Results for 'Enoch Tompte-Tom'

952 found
Order:
  1.  7
    Vérité philosophique et vérité théologique.Enoch Tompte-Tom - 2016 - Paris: L'Harmattan.
    Chaque jour, l'homme est en bute à la notion de vérité. La question flagrante "qu'est-ce que la vérité?" ne se pose pas seulement dans le cadre de la connaissance philosophique, mais également par le biais des sentiments d'ambiguïté et d'angoisse que l'être humain éprouve durant son existence terrestre. Cette recherche a été faite d'abord sous l'angle de l'émergence de la vérité dans la pensée philosophique, ensuite dans le cadre théologique. Enfin, un autre volet a été pris en compte, celui de (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. The epistemological challenge to metanormative realism: how best to understand it, and how to cope with it.David Enoch - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 148 (3):413-438.
    Metaethical—or, more generally, metanormative— realism faces a serious epistemological challenge. Realists owe us—very roughly speaking—an account of how it is that we can have epistemic access to the normative truths about which they are realists. This much is, it seems, uncontroversial among metaethicists, myself included. But this is as far as the agreement goes, for it is not clear—nor uncontroversial—how best to understand the challenge, what the best realist way of coping with it is, and how successful this attempt is. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  3. Not Just a Truthometer: Taking Oneself Seriously (but not Too Seriously) in Cases of Peer Disagreement.David Enoch - 2010 - Mind 119 (476):953-997.
    How should you update your (degrees of) belief about a proposition when you find out that someone else — as reliable as you are in these matters — disagrees with you about its truth value? There are now several different answers to this question — the question of `peer disagreement' — in the literature, but none, I think, is plausible. Even more importantly, none of the answers in the literature places the peer-disagreement debate in its natural place among the most (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  4. A Defense of Moral Deference.David Enoch - 2014 - Journal of Philosophy 111 (5):229-258.
    The combination of this vindication of moral deference and diagnosis of its fishiness nicely accommodates, I argue, some related phenomena, like the (neglected) fact that our uneasiness with moral deference is actually a particular instance of uneasiness with opaque evidence in general when it comes to morality, and the (familiar) fact that the scope of this uneasiness is wider than the moral as it includes other normative domains.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  5. False Consciousness for Liberals, Part I: Consent, Autonomy, and Adaptive Preferences.David Enoch - 2020 - Philosophical Review 129 (2):159-210.
    The starting point regarding consent has to be that it is both extremely important, and that it is often suspicious. In this article, the author tries to make sense of both of these claims, from a largely liberal perspective, tying consent, predictably, to the value of autonomy and distinguishing between autonomy as sovereignty and autonomy as nonalienation. The author then discusses adaptive preferences, claiming that they suffer from a rationality flaw but that it's not clear that this flaw matters morally (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  6. How Principles Ground.David Enoch - 2019 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 14:1-22.
    Specific moral facts seem to be grounded in relevant natural facts, together with relevant moral principles. This picture—according to which moral principles play a role in grounding specific moral facts—is a very natural one, and it may be especially attractive to non-naturalist, robust realists. A recent challenge from Selim Berker threatens this picture, though. Moral principles themselves seem to incorporate grounding claims, and it’s not clear that this can be reconciled with according the principles a grounding role. This chapter responds (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  7. Hypothetical Consent and the Value (s) of Autonomy.David Enoch - 2017 - Ethics 128 (1):6-36.
    Hypothetical consent is puzzling. On the one hand, it seems to make a moral difference across a wide range of cases. On the other hand, there seem to be principled reasons to think that it cannot. In this article I put forward reasonably precise formulations of these general suspicions regarding hypothetical consent; I draw several distinctions regarding the ways in which hypothetical consent may make a moral difference; I distinguish between two autonomy-related concerns, nonalienation and sovereignty; and, utilizing these distinctions, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  8. Statistical resentment, or: what’s wrong with acting, blaming, and believing on the basis of statistics alone.David Enoch & Levi Spectre - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):5687-5718.
