difficult than Pietraszewski envisages.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  43
    From language-specific to shared syntactic representations: The influence of second language proficiency on syntactic sharing in bilinguals.Sarah Bernolet, Robert J. Hartsuiker & Martin J. Pickering - 2013 - Cognition 127 (3):287-306.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15.  38
    Sharing the Light: Representations of Women and Virtue in Early China.Jane M. Geaney & Lisa Raphals - 2000 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 120 (1):140.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  16.  20
    What's Shared in Movement Kinematics: Investigating Co-representation of Actions Through Movement.Matilde Rocca & Andrea Cavallo - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  16
    Physician-reported characteristics, representations, and ethical justifications of shared decision-making practices in the care of paediatric patients with prolonged disorders of consciousness.Marta Fadda, Emiliano Albanese, Roberto Malacrida, Federica Merlo & Vinurshia Sellaiah - 2023 - BMC Medical Ethics 24 (1):1-13.
    BackgroundDespite consensus about the importance of implementing shared decision-making (SDM) in clinical practice, this ideal is inconsistently enacted today. Evidence shows that SDM practices differ in the degree of involvement of patients or family members, or in the amount of medical information disclosed to patients in order to “share” meaningfully in treatment decisions. Little is known on which representations and moral justifications physicians hold when realizing SDM. This study explored physicians’ experiences of SDM in the management of paediatric (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Sharing the Light: Representations of Women and Virtue in Early China, by Lisa Raphals.L. Li-Hsiang - 2000 - Philosophy East and West 50 (1):149-152.
  19.  15
    Deep learning of shared perceptual representations for familiar and unfamiliar faces: Reply to commentaries.Nicholas M. Blauch, Marlene Behrmann & David C. Plaut - 2021 - Cognition 208 (C):104484.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  51
    Neural Representations Beyond “Plus X”.Vivian Cruz & Alessio Plebe - 2018 - Minds and Machines 28 (1):93-117.
    In this paper we defend structural representations, more specifically neural structural representation. We are not alone in this, many are currently engaged in this endeavor. The direction we take, however, diverges from the main road, a road paved by the mathematical theory of measure that, in the 1970s, established homomorphism as the way to map empirical domains of things in the world to the codomain of numbers. By adopting the mind as codomain, this mapping became a boon for all (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  79
    Lessons from Galileo: The pragmatic model of shared characteristics of scientific representation.Steffen Ducheyne - 2005 - Philosophia Naturalis 42 (2):213-234.
    In this paper I will defend a new account of scientific representation. I will begin by looking at the benefits and drawbacks of two recent accounts on scientific representation: Hughes’ DDI account and Suárez’ inferential account. Next I use some of Galileo’s models in the Discorsi as a heuristic tool for a better account of scientific representation. Next I will present my model. The main idea of my account, which I refer to as the pragmatic model of shared characteristics (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  51
    Facing the mirror: A relativist account of immune nonconceptual self-representations.Jérémie Lafraire - 2017 - Philosophical Psychology 30 (1-2):140-160.
    There is a consensus among philosophers that some “I”-thoughts are immune to error through misidentification. In some recent papers, this property has been formulated in the following deflationist way: an “I”-thought is immune to error through misidentification when it can misrepresent the mental or bodily property self-ascribed but cannot misrepresent the subject possessing that property. However, it has been put forward that the range of mental and bodily states that are immune in that limited sense cannot include nonconceptual forms of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  50
    Shared Memory, Odours and Sociotransmitters or: "Save the Interaction!".Joël Candau - 2010 - Outlines. Critical Practice Studies 12 (2):29-42.
    Collective memory, social memory, professional memory: although these notions are in current use when we name the shared (or assumed to be shared) representations of the past, they are very ambiguous. The point at issue is to show how memories can become common to some or to all members of a group . In this paper, I shall base my arguments on the simplest situation imaginable: The sharing of a memory of an olfactory experience by two individuals, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Analog Representation and the Parts Principle.John Kulvicki - 2015 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (1):165-180.
