Results for 'Kirsten Gilbert'

964 found
Order:
  1.  28
    Styles of Leadership, Fears of Compassion, and Competing to Avoid Inferiority.Jaskaran Basran, Claudia Pires, Marcela Matos, Kirsten McEwan & Paul Gilbert - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
  2.  50
    Beliefs about the automaticity of positive mood regulation: examination of the BAMR-Positive Emotion Downregulation Scale in relation to emotion regulation strategies and mood symptoms.Alyson L. Dodd, Kirsten Gilbert & June Gruber - 2020 - Cognition and Emotion 34 (2):384-392.
    ABSTRACTEmotion regulation is a topic of great interest due to its relevance to navigating everyday life, as well as its relevance to psychopathology. Recent research indicates that beliefs about t...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error.Gilbert Harman - 1999 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1999):315-331.
    Ordinary moral thought often commits what social psychologists call 'the fundamental attribution error '. This is the error of ignoring situational factors and overconfidently assuming that distinctive behaviour or patterns of behaviour are due to an agent's distinctive character traits. In fact, there is no evidence that people have character traits in the relevant sense. Since attribution of character traits leads to much evil, we should try to educate ourselves and others to stop doing it.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   345 citations  
  4. Knowing How and Knowing That: The Presidential Address.Gilbert Ryle - 1946 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 46:1 - 16.
  5. Modelling collective belief.Margaret Gilbert - 1987 - Synthese 73 (1):185-204.
    What is it for a group to believe something? A summative account assumes that for a group to believe that p most members of the group must believe that p. Accounts of this type are commonly proposed in interpretation of everyday ascriptions of beliefs to groups. I argue that a nonsummative account corresponds better to our unexamined understanding of such ascriptions. In particular I propose what I refer to as the joint acceptance model of group belief. I argue that group (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   263 citations  
  6. Agreements, coercion, and obligation.Margaret Gilbert - 1993 - Ethics 103 (4):679-706.
    Typical agreements can be seen as joint decisions, inherently involving obligations of a distinctive kind. These obligations derive from the joint commitment' that underlies a joint decision. One consequence of this understanding of agreements and their obligations is that coerced agreements are possible and impose obligations. It is not that the parties to an agreement should always conform to it, all things considered. Unless one is released from the agreement, however, one has some reason to conform to it, whatever else (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  7. Logic and reasoning.Gilbert Harman - 1984 - Synthese 60 (1):107-127.
  8. Collective guilt and collective guilt feelings.Margaret Gilbert - 2002 - The Journal of Ethics 6 (2):115-143.
    Among other things, this paper considers what so-called collective guilt feelings amount to. If collective guilt feelings are sometimes appropriate, it must be the case that collectives can indeed be guilty. The paper begins with an account of what it is for a collective to intend to do something and to act in light of that intention. An account of collective guilt in terms of membership guilt feelings is found wanting. Finally, a "plural subject" account of collective guilt feelings is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  9. Skepticism about Character Traits.Gilbert Harman - 2009 - The Journal of Ethics 13 (2-3):235 - 242.
    The first part of this article discusses recent skepticism about character traits. The second describes various forms of virtue ethics as reactions to such skepticism. The philosopher J.-P. Sartre argued in the 1940s that character traits are pretenses, a view that the sociologist E. Goffman elaborated in the 1950s. Since then social psychologists have shown that attributions of character traits tend to be inaccurate through the ignoring of situational factors. (Personality psychology has tended to concentrate on people's conceptions of personality (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  10.  88
    Ethics and the Community of Inquiry: Education for deliberative democracy.Gilbert Burgh, Terri Field & Mark Freakley - 2006 - South Melbourne: Cengage/Thomson.
    Ethics and the Community of Inquiry gets to the heart of democratic education and how best to achieve it. The book radically reshapes our understanding of education by offering a framework from which to integrate curriculum, teaching and learning and to place deliberative democracy at the centre of education reform. It makes a significant contribution to current debates on educational theory and practice, in particular to pedagogical and professional practice, and ethics education.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  11. Studying the chimpanzee's theory of mind.Gilbert Harman - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (4):576-577.
  12.  9
    (1 other version)Practical reasoning.Gilbert Harman - 1997 - In Alfred R. Mele, The philosophy of action. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 431--63.
  13.  88
    Reasoning and Explanatory Coherence.Gilbert Harman - 1980 - American Philosophical Quarterly 17 (2):151 - 157.