    Statistical evidence—say, that 95% of your co-workers badmouth each other—can never render resenting your colleague appropriate, in the way that other evidence (say, the testimony of a reliable friend) can. The problem of statistical resentment is to explain why. We put the problem of statistical resentment in several wider contexts: The context of the problem of statistical evidence in legal theory; the epistemological context—with problems like the lottery paradox for knowledge, epistemic impurism and doxastic wrongdoing; and the context of a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  9. Autonomy as Non‐alienation, Autonomy as Sovereignty, and Politics.David Enoch - 2021 - Journal of Political Philosophy 30 (2):143-165.
    Journal of Political Philosophy, Volume 30, Issue 2, Page 143-165, June 2022.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  10. Authority and Reason‐Giving.David Enoch - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (2):296-332.
  11. The case against moral luck.David Enoch & Andrei Marmor - 2007 - Law and Philosophy 26 (4):405-436.
  12. The Disorder of Public Reason.David Enoch - 2013 - Ethics 124 (1):141-176.
  13. II—What’s Wrong with Paternalism: Autonomy, Belief, and Action.David Enoch - 2016 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 116 (1):21-48.
    Several influential characterizations of paternalism or its distinctive wrongness emphasize a belief or judgement that it typically involves—namely, 10 the judgement that the paternalized is likely to act irrationally, or some such. But it's not clear what about such a belief can be morally objectionable if it has the right epistemic credentials (if it is true, say, and is best supported by the evidence). In this paper, I elaborate on this point, placing it in the context of the relevant epistemological (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  14. Why idealize?David Enoch - 2005 - Ethics 115 (4):759-787.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  15. Does legal epistemology rest on a mistake? On fetishism, two‐tier system design, and conscientious fact‐finding.David Enoch, Talia Fisher & Levi Spectre - 2021 - Philosophical Issues 31 (1):85-103.
  16. Sensitivity, safety, and the law: A reply to Pardo.David Enoch & Levi Spectre - 2019 - Legal Theory 25 (3):178-199.
    ABSTRACTIn a recent paper, Michael Pardo argues that the epistemic property that is legally relevant is the one called Safety, rather than Sensitivity. In the process, he argues against our Sensitivity-related account of statistical evidence. Here we revisit these issues, partly in order to respond to Pardo, and partly in order to make general claims about legal epistemology. We clarify our account, we show how it adequately deals with counterexamples and other worries, we raise suspicions about Safety's value here, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  17. Can there be a global, interesting, coherent constructivism about practical reason?David Enoch - 2009 - Philosophical Explorations 12 (3):319-339.
    More and more people seem to think that constructivism - in political philosophy, in moral philosophy, and perhaps in practical reasoning most generally - is the way to go. And yet it is surprisingly hard to even characterize the view. In this paper, I go to some lengths trying to capture the essence of a constructivist position - mostly in the realm of practical reason - and to pinpoint its theoretical attractions. I then give some reason to suspect that there (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  18.  2
    Nietzsche et "la grande erreur fondamentale de Schopenhauer".Tom Bildstein - 2024 - Voluntas: Revista Internacional de Filosofia 15 (1):e87684.
    Le Fragment 47[5] constitue un point aveugle dans la recherche sur Nietzsche. Ce texte est pourtant capital pour saisir le fond de la critique de la philosophie schopenhauerienne, dans la mesure où Nietzsche y dévoile ce qu’il nomme la «grande erreur fondamentale de Schopenhauer» qui, selon lui, réside dans une fausse compréhension du rapport entre la «volonté» et la «connaissance». La comparaison de ce fragment avec d’autres permet d’une part de souligner que Nietzsche est en désaccord non seulement avec les (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Hume and the polics of money.Tom Hopkins - 2024 - In Max Skjönsberg & Felix Waldmann (eds.), Hume's Essays: A Critical Guide. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  20. Thanks, We’re good: why moral realism is not morally objectionable.David Enoch - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (5):1689-1699.
    This paper responds to a recently popular objection to non-naturalist, robust moral realism. The objection is that moral realism is morally objectionable, because realists are committed to taking evidence about the distribution of non-natural properties to be relevant to their first-order moral commitments. I argue that such objections fail. The moral realist is indeed committed to conditionals such as “If there are no non-natural properties, then no action is wrong.” But the realist is not committed to using this conditional in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  21. What do you mean “This isn’t the question”?David Enoch & Tristram McPherson - 2017 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 47 (6):820-840.