    Analog representation is often cast in terms of an engineering distinction between smooth and discrete systems. The engineering notion cuts across interesting representational categories, however, so it is poorly suited to thinking about kinds of representation. This paper suggests that analog representations support a pattern of interaction, specifically open-ended searches for content across levels of abstraction. They support the pattern by sharing a structure with what they represent. Continuous systems that satisfy the engineering notion are exemplars of this kind (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  25.  31
    The Development of Shared Liking of Representational but not Abstract Art in Primary School Children and Their Justifications for Liking.Paul Rodway, Julie Kirkham, Astrid Schepman, Jordana Lambert & Anastasia Locke - 2016 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 10.
  26.  39
    Shared intentions without a self.Michael Lewis - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (5):707-708.
    Shared knowledge of intentionality as well as shared knowledge of anything depends on the organism's understanding of itself, others, and the possible relations between self and other. This understanding involves mental representations of me, which emerges in the second half of the second year in the human infant, and it is this ability that gives rise to humanlike social understanding and complex self-conscious emotions.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  8
    Sensitising concept, themata and shareness: A dialogical perspective of social representations. Liliu - 2004 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 34 (3):249–264.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Mental lexicon and machine lexicon: Which properties are shared by machine and mental word representations? Which are not.Jean-Francois le Ny - 1995 - In Patrick Saint-Dizier & Evelyn Viegas (eds.), Computational lexical semantics. New York: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  12
    Understanding, Representation, Information.Frank Jackson - 2010 - In Language, Names and Information. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 30–60.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Some stage setting on the value of understanding words and plans Agreement and shared understandings Davidson's challenge to representation Are we confusing semantics and pragmatics? Why we need possible worlds Voyages through logical space How to finesse the issue in analytic ontology The need for centered worlds Getting information from sentences with centered content Saying things a new now that centering is in the story Where to now?
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  30.  76
    Neural Representations Beyond “Plus X”.Alessio Plebe & Vivian M. De La Cruz - 2018 - Minds and Machines 28 (1):93-117.
    In this paper we defend structural representations, more specifically neural structural representation. We are not alone in this, many are currently engaged in this endeavor. The direction we take, however, diverges from the main road, a road paved by the mathematical theory of measure that, in the 1970s, established homomorphism as the way to map empirical domains of things in the world to the codomain of numbers. By adopting the mind as codomain, this mapping became a boon for all (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  31. Getting Serious about Shared Features.Donal Khosrowi - 2020 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 71 (2):523-546.
    In Simulation and Similarity, Michael Weisberg offers a similarity-based account of the model–world relation, which is the relation in virtue of which successful models are successful. Weisberg’s main idea is that models are similar to targets in virtue of sharing features. An important concern about Weisberg’s account is that it remains silent on what it means for models and targets to share features, and consequently on how feature-sharing contributes to models’ epistemic success. I consider three potential ways of concretizing the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  32. Knowledge representation, the World Wide Web, and the evolution of logic.Christopher Menzel - 2011 - Synthese 182 (2):269-295.
    It is almost universally acknowledged that first-order logic (FOL), with its clean, well-understood syntax and semantics, allows for the clear expression of philosophical arguments and ideas. Indeed, an argument or philosophical theory rendered in FOL is perhaps the cleanest example there is of “representing philosophy”. A number of prominent syntactic and semantic properties of FOL reflect metaphysical presuppositions that stem from its Fregean origins, particularly the idea of an inviolable divide between concept and object. These presuppositions, taken at face value, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  26
    Shared models: The cognitive equivalent of aLingua Franca.Robert W. Lawler - 1989 - AI and Society 3 (1):3-27.
    The richness of humanity is the diversity of its cultures, but now as never before the destructive power of modern technology and threatening ecological disasters make it necessary that we all recognize we are many peoples of one world. Complementing the diversity of our different cultures, the growth of a common, scientific knowledge inspires the hope that we may achieve and share a secondary culture of ideas. Computers, which can help represent explicitly the best ideas of modern science, can aid (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  35
    The Shared Cognitive Intent of Science and Theatre.Eli Rozik - 2012 - The European Legacy 17 (5):659 - 673.