  14. Logical form.Gilbert Harman - 1972 - Foundations of Language 9 (1):38-65.
    Theories of adverbial modification can be roughly distinguished into two sorts. One kind of theory takes logical form to follow surface grammatical form. Adverbs are treated as unanalyzable logical operators that turn a predicate or sentence into a different predicate or sentence respectively. And new rules of logic are stated for these operators. -/- A different kind of theory does not suppose that logical form must parallel surface grammatical form. It allows that logical form may have more to do with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  15. Game Theory and “Convention‘.Margaret Gilbert - 1981 - Synthese 46 (1):41 - 93.
    A feature of David Lewis's account of conventions in his book "Convention" which has received admiring notices from philosophers is his use of the mathematical theory of games. In this paper I point out a number of serious flaws in Lewis's use of game theory. Lewis's basic claim is that conventions cover 'coordination problems'. I show that game-Theoretical analysis tends to establish that coordination problems in Lewis's sense need not underlie conventions.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  16. Agreements, conventions, and language.Margaret Gilbert - 1983 - Synthese 54 (3):375 - 407.
    The question whether and in what way languages and language use involve convention is addressed, With special reference to David Lewis's account of convention in general. Data are presented which show that Lewis has not captured the sense of 'convention' involved when we speak of adopting a linguistic convention. He has, In effect, attempted an account of social conventions. An alternative account of social convention and an account of linguistic convention are sketched.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  17. Multi-modal argumentation.Michael A. Gilbert - 1994 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 24 (2):159-177.
    The main stream of formal and informal logic as well as more recent work in discourse analysis provides a way of understanding certain arguments that particularly lend themselves to rational analysis. I argue, however, that these, and allied modes of analysis, be seen as heuristic models and not as the only proper mode of argument. This article introduces three other modes of argumen tation that emphasize distinct aspects of human communication, but that, at the same time, must be considered for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  18. Rationality and salience.Margaret Gilbert - 1989 - Philosophical Studies 57 (1):61-77.
    A number of authors, Including Thomas Schelling and David Lewis, have envisaged a model of the generation of action in coordination problems in which salience plays a crucial role. Empirical studies suggest that human subjects are likely to try for the salient combination of actions, a tendency leading to fortunate results. Does rationality dictate that one aim at the salient combination? Some have thought so, Thus proclaiming that salience is all that is needed to resolve coordination problems for agents who (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  19. Rationality, coordination, and convention.Margaret Gilbert - 1990 - Synthese 84 (1):1 - 21.
    Philosophers using game-theoretical models of human interactions have, I argue, often overestimated what sheer rationality can achieve. (References are made to David Gauthier, David Lewis, and others.) In particular I argue that in coordination problems rational agents will not necessarily reach a unique outcome that is most preferred by all, nor a unique 'coordination equilibrium' (Lewis), nor a unique Nash equilibrium. Nor are things helped by the addition of a successful precedent, or by common knowledge of generally accepted personal principles. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  20. (1 other version)Language, thought, and communication.Gilbert Harman - 1975 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7:270-298.
    Consider the idea that a natural language like English is in the first instance incorporated into the system of representation one thinks with. This ‘incorporation’ view is compared with a translation or ‘decoding’ view of communication. Compositional semantics makes sense only given the implausible decoding view.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  21. Moral Philosophy and Linguistics.Gilbert Harman - 1999 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 1:107-115.
    Any acceptable account of moral epistemology must accord with the following points. (1) Different people acquire seemingly very different moralities. (2) All normal people acquire a moral sense, whether or not they are given explicit moral instruction. Language resembles morality in these ways. There is considerable evidence from linguistics for linguistic universals. This suggests that (3) despite the first point, there are moral universals. If so, it might be possible to develop a moral epistemology that is analogous to the theory (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  22. Linguistic competence and empiricism.Gilbert Harman - 1969 - In Sidney Hook, Language and philosophy. [New York]: New York University Press.
  23. Group Membership and Political Obligation.Margaret Gilbert - 1993 - The Monist 76 (1):119-131.
    This is how A. John Simmons sets the scene for his discussion of political obligation in his book Moral Principles and Political Obligations, one of the best known contemporary philosophical treatments of the subject.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  24. Collective preferences, obligations, and rational choice.Margaret Gilbert - 2001 - Economics and Philosophy 17 (1):109-119.