    This is a contribution to the symposium on Tim Scanlon’s Being Realistic about Reasons. We have two aims here: First, we ask for more details about Scanlon’s meta-metaphysical view, showing problems with salient clarifications. And second, we raise independent objections to the view – to its explanatory productivity, its distinctness, and the argumentative support it enjoys.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  22.  9
    Wat is ‘publieke verantwoording’?Tom Willems & Wouter Van Dooren - 2013 - Res Publica 55 (3):407-409.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  45
    Editors' Overview Perspectives on Teaching Social Responsibility to Students in Science and Engineering.Henk Zandvoort, Tom Børsen, Michael Deneke & Stephanie J. Bird - 2013 - Science and Engineering Ethics 19 (4):1413-1438.
    Global society is facing formidable current and future problems that threaten the prospects for justice and peace, sustainability, and the well-being of humanity both now and in the future. Many of these problems are related to science and technology and to how they function in the world. If the social responsibility of scientists and engineers implies a duty to safeguard or promote a peaceful, just and sustainable world society, then science and engineering education should empower students to fulfil this responsibility. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  24.  96
    Politics and suffering.David Enoch - forthcoming - Analytic Philosophy.
    Political philosophy should focus not on uplifting ideals, but rather, so I argue, on minimizing serious suffering. This is so not because other things do not ultimately matter (they do), but rather because in the political context, the stakes in terms of suffering are usually extremely high, so that any other considerations are almost always outweighed. Put in moderately deontological terms: the high stakes carry most political decisions across the thresholds of the relevant deontological constraints. While the argument is substantive (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  92
    Disability and difference: balancing social and physical constructions.Tom Koch - 2001 - Journal of Medical Ethics 27 (6):370-376.
    The world of disability theory is currently divided between those who insist it reflects a physical fact affecting life quality and those who believe disability is defined by social prejudice. Despite a dialogue spanning bioethical, medical and social scientific literatures the differences between opposing views remains persistent. The result is similar to a figure-ground paradox in which one can see only part of a picture at any moment. This paper attempts to find areas of commonality between the opposing camps, and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  26.  83
    A right to violate one's duty.David Enoch - 2002 - Law and Philosophy 21 (s 4-5):355-384.
  27. Cognitive Biases and Moral Luck.David Enoch - 2010 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (3):372-386.
    Some of the recent philosophical literature on moral luck attempts to make headway in the moral-luck debate by employing the resources of empirical psychology, in effect arguing that some of the intuitive judgments relevant to the moral-luck debate are best explained - and so presumably explained away - as the output of well-documented cognitive biases. We argue that such attempts are empirically problematic, and furthermore that even if they were not, it is still not at all clear what philosophical significance (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  28.  3
    Menswear: Vintage People on Photo Postcards.Tom Phillips - 2012 - Bodleian Library, University of Oxford.
    This series celebrates the Bodleian Library's acquisition of Tom Phillips's archive of over 50,000 photographic postcards dating from the first half of the twentieth century, a period in which, thanks to the ever cheaper medium of photography, 'ordinary' people could afford to own their portraits. Each title in this series is thematically assembled and designed by the artist, the covers featuring a linked painting specially created for each title from Tom Phillips's signature work, A Humument.With an illuminating foreword by Eric (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  89
    Playing the Hand You're Dealt: How Moral Luck Is Different from Morally Significant Plain Luck.David Enoch - 2019 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 43 (1):257-270.
    What you ought to do is sensitive to circumstances that are not under your control, or to luck. So plain luck is often morally significant. Still, some of us think that there's no moral luck - that praiseworthiness and blameworthiness are not sensitive to luck. What explains this asymmetry between the luck-sensitivity of ought-judgments and the luck-insensitivity of blameworthiness and praiseworthiness judgments? I suggest an explanation, relying on the analogy to rational luck. I argue that some rational assessments - like (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  66
    The Canadian Question: What's So Great About Intelligence?Tom Koch - 1996 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 5 (2):307.