    Science and theatre are generally thought to share no common cognitive ground for the simple reason that the former appeals to the intellect, whereas the latter appeals to the emotions. Contrary to this view, I claim that like scientific texts, theatrical texts evince a cognitive intent and that, despite obvious differences, both types show similarities on three cognitive levels: (a) the use of equivalent systems of representation and communication; (b) the operation of a mode of thinking; and (c) the embodiment (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  31
    Editorial: What's Shared in Sharing Tasks and Actions? Processes and Representations Underlying Joint Performance.Motonori Yamaguchi, Timothy N. Welsh, Karl Christoph Klauer & Kerstin Dittrich - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Understanding and sharing intentions: The origins of cultural cognition.Michael Tomasello, Malinda Carpenter, Josep Call, Tanya Behne & Henrike Moll - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (5):675-691.
    We propose that the crucial difference between human cognition and that of other species is the ability to participate with others in collaborative activities with shared goals and intentions: shared intentionality. Participation in such activities requires not only especially powerful forms of intention reading and cultural learning, but also a unique motivation to share psychological states with others and unique forms of cognitive representation for doing so. The result of participating in these activities is species-unique forms of cultural (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   557 citations  
  37.  14
    Equal Representation Does Not Mean Equal Opportunity: Women Academics Perceive a Thicker Glass Ceiling in Social and Behavioral Fields Than in the Natural Sciences and Economics.Ruth van Veelen & Belle Derks - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    In the study of women in academia, the focus is often particularly on women’s stark underrepresentation in the math-intensive fields of natural sciences, technology, and economics. In the non-math-intensive of fields life, social and behavioral sciences, gender issues are seemingly less at stake because, on average, women are well-represented. However, in the current study, we demonstrate that equal gender representation in LSB disciplines does not guarantee women’s equal opportunity to advance to full professorship—to the contrary. With a cross-sectional survey among (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Representation, Knowledge, and Structure in Computational Explanations in Cognitive Science.Charles Wallis - 1995 - Dissertation, University of Minnesota
    Most of this work is concerned with two theories that underlie cognitive science; theories which I call "the representational theory of intentionality" and "the computational theory of cognition" . While the representational theory of intentionality asserts that mental states are about the world in virtue of a representation relation between the world and the state, the computational theory of cognition asserts that humans and others perform cognitive tasks by computing functions on these representations. CTC draws upon a rich analogy (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  28
    Patient Representation and Advocacy for Alzheimer Disease in Germany and Israel.Silke Schicktanz, Nitzan Rimon-Zarfaty, Aviad Raz & Karin Jongsma - 2018 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 15 (3):369-380.
    This paper analyses self-declared aims and representation of dementia patient organizations and advocacy groups in relation to two recent upheavals: the critique of social stigmatization and biomedical research focusing on prediction. Based on twenty-six semi-structured interviews conducted in 2016–2017 with members, service recipients, and board representatives of POs in Germany and Israel, a comparative analysis was conducted, based on a grounded theory approach, to detect emerging topics within and across the POs and across national contexts. We identified a heterogeneous landscape, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  23
    Representation, Interaction, and Intersubjectivity.Richard Alterman - 2007 - Cognitive Science 31 (5):815-841.
    What the participants share, their common “sense” of the world, creates a foundation, a framing, an orientation that enables human actors to see and act in coordination with one another. For recurrent activities, the methods the participants use to understand each other as they act change, making the intersubjective space in which actors operate richer and easier to produce. This article works through some of the issues that emerge from a close examination of intersubjectivity as it is managed through representation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  31
    Representations of China by Western Travellers in the Blogsphere.Stefano Calzati - 2016 - Cultura 13 (2):153-172.
    This article adopts a transmedial perspective in order to investigate narrative similarities and differences between print and online travel writing. Texts, which are contemporary and Western-authored, are written either in English, French and Italian and they all focus on China as the travel destination. Drawing upon Gérard Genette and Mieke Bal's studies on the narrative discourse, it is contended that travel books and travel blogs, despite sharing basic generic features, present substantial differences. In the former, readers are presented with a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  48
    Representations and Reproductive Hazards of Agent Orange.Leslie J. Reagan - 2011 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 39 (1):54-61.