    Can teams and other collectivities have preferences of their own, preferences that are not in some way reducible to the personal preferences of their members? In short, are collective preferences possible? In everyday life people speak easily of what we prefer, where what is at issue seems to be a collective preference. This is suggested by the acceptability of such remarks as ‘My ideal walk would be . . . along rougher and less well-marked paths than we prefer as a (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  25. Group wrongs and guilt feelings.Margaret Gilbert - 1997 - The Journal of Ethics 1 (1):65-84.
    Can it ever be appropriate to feel guilt just because one's group has acted badly? Some say no, citing supposed features of guilt feelings as such. If one understands group action according to my plural subject account of groups, however, one can argue for the appropriateness of feeling guilt just because one's group has acted badly - a feeling that often occurs. In so arguing I sketch a plural subject account of groups, group intentions and group actions: for a group (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  26. Symposium: Pleasure.Gilbert Ryle & W. B. Gallie - 1954 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 28 (1):135 - 164.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  27. Communities of Inquiry: Politics, power and group dynamics.Gilbert Burgh & Mor Yorshansky - 2011 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 43 (5):436-452.
    The notion of a community of inquiry has been treated by many of its proponents as being an exemplar of democracy in action. We argue that the assumptions underlying this view present some practical and theoretical difficulties, particularly in relation to distribution of power among the members of a community of inquiry. We identify two presuppositions in relation to distribution of power that require attention in developing an educational model that is committed to deliberative democracy: (1) openness to inquiry and (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  28. Three trends in moral and political philosophy.Gilbert Harman - 2003 - Journal of Value Inquiry 37 (3):415-425.
  29.  69
    Positive versus negative undermining in belief revision.Gilbert Harman - 1984 - Noûs 18 (1):39-49.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  30. Skepticism and foundations.Gilbert Harman - 2003 - In Luper Steven, The Skeptics: Contemporary Essays. Ashgate Press. pp. 1--11.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  31. Necessary Assumptions.Gilbert Plumer - 1999 - Informal Logic 19 (1):41-61.
    In their book EVALUATING CRITICAL THINKING Stephen Norris and Robert Ennis say: “Although it is tempting to think that certain [unstated] assumptions are logically necessary for an argument or position, they are not. So do not ask for them.” Numerous writers of introductory logic texts as well as various highly visible standardized tests (e.g., the LSAT and GRE) presume that the Norris/Ennis view is wrong; the presumption is that many arguments have (unstated) necessary assumptions and that readers and test takers (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  32. A Defense of Taking Some Novels As Arguments.Gilbert Plumer - 2015 - In B. J. Garssen, D. Godden, G. Mitchell & A. F. Snoeck Henkemans, Proceedings of the 8th International Conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation [CD-ROM]. Sic Sat. pp. 1169-1177.
    This paper’s main thesis is that in virtue of being believable, a believable novel makes an indirect transcendental argument telling us something about the real world of human psychology, action, and society. Three related objections are addressed. First, the Stroud-type objection would be that from believability, the only conclusion that could be licensed concerns how we must think or conceive of the real world. Second, Currie holds that such notions are probably false: the empirical evidence “is all against this idea…that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33. Taking Sides in Philosophy.Gilbert Ryle - 1937 - Philosophy 12 (47):317 - 332.
    There is a certain emotion of repugnance which I, and I hope a good many would-be philosophers, feel when asked the conventional question, “If you are a philosopher, to what school of thought do you belong? Are you an Idealist or a Realist, a Platonist or a Hobbist, a Monist or a Pluralist?”.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  34. Category mistakes in m&e.Gilbert Harman - 2003 - Philosophical Perspectives 17 (1):165–180.
    Theories of causation may imply that your birth causes your death, which seems odd in the way that it is not odd to say that your birth precedes your death. Theories of knowledge may imply that the object of knowledge is the same as the object of belief, although we know but do not believe facts and we can know a proposition without knowing whether it is true.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  35.  69
    Corporate strategy and ethics.Daniel R. Gilbert - 1986 - Journal of Business Ethics 5 (2):137 - 150.
    Corporate Strategy has emerged as a central metaphor for private-sector enterprise. Given inherent imperfections in markets, one important question to consider is how well the practice of Corporate Strategy contributes to social welfare. An account of the implicit morality of free markets is developed as a standard against which two particular, second best solutions to market imperfections — namely, American federal antitrust policy and Corporate Strategy — are compared. Corporate Strategy is subsequently evaluated in terms of the fundamental principles of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  36. Self-reflexive thoughts.Gilbert Harman - 2006 - Philosophical Issues 16 (1):334-345.