    A personable teenager with Down's syndrome became a Canadian cause célèbre a few months ago when University Hospital in Edmonton, Alberta, denied him a position on the organ transplantation waiting list. Terry Urquart lacked “reasonable” intelligence, hospital officials said, a criterion for all transplant candidates at that hospital. Protests by the boy's family, and by groups active in the cause of those with developmental disabilities, became well-photographed stories on the nightly television news and in the nation's newspapers. It did not (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  60
    Reason, Irrationality and Akrasia (Weakness of the Will) in Buddhism: Reflections upon Śāntideva’s Arguments with Himself.Tom J. F. Tillemans - 2008 - Argumentation 22 (1):149-163.
    Let it be granted that Buddhism has, e.g., in its logical literature, detailed canons and explicit rules of right reason that, amongst other things, ban inconsistency as irrational. This is the normative dimension of how people should think according to many major Buddhist authors. But do important Buddhist writers ever recognize any interesting or substantive role for inconsistency and forms of irrationality in their account of how people actually do think and act? The article takes as its point of departure (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32. Wouldn’t It Be Nice If P, Therefore, P.David Enoch - 2009 - Utilitas 21 (2):222-224.
    Suppose that a world in which we have an utterly non-consequentialist moral status is a better world than one in which we don’t have such a status. Does this give any reason to believe that we have such moral status? Suppose that a world without moral luck is worse than a world with moral luck. Does this give any reason to believe that there is moral luck? The problem is that positive answers to these questions1 seem to commit us to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  33.  59
    In defense of procedural rights : A response to Wellman.David Enoch - 2018 - Legal Theory 24 (1):40-49.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  34.  13
    Young, Gay, and Suicidal: Dynamic Nominalism and the Process of Defining a Social Problem with Statistics.Tom Waidzunas - 2012 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 37 (2):199-225.
    Since 1989, widely circulating statistics on gay teen suicide in the United States have acted as catalysts for institutional reforms, scientific research, and the creation of an identity category “gay youth.” While one figure has been replicated scientifically, these numbers originated not from a scientific research study but as risk estimates developed by a social worker and published in a government document. Many people within the public took up these original numbers, attributing their author the status of scientific researcher. In (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  5
    The bankers and the "nameless virtue".Tom Sorell - 2019 - In Christopher Cowton & James Dempsey (eds.), Business Ethics After the Global Financial Crisis: Lessons From the Crash. New York: Routledge.
    Bankers have been slow to claim responsibility or apologise for the seismic damage of the 2008 financial crisis. How is this shortcoming to be spelled out? One possibility is by saying that the bankers failed to display what Susan Wolff calls "the nameless virtue" --the disposition to take responsibility for untoward events that occur in one's area of influence, even if we did not intend them or directly cause them. I think this diagnosis is unduly generous to leaders of banks (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  18
    Commentary: Defending the indigent in capital cases.Tom Wicker - 1983 - Criminal Justice Ethics 2 (1):2-66.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Natural illumination, shadows and primate colour vision.Tom Troscianko, C. Alejandro Parraga, P. George Lovell, D. J. Tolhurst, R. J. Baddeley & U. Leonards - 1996 - In Enrique Villanueva (ed.), Perception. Ridgeview Pub. Co.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  13
    De invloed van interne partijfactoren op partijvernieuwing : een verkennende analyse.Tom Verstraete - 2003 - Res Publica 45 (1):173-200.
    A comparative study of the literature on party changes shows that there are many different views on why and how parties change. The existing literature is rather theoretical. Most authors have based their model on a survey of a limited number of parties. The only general conclusion one can draw is that both external and internal factors can provoke party changes. In this contribution, we concentrate on the role of the internal factors. We find that change is less likely to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  38
    Comment on 'doxastic incontinence'.Tom Vinci - 1985 - Mind 94 (373):116-119.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  54
    Intending, foreseeing, and the state.David Enoch - 2007 - Legal Theory 13 (2):69-99.