    United States Air Force planes fly across mountains of green forest; behind them, fine white streams of chemical spray fill the sky. The planes fly alone or in formation covering wide swaths of the entire landscape. These images of the herbicide spraying during the United States-Vietnam War are ubiquitous in media material about Agent Orange, the most heavily used of the fifteen herbicides sprayed during the war. This representation of the war does not include guns, grenades, tanks, bombs, or dead (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  22
    Pretensive Shared Reality: From Childhood Pretense to Adult Imaginative Play.Rohan Kapitany, Tomas Hampejs & Thalia R. Goldstein - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13:774085.
    Imaginative pretend play is often thought of as the domain of young children, yet adults regularly engage in elaborated, fantastical, social-mediated pretend play. We describe imaginative play in adults via the term “pretensive shared reality;” Shared Pretensive Reality describes the ability of a group of individuals to employ a range of higher-order cognitive functions to explicitly and implicitly share representations of a bounded fictional reality in predictable and coherent ways, such that this constructed reality may be explored (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  25
    Introspecting Representations.Susanna Radovic - 2005 - Dissertation, Gothenburg University
    During the last couple of decades, so called representationalist theories of mind have gained increased popularity. These theories describe mental states in terms of representations of external objects and states of affairs. It is also often held that the content of a subject’s thoughts and perceptions is determined by facts outside her mind, such as social relations between her and other people and causal relations between her and external objects. Some representationalists even argue that the phenomenal character of perceptual (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  22
    Shared Attention as a Revelatory Practice.Antony Fredriksson - 2024 - Topoi 43 (2):349-359.
    In order to understand what we are talking about when we talk about joint attention, I will scrutinize how the mainstream view that builds on representational and intentionalist theories of mind is constituted. My aim is to show that much of the theory of joint attention is quite narrowly constructed and comes with tacit disciplinary biases that exclude much of what is existentially important in our practices of sharing our perceptions and guiding others to attend to the world in novel (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  77
    Shared circuits in language and communication.Simon Garrod & Martin J. Pickering - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (1):26-27.
    The target article says surprisingly little about the possible role of shared circuits in language and communication. This commentary considers how they might contribute to linguistic communication, particularly during dialogue. We argue that shared circuits are used to promote alignment between linguistic representations at many levels and to support production-based emulation of linguistic input during comprehension.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  24
    What Do Group Members Share? The Privileged Status of Cultural Knowledge for Children.Gaye Soley - 2019 - Cognitive Science 43 (10):e12786.
    An essential aspect of forming representations of social groups is to recognize socially relevant attributes licensed by the group membership. Because knowledge of cultural practices tends to be transmitted through social contact within social groups, it is one of the fundamental attributes shared among members of a social group. Two experiments explored whether 5‐ and 6‐year‐olds selectively attribute shared cultural knowledge on the basis of group membership of agents. Using novel social groups, children were introduced to one (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  67
    Scientific representation and perspective.Ioannis Votsis - unknown
    Consider the aims of the following three influential philosophical views. The semantic view of theories aims to supply the proper form and content of scientific theories. Structural realism aspires to delimit the epistemology and ontology of science. Mathematical structuralism seeks to reveal the epistemological and ontological nature of – you guessed it – mathematical objects. Given their divergent aims they may seem like unlikely bedfellows, but the semantic view of theories, structural realism and mathematical structuralism share enough ground to be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Making our ends meet: shared intention, goal adoption and the third-person perspective.Luca Tummolini - 2014 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13 (1):75-98.
    Mind reading (i.e. the ability to infer the mental state of another agent) is taken to be the main cognitive ability required to share an intention and to collaborate. In this paper, I argue that another cognitive ability is also necessary to collaborate: representing others’ and ones’ own goals from a third-person perspective (other-centred or allocentric representation of goals). I argue that allocentric mind reading enables the cognitive ability of goal adoption, i.e. having the goal that another agent’s achieve p (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50. Medieval Representations of Change and Their Early Modern Application.Matthias Schemmel - 2014 - Foundations of Science 19 (1):11-34.
    The article investigates the role of symbolic means of knowledge representation in concept development using the historical example of medieval diagrams of change employed in early modern work on the motion of fall. The parallel cases of Galileo Galilei, Thomas Harriot, and René Descartes and Isaac Beeckman are discussed. It is argued that the similarities concerning the achievements as well as the shortcomings of their respective work on the motion of fall can to a large extent be attributed to their (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 977