    Alice has insomnia. She has trouble falling asleep and part of the problem is that she worries about it and realizes that her worrying about it tends to keep from falling asleep. It occurs to her that thinking that she will not be able to fall asleep may be a kind of self-fulfilling prophecy. Perhaps she even has a thought that might be expressed like this: I am not going to fall asleep because of my having this very thought. This (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  37.  88
    How to build and use agent-based models in social science.Nigel Gilbert & Pietro Terna - 2000 - Mind and Society 1 (1):57-72.
    The use of computer simulation for building theoretical models in social science is introduced. It is proposed that agent-based models have potential as a “third way” of carrying out social science, in addition to argumentation and formalisation. With computer simulations, in contrast to other methods, it is possible to formalise complex theories about processes, carry out experiments and observe the occurrence of emergence. Some suggestions are offered about techniques for building agent-based models and for debugging them. A scheme for structuring (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  38.  23
    The Point of a Ban: Or, How to Think about Stem Cell Research.Meilaender Gilbert - 2012 - Hastings Center Report 31 (1):9-16.
    We might be convinced that the goal of relieving suffering offers a straightforward justification of sacrificing embryos in research. Or we might hold that although embryos merit our respect, the greater the good to be achieved by destroying them, the more respect must give way to research. Or, if we take the notion of respect seriously, we might find that relieving suffering is a real but not supreme imperative.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39. Bernardo rucellai and the orti oricellari: A study on the origin of modern political thought.Felix Gilbert - 1949 - Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 12 (1):101-131.
  40. The Anatomy of Science.Gilbert N. Lewis - 1928 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 35 (2):12-13.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  41.  60
    Primary Philosophy.Gilbert Harman - 1968 - Philosophical Review 77 (3):383.
  42.  86
    Symposium: Use, Usage and Meaning.Gilbert Ryle & J. N. Findlay - 1961 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 35:223 - 242.
  43.  35
    Quine on Meaning and Existence, II.Gilbert Harman - 1967 - Review of Metaphysics 21 (2):343-367.
    Quine takes philosophy to be continuous with science. Proper philosophical method is scientific method applied self-consciously to problems more general than those ordinarily considered within a particular science. Science is self-conscious common sense; and philosophy is self-conscious science. In order to understand and answer a basic philosophical question such as "What exists?" we must know something of the results of particular sciences like physics, chemistry, mathematics, biology, astronomy, and psychology. To learn what we can from these sciences is to do (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44.  32
    Reasons.Gilbert Harman - 1975 - Critica 7 (21):3-17.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45.  39
    The need to tackle concussion in Australian football codes.Frederic Gilbert & Bradley J. Partridge - 2012 - Medical Journal of Australia 196 (9):561-563.
    Postmortem evidence of chronic traumatic encephalopathy (CTE) in the brains of American National Football League players who suffered concussions while playing have intensified concerns about the risks of concussion in sport.1 Concussions are frequently sustained by amateur and professional players of Australia’s three most popular football codes (Australian football, rugby league, and rugby union) and, to a lesser extent, other contact sports such as soccer. This raises major concerns about possible long-term neurological damage, cognitive impairment and mental health problems in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  80
    Some philosophical issues in cognitive science.Gilbert Harman - 1989 - In Michael I. Posner, Foundations of Cognitive Science. MIT Press.
  47. 'The Internal Critique.Gilbert Harman - 2002 - In Dov M. Gabbay, Handbook of the logic of argument and inference: the turn towards the practical. New York: Elsevier. pp. 171--186.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48. Guilt-free morality.Gilbert Harman - 2009 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 4:203-14.
    Here are some of the ways in which some philosophers and psychologists have taken the emotion of guilt to be essential to morality. One relatively central idea is that guilt feelings are warranted if an agent knows that he or she has acted morally wrongly. It might be said that in such a case the agent has a strong reason to feel guilt, that the agent ought to have guilt feelings, that the agent is justified in having guilt feelings and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  67
    If and modus ponens.Gilbert Harman - 1979 - Theory and Decision 11 (1):41-53.
  50.  23
    Reason and Scepticism.Gilbert Harman - 1972 - Philosophical Review 81 (2):253.
1 — 50 / 964