    For many years, moral philosophers have been debating the conceptual and moral status of the distinction between intending harm and foreseeing harm. In this paper, after surveying some of the objections to the moral significance of this distinction in general, I focus on the special case of state action, arguing that whatever reasons we have to be suspicious about the distinction's moral significance in general, we have very good reasons to believe it lacks intrinsic moral significance when applied to state (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  41.  52
    Luck Between Morality, Law, and Justice.David Enoch - 2008 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 9 (1):23-59.
    In this Article, I elaborate on and defend the following argument: There is no moral luck. If there is no moral luck, there should be no legal luck. Therefore, there should be no legal luck and ). If there is no normatively significant difference between the law doing and allowing, or intending and foreseeing, then there is no normatively significant difference between legal luck and just plain luck that has legal implications. There is no normatively significant difference between the law (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  42. Once You Start Using Slippery Slope Arguments, You 're on a Very Slippery Slope'.David Enoch - 2001 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 21 (4):629-647.
    Slippery slope arguments (SSAs) are, so I argue, arguments from consequences which have the following peculiar characteristic: They take advantage of our being less than perfect in making—and acting according to—distinctions. But then, once SSAs are seen for what they are, they can be turned against themselves. Being less than perfect at making the second‐order distinction between distinctions we're good at abiding by and those we're bad at abiding by, we're bound to fail to make the distinction between good and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  43.  29
    When the political becomes personal: Reflecting on disability bioethics.Tom Shakespeare - 2019 - Bioethics 33 (8):914-921.
    A discussion of the connection between activism and academia in bioethics, highlighting the author’s own trajectory, exploring the extent to which academics have an obliation to be ‘judges’ rather than ‘barristers’ (as explored by Jonathan Haidt) and asking questions about the relationship of disability to positions in bioethics.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44. How Noncognitivists Can Avoid Wishful Thinking.David Enoch - 2003 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (4):527-545.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  45. On Mark Schroeder's Hypotheticalism: A Critical Notice of Slaves of the Passions.David Enoch - 2011 - Philosophical Review 120 (3):423-446.
    In Slaves of the Passions Mark Schroeder puts forward Hypotheticalism, his version of a Humean theory of normative reasons that is capable, so he argues, to avoid many of the difficulties Humeanism is traditionally vulnerable to. In this critical notice, I first outline the main argument of the book, and then proceed to highlight some difficulties and challenges. I argue that these challenges show that Schroeder's improvements on traditional Humeanism – while they do succeed in making the view more immune (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  46. Just because it’s a phobia doesn’t mean you shouldn’t be afraid.David Enoch - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (7):2425-2437.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  47
    The conservative use of the brain-death criterion – a critique.Tom Tomlinson - 1984 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 9 (4):377-394.
    The whole brain-death criterion of death now enjoys a wide acceptance both within the medical profession and among the general public. That acceptance is in large part the product of the contention that brain death is the proper criterion for even a conservative definition of death – the irreversible loss of the integrated functioning of the organism as a whole. This claim – most recently made in the report of the Presidential Commission and in a comprehensive article by James Bernat (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  35
    What Happened to the Third and Fourth Lemmas in Tibet?Tom J. F. Tillemans - 2015 - Journal of Buddhist Philosophy 1:24-38.
    The paper looks at how Tsong kha pa, mKhas grub, and Go rams pa understood the third and fourth lemmas in the tetralemma, “both A and B” and “neither A nor B,” respectively.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  30
    Plural Approaches to Theorizing Justice and Legitimacy in Europe.Tom Theuns & Miklós Zala - 2022 - Res Publica 28 (4):585-592.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  18
    Edward Said and the Margins.Tom Thomas - 2012 - Text Matters - a Journal of Literature, Theory and Culture 2 (2):155-168.
    Edward Said was the quintessential intellectual of the last quarter of the twentieth century. Commonly celebrated as the founding figure of postcolonialism, his critical oeuvre spans varied terrain. The very strength of his critique lies in these diverse tributaries of thought. Crossing borders and boundaries incessantly, Said’s intellectual project celebrates the culture of resistance while opposing doctrinaire rhetoric. The paper tries to journey along the multifarious “margins” of discourses that crop up in Said. “In-between” spaces have to be investigated for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 952